Jump to content

List of valid argument forms

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This is an old revision of this page, as edited by Materialscientist (talk | contribs) at 13:58, 24 November 2020 (Reverted edits by 198.57.7.136 (talk) to last version by SmartyPants22). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

Of the many and varied argument forms that can possibly be constructed, only very few are valid argument forms. In order to evaluate these forms, statements are put into logical form. Logical form replaces any sentences or ideas with letters to remove any bias from content and allow one to evaluate the argument without any bias due to its subject matter.[1]

Being a valid argument does not necessarily mean the conclusion will be true. It is valid because if the premises are true, then the conclusion has to be true. This can be proven for any valid argument form using a truth table which shows that there is no situation in which there are all true premises and a false conclusion.[2]

Valid syllogistic forms

In syllogistic logic, there are 256 possible ways to construct categorical syllogisms using the A, E, I, and O statement forms in the square of opposition. Of the 256, only 24 are valid forms. Of the 24 valid forms, 15 are unconditionally valid, and 9 are conditionally valid.

Unconditionally valid

Figure 1 Figure 2 Figure 3 Figure 4
AAA
EAE
AII
EIO
AEE
EAE
EIO
AOO
AII
IAI
OAO
EIO
AEE
IAI
EIO

Conditionally valid

Figure 1 Figure 2 Figure 3 Figure 4 Required condition
AAI
EAO
AEO
EAO
AEO S exists
AAI
EAO
EAO M exists
AAI P exists

Valid propositional forms

The following is a list of some common valid argument forms in propositional logic. It is nowhere near exhaustive, and gives only a few examples of the better known valid argument forms.

Modus ponens

One valid argument form is known as modus ponens, not to be mistaken with modus tollens which is another valid argument form that has a like-sounding name and structure. Modus ponens (sometimes abbreviated as MP) says that if one thing is true, then another will be. It then states that the first is true. The conclusion is that the second thing is true.[3] It is shown below in logical form.

If A, then B
A
Therefore B

Before being put into logical form the above statement could have been something like below.

If Kelly does not finish his homework, he will not go to class
Kelly did not finish his homework
Therefore, Kelly will not go to class

The first two statements are the premises while the third is the conclusion derived from them.

Modus tollens

Another form of argument is known as modus tollens (commonly abbreviated MT). In this form, you start with the same first premise as with modus ponens. However, the second part of the premise is denied, leading to the conclusion that the first part of the premise should be denied as well. It is shown below in logical form.

If A, then B
Not B
Therefore not A.[3]

When modus tollens is used with actual content, it looks like below.

If the Saints win the Super Bowl, there will be a party in New Orleans that night
There was no party in New Orleans that night
Therefore, the Saints did not win the Super Bowl

Hypothetical syllogism

Much like modus ponens and modus tollens, hypothetical syllogism (sometimes abbreviated as HS) contains two premises and a conclusion. It is however, slightly more complicated than the first two. In short, it states that if one thing happens, another will as well. If that second thing happens, a third will follow it. Therefore, if the first thing happens, it is inevitable that the third will too.[3] It is shown below in logical form.

If A, then B
If B, then C
Therefore if A, then C

When put into words it looks like below.

If it rains today, I will wear my rain jacket
If I wear my rain jacket, I will keep dry
Therefore if it rains today, I will keep dry

Disjunctive syllogism

Disjunctive syllogism (sometimes abbreviated DS) has one of the same characteristics as modus tollens in that it contains a premise, then in a second premise it denies a statement, leading to the conclusion. In Disjunctive Syllogism, the first premise establishes two options. The second takes one away, so the conclusion states that the remaining one must be true.[3] It is shown below in logical form.

Either A or B
Not A
Therefore B

When used A and B are replaced with real life examples it looks like below.

Either you will see Joe in class today or he will oversleep
You did not see Joe in class today
Therefore Joe overslept

Disjunctive syllogism takes two options and narrows it down to one.

Constructive dilemma

Another valid form of argument is known as constructive dilemma or sometimes just 'dilemma'. It does not leave the user with one statement alone at the end of the argument, instead, it gives an option of two different statements. The first premise gives an option of two different statements. Then it states that if the first one happens, there will be a particular outcome and if the second happens, there will be a separate outcome. The conclusion is that either the first outcome or the second outcome will happen. The criticism with this form is that it does not give a definitive conclusion; just a statement of possibilities.[3] When it is written in argument form it looks like below.

Either A or B
If A then C
If B then D
Therefore either C or D

When content is inserted in place of the letters, it looks like below.

Bill will either take the stairs or the elevator to his room
If he takes the stairs, he will be tired when he gets to his room
If he takes the elevator, he will miss the start of the football game on TV
Therefore Bill will either be tired when he gets to his room or he will miss the start of the football game

There is a slightly different version of dilemma that uses negation rather than affirming something known as destructive dilemma. When put in argumentative form it looks like below.

If A then C
If B then D
Not C or not D
Therefore not A or not B [4]

References

  1. ^ May, Robert (1993). Logical form: its structure and derivation. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.
  2. ^ Stanley, Jason (30 August 2000). "Context and Logical Form". Linguistics and Philosophy. 23 (4).
  3. ^ a b c d e Johnson, Robert (2006). A Logic Book: Fundamentals of Reasoning. Cengage Learning.
  4. ^ Elugardo, Reinaldo (1 September 2001). "Logical Form and the Vernacular". Mind and Language. 16 (4).