Evidence of absence: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Undid revision 1051017722 by FRuDIxAFLG (talk) The lead is a summary of important points in the article. This is not in the article with this reference
Add section to main body of article expanding on conditional probability interpretation
Tags: Reverted Visual edit
Line 3: Line 3:
'''Evidence of absence''' is [[evidence]] of any kind that suggests something is missing or that it does not exist.
'''Evidence of absence''' is [[evidence]] of any kind that suggests something is missing or that it does not exist.


Per the traditional [[aphorism]], "Absence of evidence is not evidence of absence", positive evidence of this kind is distinct from a lack of evidence or ignorance<ref name="Turvey2008">{{cite book |first=B.E. |last=Turvey |year=2008 |title=Criminal Profiling: An Introduction to Behavioral Evidence Analysis |publisher=Elsevier |isbn=9780123741004 |lccn=2008274380 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Oge7LFaN5xYC&pg=PA267 |page=267}}</ref> of that which should have been found already, had it existed.<ref name="Martin2007">{{cite book |first=M. |last=Martin |year=2007 |title=The Cambridge Companion to Atheism |series=Cambridge Companions to Philosophy |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=9780521842709 |lccn=2006005949 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=tAeFipOVx4MC&pg=PA70 |page=70 |quote=[Advocates] of the presumption of atheism... insist that it is precisely the absence of evidence for theism that justifies their claim that God does not exist. The problem with such a position is captured neatly by the aphorism, beloved of forensic scientists, that "absence of evidence is not evidence of absence." The absence of evidence is evidence of absence only in case in which, were the postulated entity to exist, we should expect to have more evidence of its existence than we do.}}</ref>
Per the traditional [[aphorism]], "Absence of evidence is not evidence of absence", positive evidence of this kind is distinct from a lack of evidence or ignorance<ref name="Turvey2008">{{cite book |first=B.E. |last=Turvey |year=2008 |title=Criminal Profiling: An Introduction to Behavioral Evidence Analysis |publisher=Elsevier |isbn=9780123741004 |lccn=2008274380 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Oge7LFaN5xYC&pg=PA267 |page=267}}</ref> of that which should have been found already, had it existed.<ref name="Martin2007">{{cite book |first=M. |last=Martin |year=2007 |title=The Cambridge Companion to Atheism |series=Cambridge Companions to Philosophy |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=9780521842709 |lccn=2006005949 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=tAeFipOVx4MC&pg=PA70 |page=70 |quote=[Advocates] of the presumption of atheism... insist that it is precisely the absence of evidence for theism that justifies their claim that God does not exist. The problem with such a position is captured neatly by the aphorism, beloved of forensic scientists, that "absence of evidence is not evidence of absence." The absence of evidence is evidence of absence only in case in which, were the postulated entity to exist, we should expect to have more evidence of its existence than we do.}}</ref> However, when interpreted as a claim about [[Conditional probability|conditional probabilities]], absence of evidence generally ''is'' evidence of absence.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Stephens|first=Christopher Lee|date=2011-03-11|title=A Bayesian Approach to Absent Evidence Reasoning|url=https://informallogic.ca/index.php/informal_logic/article/view/2967|journal=Informal Logic|language=en|volume=31|issue=1|doi=10.22329/il.v31i1.2967|issn=2293-734X}}</ref>


==Overview==
==Overview==
Line 32: Line 32:
:2. ''a'', not yet observed, is an ''F''... [therefore]
:2. ''a'', not yet observed, is an ''F''... [therefore]
:3. The probability that ''a'' is ''G'' is ''p''.<ref name="sep-induction-problem">{{cite encyclopedia |first=John |last=Vickers |editor=Edward N. Zalta |year=2011 |title=The Problem of Induction |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |edition=Fall 2011 |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/induction-problem#WhaPro}}</ref>|John Vickers|"The Problem of Induction" in ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy''}}
:3. The probability that ''a'' is ''G'' is ''p''.<ref name="sep-induction-problem">{{cite encyclopedia |first=John |last=Vickers |editor=Edward N. Zalta |year=2011 |title=The Problem of Induction |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |edition=Fall 2011 |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/induction-problem#WhaPro}}</ref>|John Vickers|"The Problem of Induction" in ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy''}}

== Conditional probability ==
Suppose a hypothesis <math>H</math> and evidence <math>E</math> are events in a probability space. If <math>\Pr(H \mid E) > \Pr(H)</math> (meaning that observing <math>E</math> increases our confidence in <math>H</math>), then the absence of <math>E</math> should reduce our confidence in <math>H</math>, as shown by the following proof:
:<math>
\begin{align}
\Pr(H)
&= \Pr(H \mid E)\Pr(E) + \Pr(H \mid \neg E)\Pr(\neg E) \\
&> \Pr(H)\Pr(E) + \Pr(H \mid \neg E)\Pr(\neg E) \\
\Pr(H)\bigl(1 - \Pr(E)\bigr)
&> \Pr(H \mid \neg E)\Pr(\neg E) \\
\Pr(H)\Pr(\neg E) &> \Pr(H \mid \neg E)\Pr(\neg E) \\
\Pr(H) &> \Pr(H \mid \neg E)
\end{align}
</math>
In order for this proof to work, the probability of <math>E</math> must be strictly between 0 and 1.

