Epicurus

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
  (Redirected from Epicurean paradox)
Jump to navigation Jump to search
Epicurus
Epicurus bust2.jpg
Roman marble bust of Epicurus
Born February 341 BC
Samos
Died 270 BC
Athens
Era Ancient philosophy
Region Western philosophy
School Epicureanism, atomism, materialism, hedonism
Main interests
Physics, ethics, epistemology
Notable ideas
Pleasure principle,
the "moving"/"static" pleasures distinction,
ataraxia, aponia, atomic swerve[1]
Epicurean paradox

Epicurus[a] (341–270 BC) was an ancient Greek philosopher who founded a school of philosophy now called Epicureanism. Only a few fragments and letters of Epicurus's 300 written works remain. Much of what is known about Epicurean philosophy derives from later followers and commentators.

For Epicurus, the purpose of philosophy was to attain the happy, tranquil life, characterized by ataraxia—peace and freedom from fear—and aponia—the absence of pain—and by living a self-sufficient life surrounded by friends. He taught that the root of all human neurosis was death denial, and the tendency for human beings to assume that death will be horrific and painful, which he claimed causes unnecessary anxiety, selfish self-protective behaviors, and hypocrisy. According to Epicurus, death is the end of both the body and the soul and therefore should not be feared. He also taught that the gods neither reward nor punish humans; that the universe is infinite and eternal; and that occurrences in the natural world are ultimately the result of atoms moving and interacting in empty space.

Life[edit]

Upbringing and influences[edit]

His parents, Neocles and Chaerestrate, both Athenian-born, and his father a citizen, had emigrated to the Athenian settlement on the Aegean island of Samos about ten years before Epicurus's birth in February 341 BC.[3] Epicurus grew up during the final years of the Greek Classical Period.[4] Plato had died seven years before Epicurus was born and Epicurus was seven years old when Alexander the Great crossed the Hellespont into Persia.[5] As a boy, he studied philosophy for four years under the Platonist teacher Pamphilus. At the age of eighteen, he went to Athens for his two-year term of military service. The playwright Menander served in the same age-class of the ephebes as Epicurus.

After the death of Alexander the Great, Perdiccas expelled the Athenian settlers on Samos to Colophon, on the coast of what is now Turkey. After the completion of his military service, Epicurus joined his family there. He studied under Nausiphanes, who followed the teachings of Democritus.[6]

Allocation of key positions and satrapies following the Partition of Babylon in 323 BC after the death of Alexander the Great. Epicurus came of age at a time when Greek intellectual horizons were vastly expanding due to the rise of the Hellenistic Kingdoms across the Near East.[7]

Epicurus's teachings were heavily influenced by those of earlier philosophers, particularly Democritus. Nonetheless, Epicurus differed from his predecessors on several key points of determinism and vehemently denied having been influenced by any previous philosophers, whom he denounced as "confused". Instead, he insisted that he had been "self-taught".[8] According to Norman Wentworth DeWitt, Epicurus's teachings also show influences from the contemporary philosophical school of Cynicism.[9] The Cynic philosopher Diogenes of Sinope was still alive when Epicurus would have been in Athens for his required military training and it is possible they may have met.[9] Diogenes's pupil Crates of Thebes (c. 365 – c. 285 BC) was a close contemporary of Epicurus.[9] Epicurus agreed with the Cynics' quest for honesty, but rejected their "insolence and vulgarity", instead teaching that honesty must be coupled with courtesy and kindness.[9] Epicurus shared this view with his contemporary, the comic playwright Menander.[10]

Epicurus's Letter to Menoeceus, possibly an early work of his, is written in an eloquent style similar to that of the Athenian rhetorician Isocrates (436–338 BC),[9] but, for his later works, he seems to have adopted the bald, intellectual style of the mathematician Euclid.[9] Epicurus's epistemology also bears an unacknowledged debt to the later writings of Aristotle (384–322 BC), who rejected the Platonic idea of hypostatic Reason and instead relied on nature and empirical evidence for knowledge about the universe.[7] During Epicurus's formative years, Greek knowledge about the rest of the world was rapidly expanding due to the Hellenization of the Near East and the rise of Hellenistic kingdoms.[7] Epicurus's philosophy was consequently more universal in its outlook than those of his predecessors, since it took cognizance of non-Greek peoples as well as Greeks.[7] He may have had access to the now-lost writings of the historian and ethnographer Megasthenes, who wrote during the reign of Seleucus I Nicator (ruled 305–281 BC).[7]

Teaching career[edit]

During Epicurus's lifetime, Platonism was the dominant philosophy in higher education.[11] Epicurus's radical opposition to Platonism drove the development of a large part of his thought.[12][13] Over half of the forty Authorized Doctrines of Epicureanism are flat contradictions of Platonism.[12] In around 311 BC, Epicurus, when he was only around thirty years old, Epicurus began teaching in Mytilene.[12] Around this time, Zeno of Citium, the founder of Stoicism, arrived in Athens at the age of about twenty-one.[12] Although later texts, such as the writings of the first-century BC Roman orator Cicero, portray Epicureanism and Stoicism as rivals,[12] this rivalry seems to have only emerged in later times and did not exist during Epicurus's own lifetime.[12] Zeno, however, did not begin teaching until long after Epicurus.[12]

