Jump to content

Metamath: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
No edit summary
Line 10: Line 10:
'''Metamath''' is a computer-assisted [[proof checker]].<ref name="whatismm">{{cite web | author=Megill, Norman | title=What is Metamath? | work=Metamath Home Page | url=http://us.metamath.org/#faq}}</ref> It has no specific logic embedded and can simply be regarded as a device to apply inference rules to formulas. Simplicity is the master concept in the design of Metamath: the language of Metamath, employed to state the definitions, axioms, inference rules and theorems is only composed of a handful of keywords and all the proofs are checked using one simple algorithm based on the substitution of variables (with optional provisos for what variables must remain distinct after a substitution is made)<ref name="howpswork">{{cite web | author=Megill,Norman | title=How Proofs Work | work=Metamath Proof Explorer Home Page | url=http://us.metamath.org/mpegif/mmset.html#proofs}}</ref>. This "substitution" is just the simple replacement of a variable with an expression and not the proper substitution described in works on [[predicate calculus]].
'''Metamath''' is a computer-assisted [[proof checker]].<ref name="whatismm">{{cite web | author=Megill, Norman | title=What is Metamath? | work=Metamath Home Page | url=http://us.metamath.org/#faq}}</ref> It has no specific logic embedded and can simply be regarded as a device to apply inference rules to formulas. Simplicity is the master concept in the design of Metamath: the language of Metamath, employed to state the definitions, axioms, inference rules and theorems is only composed of a handful of keywords and all the proofs are checked using one simple algorithm based on the substitution of variables (with optional provisos for what variables must remain distinct after a substitution is made)<ref name="howpswork">{{cite web | author=Megill,Norman | title=How Proofs Work | work=Metamath Proof Explorer Home Page | url=http://us.metamath.org/mpegif/mmset.html#proofs}}</ref>. This "substitution" is just the simple replacement of a variable with an expression and not the proper substitution described in works on [[predicate calculus]].


Metamath has been used to develop ''set.mm'', a human-readable database containing about 8000 ({{as of|March 2008}}) fully formal proofs of mathematical theorems built upon [[ZFC]] set theory. Those proofs may be browsed on the internet using an interface called Metamath Proof Explorer. New theorems are added to ''set.mm'' daily; a table of the most recent proofs is maintained.<ref name="recent" /> Contributions are welcome. Help and information can be received either by asking Megill himself or by consulting a [[wiki]], where some FAQs are located.
Metamath has been used to develop ''set.mm'', a human-readable database containing about 8000 ({{as of|March 2008}}) fully formal proofs of mathematical theorems built upon [[ZFC]] set theory. Those proofs may be browsed on the internet using an interface called Metamath Proof Explorer. New theorems are added to ''set.mm'' daily; a table of the most recent proofs is maintained.<ref name="recent">{{ cite web | title=Most recent proofs | author=Megill, Norman | work=Metamath Proof Explorer | url=http://us2.metamath.org:8888/mpegif/mmrecent.html }}</ref> Contributions are welcome. Help and information can be received either by asking Megill himself or by consulting a [[wiki]], where some FAQs are located.


== Pros and cons of Metamath's philosophy==
== Pros and cons of Metamath's philosophy==

Revision as of 09:44, 10 September 2009

Metamath
Developer(s)Norman Megill
Repository
Operating systemLinux, Windows, Mac OS
TypeComputer-assisted proof checking
LicenseMainly GNU General Public License for the softwares and Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication for the databases
Websitehttp://metamath.org

Metamath is a computer-assisted proof checker.[1] It has no specific logic embedded and can simply be regarded as a device to apply inference rules to formulas. Simplicity is the master concept in the design of Metamath: the language of Metamath, employed to state the definitions, axioms, inference rules and theorems is only composed of a handful of keywords and all the proofs are checked using one simple algorithm based on the substitution of variables (with optional provisos for what variables must remain distinct after a substitution is made)[2]. This "substitution" is just the simple replacement of a variable with an expression and not the proper substitution described in works on predicate calculus.

Metamath has been used to develop set.mm, a human-readable database containing about 8000 (As of March 2008) fully formal proofs of mathematical theorems built upon ZFC set theory. Those proofs may be browsed on the internet using an interface called Metamath Proof Explorer. New theorems are added to set.mm daily; a table of the most recent proofs is maintained.[3] Contributions are welcome. Help and information can be received either by asking Megill himself or by consulting a wiki, where some FAQs are located.

