Structuralism (biology)

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Jump to: navigation, search
In his 1917 book On Growth and Form, D'Arcy Thompson illustrates the geometric transformation of one fish's body form into another with a 20° shear mapping. He does not discuss the evolutionary causes of such a change, and has accordingly been suspected of vitalism.[1]

Biological or process structuralism is a school of biological thought that objects to an exclusively Darwinian or adaptationist explanation of natural selection (in the Neodarwinian synthesis for example), arguing that other mechanisms also guide evolution, and sometimes implying that these supersede selection altogether.

Structuralists have proposed different mechanisms that might have guided the formation of body plans. Before Darwin, Étienne Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire argued that animals shared homologous parts, and that if one was enlarged, the others would be reduced in compensation. After Darwin, D'Arcy Thompson hinted at vitalism and offered geometric explanations in his classic 1917 book On Growth and Form. Adolf Seilacher suggested mechanical inflation for "pneu" structures in Ediacaran biota fossils such as Dickinsonia. Günter P. Wagner argued for developmental bias, structural constraints on embryonic development. Stuart Kauffman favoured self-organisation, the idea that complex structure emerges holistically and spontaneously from the dynamic interaction of all parts of an organism. Michael Denton argued for laws of form by which Platonic universals or "Types" are self-organised. Stephen J. Gould and Richard Lewontin proposed biological "spandrels", features created as a byproduct of the adaptation of nearby structures. G. B. Muller and S. A. Newman argued that the appearance in the fossil record of most of the current phyla in the Cambrian explosion was "pre-Mendelian"[a] evolution caused by physical factors. Brian Goodwin, described by Wagner as part of "a fringe movement in evolutionary biology",[2] denies that biological complexity can be reduced to natural selection, and argues that pattern formation is driven by morphogenetic fields.

Darwinian biologists have criticised structuralism, emphasising that there is plentiful evidence from deep homology that genes have been involved in shaping organisms throughout evolutionary history. They accept that some structures such as the cell membrane self-assemble, but question the ability of self-organisation to drive large-scale evolution.

History[edit]

Multiple alternatives to Darwinism have been offered since the 19th century to explain how evolution took place, given that many scientists initially objected to natural selection. Many of these theories, including structural or developmental constraints, led to some form of directed evolution (orthogenesis), with or without invoking divine control. These theories were largely swept aside by the modern synthesis of genetics and natural selection in the early 20th century.

Geoffroy St-Hilaire's law of compensation[edit]

In 1830, Étienne Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire argued a structuralist case against the functionalist (teleological) position of Georges Cuvier. Geoffroy believed that homologies of structure between animals indicated that they shared an ideal pattern; these did not imply evolution but a unity of plan, a law of nature.[b] He further believed that if one part was more developed within a structure, the other parts would necessarily be reduced in compensation, as nature always used the same materials: if more of them were used for one feature, less was available for the others.[3]

D'Arcy Thompson's morphology[edit]

In his "eccentric, beautiful"[4] 1917 book On Growth and Form, D'Arcy Wentworth Thompson revisited the old idea of "universal laws of form" to explain the observed forms of living organisms.[1] The science writer Philip Ball states that Thompson "presents mathematical principles as a shaping agency that may supersede natural selection, showing how the structures of the living world often echo those in inorganic nature", and notes his "frustration at the 'Just So' explanations of morphology offered by Darwinians." Instead, Ball writes, Thompson elaborates on how not heredity but physical forces govern biological form.[5] The philosopher of biology Michael Ruse similarly wrote that Thompson "had little time for natural selection", certainly preferring "mechanical explanations" and possibly straying into vitalism.[1]

Seilacher's pneu structures[edit]

Dickinsonia fossil described as a "pneu" structure with chambers inflated like a quilted air mattress. In Adolf Seilacher's structuralist view, the structure is determined mechanically by the need to distribute the tension across the surface, rather than having been guided by natural selection.