Epicurus's teachings caused strife in Mytilene and he was forced to leave. He then founded a school in Lampsacus before returning to Athens in 306 BC where he remained until his death. There he founded The Garden (κῆπος), a school named for the garden he owned that served as the school's meeting place, about halfway between the locations of two other schools of philosophy, the Stoa and the Academy.[6] Epicurus never married and had no known children. He was most likely a vegetarian.[14][15]

In Mytilene, the capital of the island Lesbos, and then in Lampsacus Epicurus taught and gained followers. In Athens Epicurus bought a property for his school called "Garden", later the name of Epicurus school.[16] The primary members were Hermarchus, the financier Idomeneus, Leonteus and his wife Themista, the satirist Colotes, the mathematician Polyaenus of Lampsacus, Leontion, and Metrodorus of Lampsacus, the most famous popularizer of Epicureanism. His school was the first of the ancient Greek philosophical schools to admit women as a rule rather than an exception.[b] An inscription on the gate to The Garden is recorded by Seneca the Younger in epistle XXI of Epistulae morales ad Lucilium:[17]

Stranger, here you will do well to tarry; here our highest good is pleasure.

Epicurus emphasised friendship as an important ingredient of happiness, and the school resembled in many ways a community of friends living together. However, he also instituted a hierarchical system of levels among his followers, and had them swear an oath on his core tenets.

According to Diskin Clay, Epicurus himself established a custom of celebrating his birthday annually with common meals, befitting his stature as heros ktistes ("founding hero") of the Garden. He ordained in his will annual memorial feasts for himself on the same date (10th of Gamelion month).[18] Epicurean communities continued this tradition,[19] referring to Epicurus as their "saviour" (soter) and celebrating him as hero. Lucretius apotheosized Epicurus as the main character of his epic poem De rerum natura. The hero cult of Epicurus may have operated as a Garden variety civic religion.[20] However, clear evidence of an Epicurean hero cult, as well as the cult itself, seems buried by the weight of posthumous philosophical interpretation.[21] Epicurus' cheerful demeanour, as he continued to work despite dying from a painful stone blockage of his urinary tract lasting a fortnight, according to his successor Hermarchus and reported by his biographer Diogenes Laërtius, further enhanced his status among his followers.[22]

Death[edit]

He suffered from kidney stones,[22] to which he finally succumbed in 270 BC[23] at the age of seventy-two, and despite the prolonged pain involved, he wrote to Idomeneus:

I have written this letter to you on a happy day to me, which is also the last day of my life. For I have been attacked by a painful inability to urinate, and also dysentery, so violent that nothing can be added to the violence of my sufferings. But the cheerfulness of my mind, which comes from the recollection of all my philosophical contemplation, counterbalances all these afflictions. And I beg you to take care of the children of Metrodorus, in a manner worthy of the devotion shown by the young man to me, and to philosophy.[24]

Three Epicurus bronze busts were recovered from the Villa of the Papyri, as well as text fragments.[25]

Konstan from the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy notes "Short citations of Epicurus' works appear in other writers (e.g., Plutarch, Sextus Empiricus, and the Greek commentators on Aristotle), often taken out of context or presented in a polemical and distorted fashion. [...] The school tended to be conservative and later thinkers embellished rather than altered Epicurus' own teachings."[16]

Teachings[edit]

Small bronze bust of Epicurus from Herculaneum. Illustration from Baumeister, 1885

Prefiguring science and ethics[edit]

Epicurus is a key figure in the development of science and scientific methodology because of his insistence that nothing should be believed, except that which was tested through direct observation and logical deduction. Epicurus's teachings represented a departure from the other major Greek thinkers of his period, and before, but was nevertheless founded on many of the same principles as Democritus. Like Democritus, he was an atomist, believing that the fundamental constituents of the world were indivisible little bits of matter (atoms; Greek: ἄτομος atom os, "indivisible") flying through empty space (Greek: κενόν kenon). Everything that occurs is the result of the atoms colliding, rebounding, and becoming entangled with one another. His theory differs from the earlier atomism of Democritus because he admits that atoms do not always follow straight lines but their direction of motion may occasionally exhibit a "swerve" (Greek: παρέγκλισις parenklisis; Latin: clinamen). This allowed him to avoid the determinism implicit in the earlier atomism and to affirm free will.[26]

He regularly admitted women and slaves into his school and was one of the first Greeks to break from the god-fearing and god-worshipping tradition common at the time, even while affirming that religious activities are useful as a way to contemplate the gods and to use them as an example of the pleasant life. Epicurus participated in the activities of traditional Greek religion, but taught that one should avoid holding false opinions about the gods. The gods are immortal and blessed and men who ascribe any additional qualities that are alien to immortality and blessedness are, according to Epicurus, impious. The gods do not punish the bad and reward the good as the common man believes. The opinion of the crowd is, Epicurus claims, that the gods "send great evils to the wicked and great blessings to the righteous who model themselves after the gods," whereas Epicurus believes the gods, in reality, do not concern themselves at all with human beings.