Pros and cons of Metamath's philosophy

Metamath's simplicity philosophy has good and bad consequences. Unlike the Mizar system and other proof assistants, which tend to imitate the informal proofs normally used by mathematicians by automating (and hiding) the most technical parts, proofs developed using Metamath are fully detailed; this entails that every step can be verified by the readers even if the mathematical field the theorem belongs to is not known to them (though actual development of theorems and proofs normally requires some knowledge of the related subject). On the other hand resulting proofs are much longer than informal proofs or even formal developments in more advanced proof assistants—a proof that would only take two or three lines in a textbook might take over fifty steps in Metamath. Most of those steps are propositional or predicate calculus inferences, which are shown in Metamath and normally not mentioned in an informal proof.

A generic proof checker

Even if Metamath is used for mathematical proof checking, its algorithm is so general we can extend the field of its usage. In fact Metamath could be used with every sort of formal systems: the checking of a computer program could be considered (even if Metamath's low level would make it difficult); it could possibly even be a syntactic checker for a natural language. Because Metamath has a very generic concept of what a proof is (namely a tree of formulas connected by inference rules) and no specific logic is embedded in the software, Metamath can be used with species of logic as different as Hilbert-style logics or sequents-based logics or even with lambda calculus. In contrast, it is largely incompatible with logical systems which uses other things than formulas and inference rules. The original natural deduction system (due to Gerhard Gentzen), which uses an extra stack, is an example of a system that cannot be implemented with Metamath. In the case of natural deduction however it is possible to append the stack to the formulas (transforming the natural deduction formulas into a sort of sequent) so that Metamath's requirements are met.

What makes Metamath so generic is its substitution algorithm. This algorithm makes no assumption about the used logic and only checks the substitutions of variables are correctly done.

A step-by-step proof.

So here is a detailed example of how this algorithm works. Steps 1 and 2 of the theorem 2p2e4 in set.mm are depicted left. Let's explain how Metamath uses its substitution algorithm to check that step 2 is the logical consequence of step 1 when you use the theorem opreq2i. Step 2 states that . It is the conclusion of the theorem opreq2i. The theorem opreq2i states that if , then . This theorem would never appear under this cryptic form in a textbook but its literate formulation is banal: when two quantities are equal , one can replace one by the other in an operation. To check the proof Metamath attempts to unify with . There is only one way to do so: unifying with , with , with and with . So now Metamath uses the premise of opreq2i. This premise states that . As a consequence of its previous computation, Metamath knows that should be substituted by and by . The premise becomes and thus step 1 is therefore generated. In its turn step 1 is unified with df-2. df-2 is the definition of the number 2 and states that 2 = ( 1 + 1 ). Here the unification is simply a matter of constants and is straightforward (no problem of variables to substitute). So the verification is finished and these two steps of the proof of 2p2e4 are correct.

There is however some complications that are not shown on the picture. When Metamath unifies with it has to check that the syntactical rules are respected. In fact has the type class thus Metamath has to check that is also typed class This is done using the same sort of unification described in the paragraph above.

The above explanation may let suppose that formulas are stored by Metamath. In fact nothing of that sort exists. Metamath only stores the conclusion and the premises of the proven theorem and the list of the names of the theorems used by the proof and nothing more. But since it is possible, with the substitution algorithm, to generate the conclusion from the premises nothing more is required.

The Metamath language

The Metamath language is based on a very small number of tokens. There are two tokens to declare the symbols of the logic: one to declare the constants ($c) and one to declare the variables ($v). Syntactic rules and axioms are declared using the $a token, and inference rules are declared using $a for the conclusion and $e for the premises. Eventually, $p is used to declare a theorem and its proof.

Metamath tokens carefully follow the definition of a formal system. Typically a formal system is a quadruplet where is a finite set of symbols, a set of formulas ( syntactic rules allow to decide if a string of symbols is a formula or not ), a set of axioms, a set of inference rules.

It is pretty straightforward to connect the tokens of Metamath with the abstract definition of a formal system. The finite set of symbols is declared using the $c and the $v tokens. The syntactic rules (used to define the set of formulas), the set of axioms and the set of inference rules are declared using the $a token.

We can notice that in Metamath syntactic rules, axioms and inference rules use the same token (namely the $a token). This feature is not obvious if one refers to the definition of a formal system above since this definition uses three different sets (, , ) . This at least shows that in Metamath there is no essential separation between the syntactical analysis and the properly logic treatment nor any separation between axioms and inference rules. This economical point of view is in many ways proper to Metamath where things that are often thought (perhaps too strongly) as being different are in fact confused (this tendency can be met in other places: for instance see below the remark definitions).