Like Thompson, the palaeontologist Adolf Seilacher emphasised fabricational constraints on form. He interpreted fossils such as Dickinsonia in the Ediacaran biota as "pneu" structures determined by mechanical inflation like a quilted air mattress, rather than having been driven by natural selection.[6][7]

Wagner's constraints on development[edit]

In his 2014 book Homology, Genes, and Evolutionary Innovation, the evolutionary biologist Günter P. Wagner argues for "the study of novelty as distinct from adaptation."[2][8] He forms a structuralist picture of evolutionary developmental biology, well supported by empirical evidence, arguing that homology and biological novelty are key aspects requiring explanation, and that developmental bias (i.e. structural constraints on embryonic development) is a key explanation for these.[9]

Kauffman's self-organisation[edit]

Darwinists and structuralists agree that cell structures like the cell membrane spontaneously self-organize. They disagree on how important self-organization is in other areas of biology.

The mathematical biologist Stuart Kauffman suggested in 1993 that self-organization may play a role alongside natural selection in three areas of evolutionary biology, namely population dynamics, molecular evolution, and morphogenesis. With respect to molecular biology, Kauffman has been criticised for ignoring the role of energy in driving biochemical reactions in cells, which can fairly be called self-catalysing but which do not simply self-organise.[10]

Denton's 'Types'[edit]

The biochemist Michael Denton has argued a structuralist case for self-organization. In a 2013 paper, he claimed that "the basic forms of the natural world—the Types—are immanent in nature, and determined by a set of special natural biological laws, the so called 'laws of form'." He asserts that these "recurring patterns and forms" are "genuine universals".[c] Form is in this view not shaped by natural selection, but by "self-organizing properties of particular categories of matter" and by "cosmic fine-tuning of the laws of nature".[12] Denton has been criticised by the biochemist Laurence A. Moran as anti-Darwinian and favouring creationism.[13]

Gould and Lewontin's spandrels[edit]

An ornamented bridge spandrel. Steven J. Gould and Richard Lewontin argued that the triangular area is a byproduct of the adaptation of structures around it.

In 1979, influenced by Seilacher among others, the paleontologist Stephen J. Gould and the population geneticist Richard Lewontin wrote what Wagner called "the most influential structuralist manifesto", "The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm".[2] They pointed out that biological features (like architectural spandrels) did not necessarily have adaptation as their direct cause. Instead, architects couldn't help creating small triangular areas between arches and pillars, as arches need (evolve) to be curved, and pillars need to be vertical. The resulting spandrels are exaptations, consequences of other evolutionary changes. Evolution, they argued, did not select for a protruding human chin: instead, reducing the length of the tooth row left the jaw protruding.[2]

Muller and Newman's pre-Mendelian evolution[edit]

Extreme structuralists like G. B. Muller and S. A. Newman, inheriting the viewpoint of D'Arcy Thompson, have proposed that physical laws of structure, not genetics, govern major diversifications such as the Cambrian explosion, followed later by co-opted genetic mechanisms.[14][15] They argued further that there was a "pre-Mendelian" phase of the evolution of animals, involving physical forces, before genes took over.[14][16] Darwinian biologists freely admit that physical factors such as surface tension can cause self-assembly, but insist that genes play a crucial role. They note for example that deep homologies between widely separated groups of organisms, such as the signalling pathways and transcription factors of choanoflagellates and metazoans, demonstrate that genes have been involved throughout evolutionary history.[17]

Goodwin's morphogenetic fields[edit]

Natural patterns like those on the skin of the Giant pufferfish can be created by spatial oscillations of chemical signals.

What Wagner calls "a fringe movement in evolutionary biology",[2] the form of structuralism exemplified by Brian Goodwin,[2][18] effectively denies that natural selection exists,[2] or at least that biological complexity could be reduced to natural selection.[19][20] This led to conflict with Darwinists such as Richard Dawkins.[21] Goodwin related the old concept of a morphogenetic field to the spatial distribution of chemical signals in a developing embryo.[22] He demonstrated with a mathematical model that a variety of patterns could be formed by choosing parameter values to set up either static geometric patterns or dynamic oscillations.[19][20] Goodwin's views have been criticised by the biologists Richard Dawkins, Stephen J. Gould, Lynn Margulis, and Steve Jones.[13]

See also[edit]

Notes[edit]

  1. ^ Gregor Mendel pioneered the study of genetics.
  2. ^ In this, Geoffroy's homologies were like Aristotle's forms.
  3. ^ Universals are central to the ancient Greek theory, Platonic realism.[11]