It is not the man who denies the gods worshipped by the multitude, who is impious, but he who affirms of the gods what the multitude believes about them.[27]

Pleasure as absence of suffering[edit]

Epicurus' philosophy is based on the theory that all good and bad derive from the sensations of what he defined as pleasure and pain: What is good is what is pleasurable, and what is bad is what is painful. His ideas of pleasure and pain were ultimately, for Epicurus, the basis for the moral distinction between good and evil. If pain is chosen over pleasure in some cases it is only because it leads to a greater pleasure. Although Epicurus has been commonly misunderstood to advocate the rampant pursuit of pleasure, his teachings were more about striving for an absence of pain and suffering, both physical and mental, and a state of satiation and tranquillity that was free of the fear of death and the retribution of the gods. Epicurus argued that when we do not suffer pain, we are no longer in need of pleasure, and we enter a state of ataraxia, "tranquillity of soul" or "imperturbability".[28][29]

Epicurus distinguishes between two different types of pleasure: "moving" pleasures (κατὰ κίνησιν ἡδοναί) and "static" pleasures (καταστηματικαὶ ἡδοναί).[30][31] "Moving" pleasures occur when one is in the process of satisfying a desire and involve an active titillation of the senses.[30] After one's desires have been satisfied, (e.g., when one is full after eating), the state of satiety is a "static" pleasure.[30] For Epicurus, static pleasures are the best pleasures.[30]

Epicurus' teachings were introduced into medical philosophy and practice by the Epicurean doctor Asclepiades of Bithynia, who was the first physician who introduced Greek medicine in Rome. Asclepiades introduced the friendly, sympathetic, pleasing and painless treatment of patients. He advocated humane treatment of mental disorders, had insane persons freed from confinement and treated them with natural therapy, such as diet and massages. His teachings are surprisingly modern, therefore Asclepiades is considered to be a pioneer physician in psychotherapy, physical therapy and molecular medicine.[32]

Epicurus explicitly warned against overindulgence because it often leads to pain. For instance, Epicurus warned against pursuing love too ardently. He defended friendships as ramparts for pleasure and denied them any inherent worth.[33] He also believed, contrary to Aristotle,[34] that death was not to be feared. When a man dies, he does not feel the pain of death because he no longer is and therefore feels nothing. Therefore, as Epicurus famously said, "death is nothing to us." When we exist, death is not; and when death exists, we are not. All sensation and consciousness ends with death and therefore in death there is neither pleasure nor pain. The fear of death arises from the belief that in death, there is awareness.

From this doctrine arose the Epicurean epitaph: Non fui, fui, non sum, non curo ("I was not; I was; I am not; I do not care"), which is inscribed on the gravestones of his followers and seen on many ancient gravestones of the Roman Empire. This quotation is often used today at humanist funerals.[35]

As an ethical guideline, Epicurus emphasised minimising harm and maximising happiness of oneself and others:

It is impossible to live a pleasant life without living wisely and well and justly, and it is impossible to live wisely and well and justly without living pleasantly.

("justly" meaning to prevent a "person from harming or being harmed by another")[36]

Theology[edit]

First-century AD Roman fresco from Pompeii, showing the mythical human sacrifice of Iphigenia, daughter of Agamemnon. Epicurus's devoted follower, the Roman poet Lucretius, cited this myth as an example of the evils of popular religion, in contrast to the more wholesome theology advocated by Epicurus.[37]

In his Letter to Menoeceus, a summary of his own moral and theological teachings, the first piece of advice Epicurus himself gives to his student is: "First, believe that a god is an indestructible and blessed animal, in accordance with the general conception of god commonly held, and do not ascribe to god anything foreign to his indestructibility or repugnant to his blessedness."[38] Epicurus maintained that he and his followers knew that the gods exist because "our knowledge of them is a matter of clear and distinct perception", meaning that people can empirically sense their presences.[39] He did not mean that people can see the gods as physical objects, but rather that they can see visions of the gods sent from the remote regions of interstellar space in which they actually reside.[39] According to George K. Strodach, Epicurus could have easily dispensed of the gods entirely without greatly altering his materialist worldview,[39] but the gods still play one important function in Epicurus's theology as the paragons of moral virtue to be emulated and admired.[39]

Epicurus rejected the conventional Greek view of the gods as anthropomorphic beings who walked the earth like ordinary people, fathered illegitimate offspring with mortals, and pursued personal feuds.[39] Instead, he taught that the gods are morally perfect, but detached and immobile beings who live in the remote regions of interstellar space.[40] In line with these teachings, Epicurus adamantly rejected the idea that deities were involved in human affairs in any way.[38][41] Epicurus maintained that the gods are so utterly perfect and removed from the world that they are incapable of listening to prayers or supplications or doing virtually anything aside from contemplating their own perfections.[40] In his Letter to Herodotus, he specifically denies that the gods have any control over natural phenomena, arguing that this would contradict their fundamental nature, which is perfect, because any kind of worldly involvement would tarnish their perfection.[41] He further warned that believing that the gods control natural phenomena would only mislead people into believing the superstitious view that the gods punish humans for wrongdoing, which only instills fear and prevents people from attaining ataraxia.[41]

Epicurus himself criticizes popular religion in both his Letter to Menoeceus and his Letter to Herodotus, but in a restrained and moderate tone.[42] Later Epicureans mainly followed the same ideas as Epicurus, believing in the existence of the gods, but emphatically rejecting the idea of divine providence.[38] Their criticisms of popular religion, however, are often less gentle than those of Epicurus himself.[43] The Letter to Pythocles, written by a later Epicurean, is dismissive and contemptuous towards popular religion[43] and Epicurus's devoted follower, the Roman poet Lucretius (c. 99 BC – c. 55 BC), passionately assailed popular religion in his philosophical poem One the Nature of Things.[43] In this poem, Lucretius declares that popular religious practices not only do not instill virtue, but rather result in "misdeeds both wicked and ungodly", citing the mythical sacrifice of Iphigenia as an example.[37] Lucretius argues that divine creation and providence are illogical, not because the gods do not exist, but rather because these notions are incompatible with the Epicurean principles of the gods' indestructability and blessedness.[44][45] The later Skeptic philosopher Sextus Empiricus (c. 160 – c. 210 AD) rejected the teachings of the Epicureans specifically because he regarded them as theological "Dogmaticists".[46]