Further remarks

Definitions
In Metamath a definition is an axiom, and the $a token is used to declare a definition as it is used to declare an axiom. The only difference lies in the fact that in definitions the definiendum may be replaced (and thus eliminated) by the definiens. For instance A =/= B is defined by ( A =/= B <-> -. A = B ) (-. meaning "not"). So if we consider the theorem |- A =/= { A } and if we replace the definiendum =/= by the definiens ( -. A = B we get -. A = { A }. Then we can continue (replacing { A } by its definition) until there are only primitive symbols (i.e. equality, the "belong to" relation, quantifiers and individual variables. The symbol used by Metamath to link definiens and definiendum is the equivalence operator. Specific operators are frequently used in textbooks to express definitions (such as a biimplication sign with a small "def" above the arrow) but the equivalence operator is appropriate and it also allows to use the normal propositional calculus to manage the formulas (a specific operator wouldn't be as economical).
Theorems and proof
A proof is associated with a theorem using the $p token. In theoretical logic, a proof is a list of formulas, each of which are either axioms or the consequences of the application of an inference rule to previous formulas in the list. Metamath allows the use of other theorems that have already been proved and supports the use of hypotheses (using the $e statement). Only the names (not the effective formulas) of the used theorems and axioms are stored in a Metamath proof.
Type of variables
In Metamath variables are typed with the $f statement. In set.mm, for instance, there are only three types: propositional, individual and class variables.
Schemes
Whereas a formal description of logic uses formulas with actual variables, Metamath uses schemes. The variables of Metamath's theorem schemes are generic variables, and any appropriate substitution can be made for them.[4] The fact that a theorem is a scheme means that in fact it refers to a whole set of theorems. The theorem in fact can be used for , or .
Symbols
since Metamath database are intended to be human-readable, Metamath uses ASCII to denote mathematical symbols. In set.mm the notation is occasionally different from standard. For example, [ y / x ] ph might denote the formula that corresponds to ph when x has been properly substituted by y (and which is usually written in a mathematics textbook), and ( F ` B ) might denote the value taken by the function F when applied to B (it would be coded in a textbook).[5]

Databases

Metamath comes along with two main databases set.mm and ql.mm. set.mm stores theorems concerning ZFC theory and ql.mm develops a set of quantum logic theorems. Three internet interfaces (the Metamath Proof Explorer, the Hilbert Space Explorer and the Quantum Logic Explorer) are provided to explore these two databases in a human friendly way.

Metamath Proof Explorer

Metamath Proof Explorer
A proof of the Metamath Proof Explorer
Type of site
Internet encyclopedia project
HeadquartersUSA
OwnerNorman Megill
Created byNorman Megill
URLus.metamath.org/mpegif/mmset.html
CommercialNo
RegistrationNo

One of the seminal ideas that lead Megill to design Metamath was the desire to precisely determine the correctness of some proofs ("I enjoy abstract mathematics, but I sometimes get lost in a barrage of definitions and start to lose confidence that my proofs are correct."[6]), we can also think that the spirit of the Encyclopedia animates the growing up of Metamath and its most important database (called set.mm). Reading set.mm we may have sometimes the impression that the ambition of its author is essentially to add all the mathematics one theorem after the other.

set.mm has been maintained for more than ten years now (the first proofs in set.mm are dated August 1993). It is mainly a work by Norman Megill but there are also proofs made by other participants. Technically speaking set.mm develops—in the Hilbert style—ZFC set theory with the addition of the Grothendieck-Tarski axiom (to manage categories). The underlying logic is classical propositional calculus and classical predicate calculus with equality.

set.mm is a valuable tool to understand how well-known set theory concepts such as classes, power sets, union, relations, functions, equivalence classes and so on are derived from the axioms.

However set.mm doesn't stop at these basic notions but explores more elaborated theories.

Cantor concepts such as ordinal and cardinal numbers, equinumerosity or aleph function are defined.

Integers and natural numbers are constructed along with traditional arithmetic tools such as operations, recursion or induction.

The real and complex numbers are constructed from Dedekind cuts, and the concepts of sequence, limit of a sequence, sum of a series and so on are developed for them. The concept of integral is still missing.

Square root, exponentiation, exponential and trigonometric functions are implemented.

General topology is currently developed: topological spaces, closed and open sets, neighborhood, limit point, continuous function, Hausdorff spaces, metric spaces, Cauchy sequences have been defined.

One can also find some theorems of algebra concerning groups, rings, vector spaces and Hilbert spaces.

Hilbert Space Explorer

The Hilbert Space Explorer presents more than 1,000 theorems pertaining to the Hilbert space theory. Those theorems are included in set.mm. They are not shown in the Metamath Proof Explorer because they have been developed by adding extra axioms to the standard axioms of set.mm. ZFC is weakened by this adding which explains why the resulting proofs are shown in a separate Explorer. This adding (justified by historical opportunity reasons) is theoretically useless since the concept of Hilbert space can be designed with the standard ZFC axioms.

