Philosophical Investigations: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Larry_Sanger (talk)
Restoring old article
(No difference)

Revision as of 21:10, 19 September 2001

Philosophical Investigations, or PI, is one of Wittgenstein's two greatest works. The other is the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Considered by many to be one of the most important philosophical works of the 20th century, if not ever, the PI is unique in its hands-on approach to philosophy. Most philosophical texts read as histories of philosophy, summaries of philosophizing which has already occurred, a completed report on thought. Wittgenstein's PI treats philosophy as a lab science, instructing the reader to undergo various thought-experiments and do the actual work of philosophy. Rather than relying on the thinking of others, the PI insists that the reader do his own thinking. Wittgenstein asks the reader to imagine various worlds, and then to attempt to test the boundaries of that world, the advantages, the problems, etc. It is through these thought-experiments that the reader comes to philosophical conclusions by himself, rather than simply being told what philosophy has already discovered.


Wittgenstein seem to be convinced that many philosophical problems are the result of philosophers failing to properly understand the rules of language. For example a philosopher may ask "What is beauty?" and be convinced that there must be some essential thing which makes something beautiful. But for Wittgenstein, this is just a mistake in grammar. We don't need to understand the essence of beauty to use the word properly, and in fact the search for the essence of beauty creates grammatical confusion about how the word should be used. In the end this grammatical confusion leads philosophers to say strange things which nobody else understands. Instead of searching for a mythical substrate which defines beauty, Wittgenstein suggests that we take our cues from the actual use of the word. In particular Wittgenstein asks us to look at the way in which we teach children to use a word.


This leads to the common gloss of W's argument in the PI -- "Meaning just is use." In other words, we don't define words by reference to things, but by the way they are used. This means there is no need to postulate that there is something called beauty which exists independent of any particular "beautiful object." This may be an acurate description of one line of thought in the PI, but it is clearly a somewhat simplistic reading of the PI as a whole.


Certainly the above gloss is correct in that the PI deals largely with difficulties of language and meaning. But the fact that he relies so strongly on indirect arguments makes understanding his project difficult. One of the most influential sections of the PI deals directly with meaning and use. As is common in the Wittgenstein's later works, he begins by asking the reader to perform a thought experiment. First he asks the reader to come up with a definition of the word "game." While this may at first seem a simple task, he then goes on to lead us through the problems with each of the possible definitions of the word "game." Any definition which focuses on amusement leaves us unsatisfied since the feelings experienced by a world class chess player are very different than those of a circle of children playing duck duck goose. Any definition which focus on competition will fail to explain the game of catch, or the game of solitaire. And a definition of the word game which focus on rules will fall on similar difficulties. The essential point is not that it is impossible to define game, but that we don't have one, and we don't need one.


Everybody understands what we mean when we talk about playing a game, and we can even clearly identify and correct inaccurate uses of the word. All without reference to any definition of the word.


How exactly does this work? Why is it that we are sure about we can be sure that a particular activity -- Olympic target shooting -- is a game while a similar activity -- military sharp shooting -- clearly is not. Wittgenstein's explanation is tied up with a important analogy. How do we recognize that two people we know are related to one another? We may see similar height, weight, eye color, hair, nose, mouth, patterns of speech, social or political views, mannerisms, body structure, last names, etc. If we see enough matches we say we've noticed a /family resemblance, at the same time this is not a conscious process -- generally we don't catalog various similarities until we reach a certain threshold, we just intuitively see the resemblances. Wittgenstein suggests that the same may be true of language. Perhaps we are all familiar with enough things which are games, and enough things which are not games that we can instantly categorize new activities intuitively.


This brings us back to Wittgenstein's reliance on indirect communication, and his reliance on thought-experiments. If many philosophers are confused, it is because they aren't able to intuitively "see" the family resemblances, They've made mistakes in understanding the vague intuitive rules language uses, and have thereby tied themselves up in philosophical knots. To untangle these knots requires more than simple deductive arguments about problems with their particular position. In fact Wittgenstein says that kind of argument only serves to pull the knot tighter. Instead Wittgenstein try's to indirectly re-train their intuitive ability to understand the family resemblances that structure language.


/Talk