Epicurean paradox[edit]

The most famous version of the problem of evil is attributed to Epicurus by David Hume (pictured), who was relying on an attribution of it to him by the Christian apologist Lactantius. The trilemma does not occur in any of Epicurus's extant writings, however. If Epicurus did write some version of it, it would have been an argument against divine providence, not the existence of deities.[47]

The Epicurean paradox or riddle of Epicurus or Epicurus' trilemma is a version of the problem of evil. Lactantius attributes this trilemma to Epicurus in De Ira Dei:

God, he says, either wishes to take away evils, and is unable; or He is able, and is unwilling; or He is neither willing nor able, or He is both willing and able. If He is willing and is unable, He is feeble, which is not in accordance with the character of God; if He is able and unwilling, He is envious, which is equally at variance with God; if He is neither willing nor able, He is both envious and feeble, and therefore not God; if He is both willing and able, which alone is suitable to God, from what source then are evils? Or why does He not remove them?

In Dialogues concerning Natural Religion (1779), David Hume also attributes the argument to Epicurus:

Epicurus’s old questions are yet unanswered. Is he willing to prevent evil, but not able? then is he impotent. Is he able, but not willing? then is he malevolent. Is he both able and willing? whence then is evil?

No extant writings of Epicurus contain this argument.[47] However, the vast majority of Epicurus's writings have been lost and it is possible that some form of this argument may have been found in his lost treatise On the Gods, which Diogenes Laërtius describes as one of his greatest works.[47] If Epicurus really did make some form of this argument, it would not have been an argument against the existence of deities, but rather an argument against divine providence.[47] Epicurus's extant writings demonstrate that he did believe in the existence of deities.[38] Furthermore, religion was such an integral part of daily life in Greece during the early Hellenistic Period that it is doubtful anyone during that period could have been an atheist in the modern sense of the word.[38] Instead, the Greek word ἄθεος (átheos), meaning "without a god", was used as a term of abuse, not as an attempt to describe a person's beliefs.[38]

Epistemology[edit]

Epicurus emphasised the senses in his epistemology, and his Principle of Multiple Explanations ("if several theories are consistent with the observed data, retain them all") is an early contribution to the philosophy of science.

There are also some things for which it is not enough to state a single cause, but several, of which one, however, is the case. Just as if you were to see the lifeless corpse of a man lying far away, it would be fitting to list all the causes of death in order to make sure that the single cause of this death may be stated. For you would not be able to establish conclusively that he died by the sword or of cold or of illness or perhaps by poison, but we know that there is something of this kind that happened to him.[48][49]

Politics[edit]

In contrast to the Stoics, Epicureans showed little interest in participating in the politics of the day, since doing so leads to trouble. He instead advocated seclusion. This principle is epitomised by the phrase lathe biōsas (λάθε βιώσας), meaning "live in obscurity", "get through life without drawing attention to yourself", i.e., live without pursuing glory or wealth or power, but anonymously, enjoying little things like food, the company of friends, etc. Plutarch elaborated on this theme in his essay Is the Saying "Live in Obscurity" Right? (Εἰ καλῶς εἴρηται τὸ λάθε βιώσας, An recte dictum sit latenter esse vivendum) 1128c; cf. Flavius Philostratus, Vita Apollonii 8.28.12.

But the Epicureans did have an innovative theory of justice as a social contract. Justice, Epicurus said, is an agreement neither to harm nor be harmed, and we need to have such a contract in order to enjoy fully the benefits of living together in a well-ordered society. Laws and punishments are needed to keep misguided fools in line who would otherwise break the contract. But the wise person sees the usefulness of justice, and because of his limited desires, he has no need to engage in the conduct prohibited by the laws in any case. Laws that are useful for promoting happiness are just, but those that are not useful are not just. (Principal Doctrines 31–40)

Works[edit]

Epicurus was an extremely prolific writer.[50][47][51] According to Diogenes Laërtius, he wrote around 300 treatises on a variety of subjects.[47][51] The only surviving complete works by Epicurus are three letters, which are quoted in their entirety in Book X of Diogenes Laërtius's Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, and two groups of quotes: the Principal Doctrines (Κύριαι Δόξαι), which are likewise preserved through quotation by Diogenes Laërtius, and the Vatican Sayings, preserved in a manuscript from the Vatican Library that was first discovered in 1888.[51] In the Letter to Herodotus and the Letter to Pythocles, Epicurus summarizes his philosophy on nature and, in the Letter to Menoeceus, he summarizes his moral teachings.[51]

Numerous fragments of Epicurus's lost thirty-seven volume treatise On Nature have been found among the charred papyrus fragments at the Villa of the Papyri at Herculaneum.[51] Scholars first began attempting to unravel and decipher these scrolls began in 1800, but the efforts are painstaking and are still ongoing.[51] In addition, other Epicurean writings found at Herculaneum contain important quotations from his other works. Moreover, numerous fragments and testimonies are found throughout ancient Greek and Roman literature, a collection of which can be found in Usener's Epicurea.[citation needed] Most of what is known about Epicurus's teachings come from the writings of his later followers, particularly the Roman poet Lucretius.[51]