Quantum Logic Explorer

Quantum logic theorems can be found in the database ql.mm. The Quantum Logic Explorer is an internet interface to this database.[7]

Annexe 1: Pedagogy

The method of proof used by Metamath is far different from what is used in a school context. In schools what is required is the literate, synthetic method of proof developed by mathematicians since Euclid's time.[8][9] In Metamath, the method of proof is the symbolic, analytical method of proof invented by Aristotle, Leibniz, Peano and Frege. Thus, Metamath is unsuitable for school exercises. To speak simply, the proofs in Metamath are much too detailed to be used with ease in school. However, set.mm can be used in a school context as an example of a symbolic system that is big enough to be interesting. set.mm can also be useful because its detailed, symbolic, unambiguous definitions can disambiguate confusing textbook definitions.

Megill gives a list of text books[10] that can be used with Metamath and many theorems in the database reference them. People who want to learn mathematics for themselves can thus use Metamath in connection with these books.

Annexe 2: Other works connected to Metamath

Proof checkers

Using the design ideas implemented in Metamath, Raph Levien has implemented what might be the smallest proof checker in the world, mmverify.py, at only 500 lines of Python code.

Ghilbert[11] is a similar though more elaborate language based on mmverify.py. Levien would like to implement a system where several people could collaborate together and his work is emphasizing modularity and connection between small theories.

Using Levien seminal works, many other implementations of the Metamath design principles have been implemented for a broad variety of languages. Juha Arpiainen has implemented his own proof checker in Common Lisp called Bourbaki[12] and Marnix Klooster has coded a proof checker in Haskell called Hmm[13].

Although they all use the overall Metamath approach to formal system checker coding, they also implement new concepts of their own.

Editors

Mel O'Cat designed a system called Mmj2[14] which provides a graphic user interface for proof entry. The initial aim of Mel O'Cat was to allow the user to enter the proofs by simply typing the formulas and letting Mmj2 find the appropriate inference rules to connect them. In Metamath on the contrary you may only enter the theorems names. You may not enter the formulas directly. Mmj2 has also the possibility to enter the proof forward or backward (Metamath only allows to enter proof backward). Moreover Mmj2 has a real grammar parser (unlike Metamath). This technical difference brings more comfort to the user. In particular Metamath sometimes hesitates between several formulas analyzes (most of them being meaningless) and asks the user to choose. In Mmj2 this limitation no longer exists.

There is also a project by William Hale to add a graphical user interface to Metamath called Mmide[15]. Paul Chapman in its turn is working on a new proof browser, which has highlighting that allows you to see the referenced theorem before and after the substitution was made.

Databases

set.mm is by far the biggest database written for Metamath, but there is also a formalization (by Robert Solovay) of Peano arithmetic called peano.mm (included in metamath.zip) and a formalization of natural deduction called nat.mm[16]. There is a database based on the formal system MIU presented in Gödel, Escher, Bach. Raph Levien has also designed several databases for his Ghilbert program.

References

  1. ^ Megill, Norman. "What is Metamath?". Metamath Home Page.
  2. ^ Megill,Norman. "How Proofs Work". Metamath Proof Explorer Home Page.
  3. ^ Megill, Norman. "Most recent proofs". Metamath Proof Explorer.
  4. ^ Megill, Norman. "A Note on the Axioms". Metamath Proof Explorer Home Page.
  5. ^ Megill. "Definition df-fv". Metamath Proof Explorer.
  6. ^ Megill. "Metamath: A Computer Language for Pure Mathematics" (PDF). p. xi
  7. ^ Norman Megill and Mladen Pavičić. "Quantum Logic Explorer Home Page". Quantum Logic Explorer.
  8. ^ Megill, Norman. "Mathematical vernacular". Asteroid Meta Wiki.
  9. ^ Wiedijk, Freek. "The mathematical vernacular" (PDF).
  10. ^ Megill, Norman. "Reading suggestions". Metamath.
  11. ^ Levien,Raph. "Presentation of Ghilbert". Asteroid Meta Wiki.
  12. ^ Arpiainen, Juha. "Presentation of Bourbaki". Asteroid Meta Wiki.
  13. ^ Klooster,Marnix. "Presentation of Hmm". Asteroid Meta Wiki.
  14. ^ O'Cat,Mel. "Presentation of mmj2". Asteroid Meta Wiki.
  15. ^ Hale, William. "Presentation of mmide". Asteroid Meta Wiki.
  16. ^ Liné, Frédéric. "Natural deduction based Metamath system". Asteroid Meta Wiki.