Probabilistic reasoning of this sort is particularly important in legal disputes. For example, a jury can be swayed by "evidentiary lacunae", or a lack of evidence they expect to hear.<ref>{{Citation|last=Tuzet|first=Giovanni|title=On the Absence of Evidence|date=2015|url=https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-16148-8_3|work=Argument Types and Fallacies in Legal Argumentation|pages=37–51|editor-last=Bustamante|editor-first=Thomas|series=Law and Philosophy Library|place=Cham|publisher=Springer International Publishing|language=en|doi=10.1007/978-3-319-16148-8_3|isbn=978-3-319-16148-8|access-date=2021-10-21|editor2-last=Dahlman|editor2-first=Christian}}</ref>


==Proving a negative==
==Proving a negative==

Revision as of 23:44, 21 October 2021

Evidence of absence is evidence of any kind that suggests something is missing or that it does not exist.

Per the traditional aphorism, "Absence of evidence is not evidence of absence", positive evidence of this kind is distinct from a lack of evidence or ignorance[1] of that which should have been found already, had it existed.[2] However, when interpreted as a claim about conditional probabilities, absence of evidence generally is evidence of absence.[3]

Overview

The difference between evidence that something is absent (e.g., an observation that suggests there were no dragons here today) and simple absence of evidence (e.g., no careful research has been done) can be nuanced. Indeed, scientists will often debate whether an experiment's result should be considered evidence of absence, or if it remains absence of evidence. The debate regards whether the experiment would have detected the phenomenon of interest if it were there.[4]

The argument from ignorance for "absence of evidence" is not necessarily fallacious, for example, that a potentially life-saving new drug poses no long-term health risk unless proved otherwise. On the other hand, were such an argument to rely imprudently on the lack of research to promote its conclusion, it would be considered an informal fallacy whereas the former can be a persuasive way to shift the burden of proof in an argument or debate.[5] Carl Sagan criticized such "impatience with ambiguity" with cosmologist Martin Rees' maxim, "Absence of evidence is not evidence of absence".[6][7]

An exhaustive inspection of the attic for vermin can provide evidence of absence, but any sign of mice will always suffice to the contrary.

In carefully designed scientific experiments, even null results can be evidence of absence. For instance, a hypothesis may be falsified if a vital predicted observation is not found empirically. (At this point, the underlying hypothesis may be rejected or revised and sometimes, additional ad hoc explanations may even be warranted.) Whether the scientific community will accept a null result as evidence of absence depends on many factors, including the detection power of the applied methods, the confidence of the inference, as well as confirmation bias within the community.

Proof and evidence

The Pyrrhonian skeptic, Sextus Empiricus, questioned the apodicticity of inductive reasoning because a universal rule cannot be established from an incomplete set of particular instances: "When they propose to establish the universal from the particulars by means of induction, they will effect this by a review of either all or some of the particulars. But if they review some, the induction will be insecure, since some of the particulars omitted in the induction may contravene the universal; while if they are to review all, they will be toiling at the impossible, since the particulars are infinite and indefinite".[8]

Until about the middle of the previous century induction was treated as a quite specific method of inference: inference of a universal affirmative proposition (All swans are white) from its instances (a is a white swan, b is a white swan, etc.) The method had also a probabilistic form, in which the conclusion stated a probabilistic connection between the properties in question... The Oxford English Dictionary defines “induction”, in the sense relevant here, as follows: "[The] process of inferring a general law or principle from the observation of particular instances..."

[Much] of what contemporary epistemology, logic, and the philosophy of science count as induction infers neither from observation nor from particulars and does not lead to general laws or principles. [Induction] was understood to be what we now know as enumerative induction or universal inference; inference from particular instances:

a1, a2, …, an are all Fs that are also G... [to a general law or principle] All Fs are G.

A weaker form of enumerative induction, singular predictive inference, leads not to a generalization but to a singular prediction:

1. a1, a2, …, an are all Fs that are also G.
2. an+1 is also F... [therefore]
3. an+1 is also G.