According to Diogenes Laertius (10.27-9), the major works of Epicurus include:

  1. On Nature, in 37 books
  2. On Atoms and the Void
  3. On Love
  4. Abridgment of the Arguments employed against the Natural Philosophers
  5. Against the Megarians
  6. Problems
  7. Fundamental Propositions (Kyriai Doxai)
  8. On Choice and Avoidance
  9. On the Chief Good
  10. On the Criterion (the Canon)
  11. Chaeridemus,
  12. On the Gods
  13. On Piety
  14. Hegesianax
  15. Four essays on Lives
  16. Essay on Just Dealing
  17. Neocles
  18. Essay addressed to Themista
  19. The Banquet (Symposium)
  20. Eurylochus
  21. Essay addressed to Metrodorus
  22. Essay on Seeing
  23. Essay on the Angle in an Atom
  24. Essay on Touch
  25. Essay on Fate
  26. Opinions on the Passions
  27. Treatise addressed to Timocrates
  28. Prognostics
  29. Exhortations
  30. On Images
  31. On Perceptions
  32. Aristobulus
  33. Essay on Music (i.e., on music, poetry, and dance)
  34. On Justice and the other Virtues
  35. On Gifts and Gratitude
  36. Polymedes
  37. Timocrates (three books)
  38. Metrodorus (five books)
  39. Antidorus (two books)
  40. Opinions about Diseases and Death, addressed to Mithras
  41. Callistolas
  42. Essay on Kingly Power
  43. Anaximenes
  44. Letters

Legacy[edit]

Ancient Epicureanism[edit]

Bust of Epicurus leaning against his disciple Metrodorus in the Louvre Museum

Epicureanism was extremely popular from the very beginning.[52][53] It rapidly spread beyond the Greek mainland all across the Mediterranean world.[52] By the first century BC, it had established a strong foothold in Italy.[52] The Roman orator Cicero, who deplored Epicurean ethics, declared, "the Epicureans have taken Italy by storm."[52] Epicureans and admirers of Epicureanism revered Epicurus himself as a great teacher of ethics, a savior, and even a god.[54] His image was worn on finger rings, portraits of him were displayed in living rooms, and wealthy followers venerated likenesses of him in marble sculpture.[55] His admirers revered his sayings as divine oracles, carried around copies of his writings, and cherished copies of his letters like the letters of an apostle.[55] On the twentieth day of every month, admirers of his teachings would perform a solemn ritual to honor his memory.[53] At the same time, opponents of his teachings denounced him with vehemence and persistence.[53]

However, in the first and second centuries AD, Epicureanism gradually began to decline as it failed to compete with Stoicism, which had an ethical system more in line with traditional Roman values.[56] Epicureanism also suffered decay in the wake of Christianity, which was also rapidly expanding throughout the Roman Empire.[57] Of all the Greek philosophical schools, Epicureanism was the one most at odds with the new Christian teachings, since Epicureans believed that the soul was mortal, denied the existence of an afterlife, denied that the divine had any active role in human life, and advocated pleasure as the foremost goal of human existence.[57] As such, Christian writers such as Justin Martyr (c. 100–c. 165 AD), Athenagoras of Athens (c. 133–c. 190), Tertullian (c. 155–c. 240), and Clement of Alexandria (c. 150–c. 215), Arnobius (died c. 330), and Lactantius all singled it out for the most vitriolic criticism.[57]

In spite of this, DeWitt argues that Epicureanism and Christianity share much common language, calling Epicureanism "the first missionary philosophy" and "the first world philosophy".[58] Both Epicureanism and Christianity placed strong emphasis on the importance of love and forgiveness[59] and early Christian portrayals of Jesus are often similar to Epicurean portrayals of Epicurus.[59] DeWitt argues that Epicureanism, in many ways, helped pave the way for the spread of Christianity by "helping to bridge the gap between Greek intellectualism and a religious way of life" and "shunt[ing] the emphasis from the political to the social virtues and offer[ing] what may be called a religion of humanity."[60]

Middle Ages[edit]

Dante Alighieri meets Epicurus in his Inferno in the Sixth Circle of Hell, where he and his followers are imprisoned in flaming coffins for having believed that the soul dies with the body,[57] shown here in an illustration by Gustave Doré.

By the early fifth century AD, Epicureanism was virtually extinct.[57] The Christian Church Father Augustine of Hippo (354–430 AD) declared, "its ashes are so cold that not a single spark can be struck from them."[57] While the ideas of Plato and Aristotle could easily be adapted to suit a Christian worldview, the ideas of Epicurus were not nearly as easily amenable.[57] As such, while Plato and Aristotle enjoyed a privileged place in Christian philosophy throughout the Middle Ages, Epicurus was not held in such esteem.[57] Information about Epicurus's teachings was available, through Lucretius's On the Nature of Things, quotations of it found in medieval Latin grammars and florilegia, and encyclopedias, such as Isidore of Seville's Etymologiae (seventh century) and Hrabanus Maurus's De universo (ninth century),[57] but there is little evidence that these teachings were systematically studied or comprehended.[57]

