BCK algebra

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Jump to: navigation, search

In mathematics, BCI and BCK algebras are algebraic structures, introduced by Y. Imai, K. Iséki and S. Tanaka in 1966, that describe fragments of the propositional calculus involving implication known as BCI and BCK logics.

Definition[edit]

BCI algebra[edit]

An algebra of type is called a BCI-algebra if, for any , it satisfies the following conditions. (Informally, we may read as "truth" and as " implies ".)

BCI-1
BCI-2
BCI-3
BCI-4
BCI-5

BCK algebra[edit]

A BCI-algebra is called a BCK-algebra if it satisfies the following condition:

BCK-1

A partial order can then be defined as xy iff x * y = 0.

A BCK-algebra is said to be commutative if it satisfies:

In a commutative BCK-algebra x * (x * y) = xy, the greatest lower bound of x and y under the partial order ≤.

A BCK-algebra is said to be bounded if it has a largest element, usually denoted by 1. In a bounded commutative BCK-algebra the least upper bound of two elements satisfies xy = 1 * ((1 * x) ∧ (1 * y)); that makes it a distributive lattice.

Examples[edit]

Every abelian group is a BCI-algebra, with * defined as group subtraction and 0 defined as the group identity.

The subsets of a set form a BCK-algebra, where A*B is the difference A\B (the elements in A but not in B), and 0 is the empty set.

A Boolean algebra is a BCK algebra if A*B is defined to be A∧¬B (A does not imply B).

The bounded commutative BCK-algebras are precisely the MV-algebras.

References[edit]