On all absolute values of rational numbers
In number theory, Ostrowski's theorem, due to Alexander Ostrowski (1916), states that every non-trivial absolute value on the rational numbers
is equivalent to either the usual real absolute value or a p-adic absolute value.[1]
Definitions[edit]
Raising an absolute value to a power less than 1 always results in another absolute value. Two absolute values
and
on a field K are defined to be equivalent if there exists a real number c > 0 such that

The trivial absolute value on any field K is defined to be

The real absolute value on the rationals
is the standard absolute value on the reals, defined to be

This is sometimes written with a subscript 1 instead of infinity.
For a prime number p, the p-adic absolute value on
is defined as follows: any non-zero rational x can be written uniquely as
, where a and b are coprime integers not divisible by p, and n is an integer; so we define

Consider a non-trivial absolute value on the rationals
. We consider two cases:

It suffices for us to consider the valuation of integers greater than one. For, if we find
for which
for all naturals greater than one, then this relation trivially holds for 0 and 1, and for positive rationals

and for negative rationals

Case (1)[edit]
This case implies that there exists
such that
By the properties of an absolute value,
and
, so
(it cannot be zero). It therefore follows that b > 1.
Now, let
with a > 1. Express bn in base a:

Hence
so 
Then we see, by the properties of an absolute value:

As each of the terms in the sum is smaller than
, it follows:

Therefore,

However, as
, we have

which implies

Together with the condition
the above argument shows that
regardless of the choice of a > 1 (otherwise
, implying
). As a result, the initial condition above must be satisfied by any b > 1.
Thus for any choice of natural numbers a, b > 1, we get

i.e.

By symmetry, this inequality is an equality.
Since a, b were arbitrary, there is a constant
for which
, i.e.
for all naturals n > 1. As per the above remarks, we easily see that
for all rationals, thus demonstrating equivalence to the real absolute value.
Case (2)[edit]
As this valuation is non-trivial, there must be a natural number for which
Factoring into primes:

yields that there exists
such that
We claim that in fact this is so for only one.
Suppose per contra that p, q are distinct primes with absolute value less than 1. First, let
be such that
. Since
and
are coprime, there are
such that
This yields

a contradiction.
So we must have
for some j, and
for i ≠ j. Letting

we see that for general positive naturals

As per the above remarks, we see that
for all rationals, implying that the absolute value is equivalent to the p-adic one.
One can also show a stronger conclusion, namely, that
is a nontrivial absolute value if and only if either
for some
or
for some
.
Another Ostrowski's theorem[edit]
Another theorem states that any field, complete with respect to an Archimedean absolute value, is (algebraically and topologically) isomorphic to either the real numbers or the complex numbers. This is sometimes also referred to as Ostrowski's theorem.[2]
See also[edit]
References[edit]