During the Middle Ages, Epicurus was remembered by the educated as a philosopher,[57] but he frequently appeared in popular culture as a gatekeeper to the Garden of Delights, the "proprietor of the kitchen, the tavern, and the brothel."[57] He appears in this guise in Martianus Capella's Marriage of Mercury and Philology (fifth century), John of Salisbury's Policraticus (1159), John Gower's Mirour de l'Omme, and Geoffrey Chaucer's Canterbury Tales.[57] Epicurus and his followers appear in Dante Alighieri's Inferno in the Sixth Circle of Hell, where they are imprisoned in flaming coffins for having believed that the soul dies with the body.[57]

Renaissance[edit]

In 1417, a manuscript-hunter named Poggio Bracciolini discovered a copy of Lucretius's On the Nature of Things in a monastery near Lake Constance.[57] The discovery of this manuscript was met with immense excitement, because scholars were eager to analyze and study the teachings of classical philosophers and this previously-forgotten text contained the most comprehensive account of Epicurus's teachings known in Latin.[57] The first scholarly dissertation on Epicurus, De voluptate (On Pleasure) by the Italian Humanist and Catholic priest Lorenzo Valla was published in 1431.[57] Valla made no mention of Lucretius or his poem.[57] Instead, he presented the treatise as a discussion on the nature of the highest good between an Epicurean, a Stoic, and a Christian.[57] Valla's dialogue ultimately rejects Epicureanism,[57] but, by presenting an Epicurean as a member of the dispute, Valla lent Epicureanism credibility as a philosophy that deserved to be taken seriously.[57]

None of the Quattrocento Humanists ever clearly endorsed Epicureanism,[57] but scholars such as Francesco Zabarella (1360–1417), Francesco Filelfo (1398–1481), Cristoforo Landino (1424–1498), and Leonardo Bruni (c. 1370–1444) did give Epicureanism a fairer analysis than it had traditionally received and provided a less overtly hostile assessment of Epicurus himself.[57] Nonetheless, "Epicureanism" remained a pejorative, synonymous with extreme egoistic pleasure-seeking, rather than a name of a philosophical school.[57] This reputation discouraged orthodox Christian scholars from taking what others might regard as an inappropriately keen interest in Epicurean teachings.[57] Epicureanism did not take hold in Italy, France, or England until the seventeenth century.[61] Even the liberal religious skeptics who might have been expected to take an interest in Epicureanism evidently did not;[61] Étienne Dolet (1509–1546) only mentions Epicurus once in all his writings and François Rabelais (between 1483 and 1494–1553) never mentions him at all.[62] Michel de Montaigne (1533–1592) is the exception to this trend, quoting a full 450 lines of Lucretius's On the Nature of Things in his Essays.[62] His interest in Lucretius, however, seems to have been primarily literary and he is ambiguous about his feelings on Lucretius's Epicurean worldview.[62] During the Protestant Reformation, the label "Epicurean" was bandied back and forth as an insult between Protestants and Catholics.[62]

Revival[edit]

In the seventeenth century, the French Catholic priest and scholar Pierre Gassendi (1592–1655) sought to dislodge Aristotelianism from its position of the highest dogma by presenting Epicureanism as a better and more rational alternative.[62] In 1647, Gassendi published his book De vita et moribus Epicuri (The Life and Morals of Epicurus), a passionate defense of Epicureanism.[62] In 1649, he published a commentary on Diogenes Laertius's Life of Epicurus.[62] He left Syntagma philosophicum (Philosophical Compendium), a synthesis of Epicurean doctrines, unfinished at the time of his death in 1655.[62] It was finally published in 1658, after undergoing revision by his editors.[62] Gassendi modified Epicurus's teachings to make them palatable for a Christian audience.[62] For instance, he argued that atoms were not eternal, uncreated, and infinite in number, instead contending that an extremely large but finite number of atoms were created by God at creation.[62] As a result of Gassendi's modifications, his books were never censored by the Catholic Church.[62] They came to exert profound influence on later writings about Epicurus.[62]

His emphasis on minimising harm and maximising happiness in his formulation of the Ethic of Reciprocity was later picked up by the democratic thinkers of the French Revolution, and others, like John Locke, who wrote that people had a right to "life, liberty, and property."[63]

This triad, as well as the egalitarianism of Epicurus, was carried forward into the American freedom movement and Declaration of Independence, by the American founding father, Thomas Jefferson, as "all men are created equal" and endowed with certain "unalienable rights," such as "life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness." Jefferson considered himself an Epicurean.[64]

Epicurus was first to assert human freedom as coming from a fundamental indeterminism in the motion of atoms. This has led some philosophers to think that for Epicurus free will was caused directly by chance. In his On the Nature of Things (De rerum natura), Lucretius appears to suggest this in the best-known passage on Epicurus' position.[65] But in his Letter to Menoeceus, Epicurus follows Aristotle and clearly identifies three possible causes - "some things happen of necessity, others by chance, others through our own agency." Aristotle said some things "depend on us" (eph'hemin). Epicurus agreed, and said it is to these last things that praise and blame naturally attach. For Epicurus, the "swerve" (or clinamen) of the atoms simply defeated determinism to leave room for autonomous agency.[66]

In literature and popular media[edit]

Paul the Apostle encountered Epicurean and Stoic philosophers as he was ministering in Athens.[67]

Horace describes himself as Epicuri de grege porcum "a swine from Epicurus's herd" in his Epistles.[68]

Chaucer's Frankeleyn, in the General Prologue of his Canterbury Tales, is described as an Epicurean: "Wel loved he by the morwe a sop in wyn; / To lyven in delit was evre his wone, / For he was Epicurus owene sone, / That heeld opinioun that pleyn delit / Was verray felicitee parfit" (344-38). [He well loved bread soaked in wine for breakfast; / To live in pleasure was ever his custom, / For he was a son of Epicurus, / Who was of the opinion that pure pleasure / Was true perfect happiness.]