Singular predictive inference also has a more general probabilistic form:

1. The proportion p of observed Fs have also been Gs.
2. a, not yet observed, is an F... [therefore]
3. The probability that a is G is p.[9]
— John Vickers, "The Problem of Induction" in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Conditional probability

Suppose a hypothesis and evidence are events in a probability space. If (meaning that observing increases our confidence in ), then the absence of should reduce our confidence in , as shown by the following proof:

In order for this proof to work, the probability of must be strictly between 0 and 1.

Probabilistic reasoning of this sort is particularly important in legal disputes. For example, a jury can be swayed by "evidentiary lacunae", or a lack of evidence they expect to hear.[10]

Proving a negative

A negative claim is a colloquialism for an affirmative claim that asserts the non-existence or exclusion of something.[11] Claiming that it is impossible to prove a negative is a pseudologic, because there are many proofs that substantiate negative claims in mathematics, science, and economics, including Euclid's theorem, which proves that there is no largest prime number, and Arrow's impossibility theorem.[citation needed] There can be multiple claims within a debate, nevertheless, whoever makes a claim carries the burden of proof regardless of positive or negative content in the claim.[citation needed]

A negative claim may or may not exist as a counterpoint to a previous claim. A proof of impossibility or an evidence of absence argument are typical methods to fulfill the burden of proof for a negative claim.[11][12]

Philosopher Steven Hales argues that typically one can logically be as confident with the negation of an affirmation. Hales says that if one's standards of certainty leads them to say "there is never 'proof' of non-existence", then they must also say that "there is never 'proof' of existence either". Hales argues that there are many cases where we may be able to prove something does not exist with as much certainty as proving something does exist.[11]: 109–112 

See also

References

  1. ^ Turvey, B.E. (2008). Criminal Profiling: An Introduction to Behavioral Evidence Analysis. Elsevier. p. 267. ISBN 9780123741004. LCCN 2008274380.
  2. ^ Martin, M. (2007). The Cambridge Companion to Atheism. Cambridge Companions to Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. p. 70. ISBN 9780521842709. LCCN 2006005949. [Advocates] of the presumption of atheism... insist that it is precisely the absence of evidence for theism that justifies their claim that God does not exist. The problem with such a position is captured neatly by the aphorism, beloved of forensic scientists, that "absence of evidence is not evidence of absence." The absence of evidence is evidence of absence only in case in which, were the postulated entity to exist, we should expect to have more evidence of its existence than we do.
  3. ^ Stephens, Christopher Lee (2011-03-11). "A Bayesian Approach to Absent Evidence Reasoning". Informal Logic. 31 (1). doi:10.22329/il.v31i1.2967. ISSN 2293-734X.
  4. ^ Schreuder, Duco A. (2014). Vision and Visual Perception The Conscious Base of Seeing. p. 105.
  5. ^ Walton, Douglas (1992). "Nonfallacious arguments from ignorance" (PDF). American Philosophical Quarterly: 381–387. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  6. ^ Altman, Douglas G; Bland, J Martin (1995). "Absence of evidence is not evidence of absence". British Medical Journal. 311 (19 August): 485. doi:10.1136/bmj.311.7003.485. PMC 2550545. PMID 7647644.
  7. ^ Sagan, Carl (1997). The Demon-Haunted World: Science as a Candle in the Dark (1st ed.). New York: Ballantine. p. 213. ISBN 0-345-40946-9. OCLC 32855551. Appeal to ignorance—the claim that whatever has not been proved false must be true, and vice versa (e.g., There is no compelling evidence that UFOs are not visiting the Earth; therefore UFOs exist—and there is intelligent life elsewhere in the Universe. Or: There may be seventy kazillion other worlds, but not one is known to have the moral advancement of the Earth, so we're still central to the Universe.) This impatience with ambiguity can be criticized in the phrase: absence of evidence is not evidence of absence.
  8. ^ Sextus Empiricus. Outlines of Pyrrhonism trans. R.G. Bury (Loeb edition) (London: W. Heinemann, 1933), p. 283.
  9. ^ Vickers, John (2011). "The Problem of Induction". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2011 ed.).
  10. ^ Tuzet, Giovanni (2015), Bustamante, Thomas; Dahlman, Christian (eds.), "On the Absence of Evidence", Argument Types and Fallacies in Legal Argumentation, Law and Philosophy Library, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 37–51, doi:10.1007/978-3-319-16148-8_3, ISBN 978-3-319-16148-8, retrieved 2021-10-21
  11. ^ a b c Hales, Steven D. (Summer 2005). "Thinking tools: You can prove a negative" (PDF). Think. 4 (10). Cambridge University Press: 109–112. doi:10.1017/S1477175600001287.
  12. ^ Damer, T. Edward (2009). Attacking faulty reasoning: a practical guide to fallacy-free arguments. Cengage Learning. p. 17. ISBN 9780495095064.