References[edit]

  1. ^ a b c Ruse, Michael (2013). "17. From Organicism to Mechanism-and Halfway Back?". In Henning, Brian G.; Scarfe, Adam. Beyond Mechanism: Putting Life Back Into Biology. Lexington Books. p. 419. 
  2. ^ a b c d e f g Wagner, Günter P., Homology, Genes, and Evolutionary Innovation. Princeton University Press. 2014. Chapter 1: The Intellectual Challenge of Morphological Evolution: A Case for Variational Structuralism. Pages 7–38
  3. ^ Racine, Valerie (7 October 2013). "Essay: The Cuvier-Geoffroy Debate". The Embryo Project Encyclopedia, Arizona State University. Retrieved 10 December 2016. 
  4. ^ Leroi, Armand Marie (2014). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. p. 13. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4. 
  5. ^ Ball, Philip (7 February 2013). "In retrospect: On Growth and Form". Nature. 494: 32–33. doi:10.1038/494032a. 
  6. ^ Seilacher, Adolf (1991). Schmidt-Kittler, Norbert; Vogel, Klaus, eds. Self-Organizing Mechanisms in Morphogenesis and Evolution. Constructional Morphology and Evolution. Springer. pp. 251–271. ISBN 978-3-642-76158-4. 
  7. ^ Seilacher, Adol (July 1989). "Vendozoa: Organismic construction in the Proterozoic biosphere". Lethaia. 22: 229–239. doi:10.1111/j.1502-3931.1989.tb01332.x. 
  8. ^ Simpson, Carl; Erwin, Douglas H. (quoted). "Homology, Genes, and Evolutionary Innovation Günter P. Wagner". Princeton University Press. Retrieved 9 December 2016. 
  9. ^ Brown, Rachael L. (November 2015). "Why development matters". Biology & Philosophy. 30 (6): 889–899. doi:10.1007/s10539-015-9488-9. 
  10. ^ Fox, Ronald F. (December 1993). "Review of Stuart Kauffman, The Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution". Biophys. J. 65 (6): 2698–2699. PMC 1226010Freely accessible. 
  11. ^ Silverman, Allan. "Plato's Middle Period Metaphysics and Epistemology". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 
  12. ^ Denton, Michael J. (August 2013). "The Types: A Persistent Structuralist Challenge to Darwinian Pan-Selectionism". BIO-Complexity. 
  13. ^ a b Moran, Laurence A. "What is "Structuralism"?". Sandwalk (blog of a recognised expert). Retrieved 9 December 2016. 
  14. ^ a b Erwin, Douglas H. (September 2011). "Evolutionary uniformitarianism". Developmental Biology. 357 (1): 27–34. doi:10.1016/j.ydbio.2011.01.020. 
  15. ^ Muller, G.B.; Newman, S.A. The innovation triad: an EvoDevo agenda. J. Exp. Zool. (Mol. Dev Evol), 304B (2005), pp. 487–503
  16. ^ Newman, S.A.; Forgacs, G.; Muller, G.B. Before programs: the physical origination of multicellular forms. Int. J. Dev. Biol., 50 (2006), pp. 289–299
  17. ^ King, N. The unicellular ancestry of animal development. Dev. Cell, 7 (2004), pp. 313–325
  18. ^ Goodwin, Brian (2009). Ruse, Michael; Travis, Joseph, eds. Beyond the Darwinian Paradigm: Understanding Biological Forms. Evolution: The First Four Billion Years. Harvard University Press. 
  19. ^ a b Price, Catherine S. C. (1995). Structurally Unsound. Evolution. Vol. 49, No. 6. pp. 1298-1302.
  20. ^ a b Wake, David B. (1996). How the Leopard Changed Its Spots: The Evolution of Complexity by Brian Goodwin. American Scientist. Vol. 84, No. 3. pp. 300-301.
  21. ^ Brian Goodwin obituary - The Guardian, 9 August 2009
  22. ^ Dickinson, W. Joseph. (1998). Form and Transformation: Generative and Relational Principles in Biology. by Gerry Webster; Brian Goodwin. The Quarterly Review of Biology. Vol. 73, No. 1. pp. 62-63.