See also[edit]

Notes[edit]

  1. ^ /ˌɛpɪˈkjʊərəs/;[2] Greek: Ἐπίκουρος, Epíkouros, "ally, comrade"
  2. ^ Two women, Axiothea and Lastheneia, were known to have been admitted by Plato. See Hadot, Pierre. Qu'est-ce que la philosophie antique?, page 99, Gillimard 1995. Pythagoras is also believed to have inducted one woman, Theano, into his order.

Citations[edit]

  1. ^ Bunnin & Yu (2004). The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. 
  2. ^ Jones, Daniel (2006). Cambridge English Pronouncing Dictionary. 17th edition. Cambridge UP. 
  3. ^ Apollodorus of Athens (reported by Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 10.14–15) gives his birth on the fourth day of the month February in the third year of the 109th Olympiad, in the archonship of Sosigenes
  4. ^ De Witt 1954, pp. 8–9.
  5. ^ De Witt 1954, p. 8.
  6. ^ a b "Epicurus - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy". 
  7. ^ a b c d e De Witt 1954, p. 10.
  8. ^ "Epicurus' Attitude to Democritus" JSTOR
  9. ^ a b c d e f De Witt 1954, p. 9.
  10. ^ De Witt 1954, pp. 9–10.
  11. ^ De Witt 1954, pp. 9, 11.
  12. ^ a b c d e f g De Witt 1954, p. 11.
  13. ^ Long 1999, pp. 239–240.
  14. ^ "The Hidden History of Greco-Roman Vegetarianism". 
  15. ^ Dombrowski, Daniel A. (1984). The Philosophy of Vegetarianism. ISBN 978-0870234316. 
  16. ^ a b David Konstan. "Epicurus". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 
  17. ^ "Epistulae morales ad Lucilium". 
  18. ^ D. Smith, Nicholas (2000). Reason and religion in Socratic philosophy. p. 160. ISBN 978-0-19-513322-6. 
  19. ^ Glad, Clarence E. Paul and Philodemus: adaptability in Epicurean and early Christian psychology. p. 176. ISBN 978-90-04-10067-1. 
  20. ^ Nussbaum, Martha Craven (2009). The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic Ethics. p. 119. ISBN 978-0-691-14131-2. 
  21. ^ Clay, Diskin (1998). Paradosis and survival: three chapters in the history of Epicurean philosophy. p. 76. ISBN 978-0-472-10896-1. 
  22. ^ a b Bitsori, Maria; Galanakis, Emmanouil (2004). "Epicurus' death". World Journal of Urology. 22 (6): 466–469. doi:10.1007/s00345-004-0448-2. PMID 15372192. 
  23. ^ In the second year of the 127th Olympiad, in the archonship of Pytharatus, according to Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 10.15
  24. ^ Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 10.22 (trans. C.D. Yonge).
  25. ^ Sheila Dillon (2006). Ancient Greek Portrait Sculpture: Contexts, Subjects, and Styles. Cambridge University Press. p. 45. ISBN 9780521854986 – via Google Books. 
  26. ^ The only fragment in Greek about this central notion is from the Oenoanda inscription (fr. 54 in Smith's edition). The best known reference is in Lucretius's On the nature of things, [1].
  27. ^ letter by Epicurus to Menoeceus; see Diogenes Laërtius de clarorum philosophorum vitis, dogmatibus et apophthegmatibus libri decem (X, 123)
  28. ^ Folse, Henry (2005). How Epicurean Metaphysics leads to Epicurean Ethics. Department of Philosophy, Loyola University, New Orleans, LA. 
  29. ^ Konstan, David. Epicurus, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition). forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/epicurus/>
  30. ^ a b c d Epicurus | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  31. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, X:136.
  32. ^ C, Yapijakis (2009). "Hippocrates of Kos, the father of clinical medicine, and Asclepiades of Bithynia, the father of molecular medicine. Review". In Vivo. 23 (4): 507–14. PMID 19567383. 
  33. ^ Cicero, Marcus Tullius. "II.82". De finibus bonorum et malorum. ISBN 978-3-519-01219-1. 
  34. ^ Rosenbaum, Stephen. Appraising Death In Human Life: Two Modes Of Valuation, in French, Peter, and Wettstein, Howard (editors), Life And Death: Metaphysics And Ethics, Midwest Studies In Philosophy, volume XXIV. Blackwell Publishers, Inc., 2000, p.153 (Aristotle 'seems to have believed [in] fearing death ... . [But] his conclusion should be understood to be [merely] that the fact that a person dies is bad [because] nothing is any longer good or bad for him or her.') Books.Google.com (accessed 2011-Feb-04)
  35. ^ "Epicurus (c 341-270 BC)". British Humanist Association. 
  36. ^ "Epicurus Principal Doctrines 5 and 31 transl. by Robert Drew Hicks". 1925. 
  37. ^ a b Strodach 2012, pp. 46–47.
  38. ^ a b c d e f Hickson 2014, pp. 27.
  39. ^ a b c d e Strodach 2012, p. 39.
  40. ^ a b Strodach 2012, pp. 39–40.
  41. ^ a b c Strodach 2012, pp. 42–43.
  42. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 45–46.
  43. ^ a b c Strodach 2012, p. 46.
  44. ^ Hickson 2014, pp. 27–28.
  45. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 43–45.
  46. ^ Hickson 2014, p. 28.
  47. ^ a b c d e f Hickson 2014, pp. 26–27.
  48. ^ Lucretius.[full citation needed]
  49. ^ The poem version can be found in: Carus, Titus Lucretius (Jul 2008). Of The Nature of Things. Project Gutenberg EBook. 785. William Ellery Leonard (translator). Project Gutenberg.  Book VI, Section Extraordinary and Paradoxical Telluric Phenomena, Line 9549–9560
  50. ^ Long 1999, p. 240.
  51. ^ a b c d e f g Kenny 2004, p. 94.
  52. ^ a b c d Grafton, Most & Settis 2010, p. 320.
  53. ^ a b c De Witt 1954, p. 3.
  54. ^ De Witt 1954, pp. 3, 31–32.
  55. ^ a b De Witt 1954, pp. 3, 32.
  56. ^ Grafton, Most & Settis 2010, pp. 320–321.
  57. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y Grafton, Most & Settis 2010, p. 321.
  58. ^ De Witt 1954, pp. 8, 26–33.
  59. ^ a b De Witt 1954, pp. 31–32.
  60. ^ De Witt 1954, pp. 8, cf. 26–33.
  61. ^ a b Grafton, Most & Settis 2010, pp. 321–322.
  62. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m Grafton, Most & Settis 2010, p. 322.
  63. ^ John Locke (1689) "Two Treatises of Government#Property"
  64. ^ Jefferson considered himself an Epicurean (1819): "Letter, Thomas Jefferson to William Short"
  65. ^ 2.251-262 "On the Nature of Things, 289-293" Check |url= value (help) – via Perseus Project. 
  66. ^ "Epicurus page on Information Philosopher; cf. Letter to Menoeceus, §134". 
  67. ^ The Holy Bible, Acts 17:18 – via Biblegateway.com 
  68. ^ Horace, Epistles Bk I, ep. 4 v. 16. uah.edu

