Monotone convergence theorem

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This is an old revision of this page, as edited by StrokeOfMidnight (talk | contribs) at 01:48, 8 October 2017 (→‎Monotone convergence theorem for Lebesgue integral: say explicitly that the measurability is w.r.t. Borel sigma-algebra). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

In the mathematical field of real analysis, the monotone convergence theorem is any of a number of related theorems proving the convergence of monotonic sequences (sequences that are increasing or decreasing) that are also bounded. Informally, the theorems state that if a sequence is increasing and bounded above by a supremum, then the sequence will converge to the supremum; in the same way, if a sequence is decreasing and is bounded below by an infimum, it will converge to the infimum.

Convergence of a monotone sequence of real numbers

Lemma 1

If a sequence of real numbers is increasing and bounded above, then its supremum is the limit.

Proof

Let be such a sequence. By assumption, is non-empty and bounded above. By the least-upper-bound property of real numbers, exists and is finite. Now, for every , there exists such that , since otherwise is an upper bound of , which contradicts to the definition of . Then since is increasing, and is its upper bound, for every , we have . Hence, by definition, the limit of is

Lemma 2

If a sequence of real numbers is decreasing and bounded below, then its infimum is the limit.

Proof

The proof is similar to the proof for the case when the sequence is increasing and bounded above, and is left as an exercise to the reader.

Theorem

If is a monotone sequence of real numbers (i.e., if an ≤ an+1 for every n ≥ 1 or an ≥ an+1 for every n ≥ 1), then this sequence has a finite limit if and only if the sequence is bounded.[1]

Proof

  • "If"-direction: The proof follows directly from the lemmas.
  • "Only If"-direction: By definition of limit, every sequence with a finite limit is necessarily bounded.

Convergence of a monotone series

Theorem

If for all natural numbers j and k, aj,k is a non-negative real number and aj+1,k ≤ aj,k, then[2]: 168 

The theorem states that if you have an infinite matrix of non-negative real numbers such that

  1. the columns are weakly increasing and bounded, and
  2. for each row, the series whose terms are given by this row has a convergent sum,

then the limit of the sums of the rows is equal to the sum of the series whose term k is given by the limit of column k (which is also its supremum). The series has a convergent sum if and only if the (weakly increasing) sequence of row sums is bounded and therefore convergent.

As an example, consider the infinite series of rows

where n approaches infinity (the limit of this series is e). Here the matrix entry in row n and column k is

the columns (fixed k) are indeed weakly increasing with n and bounded (by 1/k!), while the rows only have finitely many nonzero terms, so condition 2 is satisfied; the theorem now says that you can compute the limit of the row sums by taking the sum of the column limits, namely .

Monotone convergence theorem for Lebesgue integral

The following result is due to Henri Lebesgue and Beppo Levi. In what follows, denotes the -algebra of Borel sets on .

Theorem

Let be a measure space, and . Consider a pointwise non-decreasing sequence of -measurable non-negative functions , i.e., for every and every ,

Set the pointwise limit of the sequence to be . That is, for every ,

Then is -measurable and

Remark 1. The integrals may be finite or infinite.

Remark 2. The theorem remains true if its assumptions hold -almost everywhere. In other words, it is enough that there is a subset such that , and the sequence non-decreases for every . Indeed, since , for every , we would then have

and

provided that is -measurable.[3]: section 21.38 

Remark 3. Under assumptions of the theorem,

Proof

This proof does not rely on Fatou's lemma. However, we do explain how that lemma might be used.

For those not interested in independent proof, the intermediate results below may be skipped.

Intermediate results

Lebesgue integral as measure

Lemma 1. Let be a measurable space. Consider a simple -measurable non-negative function . For a subset , define

.

Then is a measure on .

Proof

We will only prove countable additivity, leaving the rest up to the reader. Let , where all the sets are pairwise disjoint. Due to simplicity,

,

for some finite non-negative constants and pairwise disjoint sets such that . By definition of Lebesgue integral,

Since all the sets are pairwise disjoint, the countable additivity of gives us

Since all the summands are non-negative, the sum of the series, whether this sum is finite or infinite, cannot change if summation order does. For that reason,

as required.

Lemma about monotonic chain of sets

Lemma 2. Let be a measure, and , where

is a non-decreasing chain with all its sets -measurable. Then

.
Proof

Let . The sequence , where , consists of pairwise disjoint sets, , and . By countable additivity,

as required.

Proof of theorem

Step 1. We begin by showing that is –measurable.[3]: section 21.3 

Note. If we were using Fatou's lemma, the measurability would follow easily from Remark 3(a).

To do this without using Fatou's lemma, it is sufficient to show that the inverse image of an interval under is an element of the sigma-algebra on , because (closed) intervals generate the Borel sigma algebra on the reals. Since is a closed interval, and, for every , ,

Thus,

Being the inverse image of a Borel set under a -measurable function , each set in the countable intersection is an element of . Since -algebras are, by definition, closed under countable intersections, this shows that is -measurable, and the integral is well defined (and possibly infinite).

Step 2. We will first show that

The definition of and monotonicity of imply that , for every and every . It follows that

and

Note that the limit on the right exists (finite or infinite) because, due to monotonicity of Lebesgue integral, the sequence is non-decreasing.

End of Step 2.

We now prove the reverse inequality. We seek to show that

.

Proof using Fatou's lemma. Per Remark 3, the inequality we want to prove is equivalent to

.

But the latter follows immediately from Fatou's lemma, and the proof is complete.

Independent proof. To prove the inequality without using Fatou's lemma, we need some extra machinery. Denote the set of simple -measurable functions such that on .

Step 3. Given a simple function and a real number , define

Then , , and .

Step 3a. To prove the first claim, let , for some finite collection of pairwise disjoint measurable sets such that , some (finite) non-negative constants , and denoting the indicator function of the set . Then

.

Since the pre-image of the Borel set under the measurable function is measurable, and -algebras, by definition, are closed under finite intersection and unions, the first claim follows.

Step 3b. To prove the second claim, note that, for each and every ,

Step 3c. To prove the third claim, we show that .

Indeed, if, to the contrary, , then an element

exists such that , for every . Taking the limit as , get

.

But by initial assumption, . This is a contradiction.

Step 4. For every simple -measurable non-negative function ,

.

To prove this, define . By Lemma 1, is a measure on . By Lemma 2,

,

as required.

Step 5. We now prove that, for every ,

.

Indeed, using the definition of , the non-negativity of , and the monotonicity of Lebesgue integral, we have

,

for every . In accordance with Step 4, as , the inequality becomes

Taking the limit as yields

,

as required.

Step 6. We are now able to prove the reverse inequality, i.e.

.

Indeed, applying the definition of Lebesgue integral and the inequality established in Step 5, we have

,

as needed. The proof is complete.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ A generalisation of this theorem was given by Bibby, John (1974). "Axiomatisations of the average and a further generalisation of monotonic sequences". Glasgow Mathematical Journal. 15 (1): 63–65. doi:10.1017/S0017089500002135.
  2. ^ See for instance Yeh, J. (2006). Real Analysis: Theory of Measure and Integration. Hackensack, NJ: World Scientific. ISBN 981-256-653-8.
  3. ^ a b See for instance Schechter, Erik (1997). Handbook of Analysis and Its Foundations. San Diego: Academic Press. ISBN 0-12-622760-8.