Bibliography[edit]

Further reading[edit]

Texts
  • Epicurus (1994). Inwood, Brad; Gerson, Lloyd P., eds. The Epicurus Reader. Selected Writings and Testimonia. Indianapolis: Hackett. ISBN 978-0-87220-242-9. 
  • Epicurus (1993). The essential Epicurus : letters, principal doctrines, Vatican sayings, and fragments. Eugene O'Connor, trans. Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books. ISBN 978-0-87975-810-3. 
  • Epicurus (1964). Letters, principal doctrines, and Vatican sayings. Russel M. Geer, trans. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill. 
  • Laertius, Diogenes (1969). Caponigri, A. Robert, ed. Lives of the Philosophers. Chicago: Henry Regnery Co. 
  • Lucretius Carus, Titus (1976). On the nature of the universe. R. E. Latham, trans. London: Penguin Books. ISBN 978-0-14-044018-8. 
  • Körte, Alfred (1987). Epicureanism : two collections of fragments and studies (in Greek). New York: Garland. ISBN 978-0-8240-6915-5. 
  • Oates, Whitney J. (1940). The Stoic and Epicurean philosophers, The Complete Extant Writings of Epicurus, Epictetus, Lucretius and Marcus Aurelius. New York: Modern Library.
  • Diogenes of Oinoanda (1993). The Epicurean inscription. Martin Ferguson Smith, trans. Napoli: Bibliopolis. ISBN 978-88-7088-270-4. 
Studies
  • Asmis, Elizabeth (1984). Epicurus' Scientific Method. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-08014-1465-7. 
  • Bailey C. (1928). The Greek Atomists and Epicurus, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Bakalis, Nikolaos (2005). Handbook of Greek Philosophy from Thales to the Stoics. Analysis and fragments. Victoria: Trafford. ISBN 978-1-4120-4843-9. 
  • Gordon, Pamela (1996). Epicurus in Lycia. The Second-Century World of Diogenes of Oenoanda. Ann Arbor: Univ. of Michigan Press. ISBN 978-0-472-10461-1. 
  • Gottlieb, Anthony (2000). The Dream of Reason. A History of Western Philosophy from the Greeks to the Renaissance. New York: W.W. Norton. ISBN 978-0-393-04951-0. 
  • Hibler, Richard W. (1984). Happiness Through Tranquillity. The school of Epicurus. Lanham, MD: University Press of America. ISBN 978-0-8191-3861-3. 
  • Hicks, R. D. (1910). Stoic and Epicurean. New York: Scribner. 
  • Jones, Howard (1989). The Epicurean Tradition. London: Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-02069-5. 
  • O'Keefe, Tim (2009). Epicureanism. University of California Press. 
  • Panichas, George Andrew (1967). Epicurus. New York: Twayne Publishers. 
  • Rist, J.M. (1972). Epicurus. An introduction. London: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-08426-0. 
  • Warren, James (2009). The Cambridge Companion to Epicureanism. New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-05218-7347-5. 
  • William Wallace. Epicureanism. SPCK (1880)

External links[edit]

Portrait
Primary sources