A Natural History of Rape: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Yobot (talk | contribs)
m clean up / updated infobox parameters using AWB (8976)
+ wilson et al.
Line 23: Line 23:
Psychology professor [[Frans de Waal]] argues that rape involves both sex and violence, and that while ''A Natural History of Rape'' serves as a corrective to the dogmatic view that rape is primarily about power, its view that rape is primarily sexually motivated is equally dogmatic. In de Waal's view, Thornhill and Palmer's theory could only be true if men who rape differ genetically from men who do not rape and sire more children than they could without committing rape, and there is no evidence that either of these things is true. He believes Thornhill and Palmer wrongly describe premature ejaculation as a rape adaptation, when other explanations for it exist.<ref>http://www.nytimes.com/books/00/04/02/reviews/000402.002waalt.html</ref>
Psychology professor [[Frans de Waal]] argues that rape involves both sex and violence, and that while ''A Natural History of Rape'' serves as a corrective to the dogmatic view that rape is primarily about power, its view that rape is primarily sexually motivated is equally dogmatic. In de Waal's view, Thornhill and Palmer's theory could only be true if men who rape differ genetically from men who do not rape and sire more children than they could without committing rape, and there is no evidence that either of these things is true. He believes Thornhill and Palmer wrongly describe premature ejaculation as a rape adaptation, when other explanations for it exist.<ref>http://www.nytimes.com/books/00/04/02/reviews/000402.002waalt.html</ref>


''Evolution, Gender, and Rape'', a 2003 book written in response to ''A Natural History of Rape'', compiles the views of twenty-eight scholars opposed to sociobiological theories of rape. One contributor, Michael Kimmel, criticizes Thornhill and Palmer's argument that female rape victims tend to be sexually attractive young women, rather than children or older women, contrary to what would be expected if rapists selected victims based on inability to resist. Kimmel argues that younger women are the least likely to be married and the most likely to be out on dates with men, and therefore are the most likely to be raped because of opportunity arising from social exposure and marital status.<ref>{{cite book|title=Evolution, Gender, and Rape|isbn=0-262-20143-7|publisher=Massachusetts Institute of Technology|year=2003|editor=Travis, Cheryl Brown|author=Kimmel, Michael|chapter=An Unnatural History of Rape|pages=228}}</ref> Palmer and Thornhill responded in an article in the journal ''Evolutionary Psychology''.<ref>{{cite web|last=Palmer, Craig T., & Thornhill, Randy (2003)|title=A posse of good citizens bring outlaw evolutionists to justice|url=http://www.epjournal.net/filestore/ep011027.pdf|publisher=Evolutionary Psychology 1, p. 10-27}}</ref>
''Evolution, Gender, and Rape'', a 2003 book written in response to ''A Natural History of Rape'', compiles the views of twenty-eight scholars opposed to sociobiological theories of rape. One contributor, [[Michael Kimmel]], criticizes Thornhill and Palmer's argument that female rape victims tend to be sexually attractive young women, rather than children or older women, contrary to what would be expected if rapists selected victims based on inability to resist. Kimmel argues that younger women are the least likely to be married and the most likely to be out on dates with men, and therefore are the most likely to be raped because of opportunity arising from social exposure and marital status.<ref>{{cite book|title=Evolution, Gender, and Rape|isbn=0-262-20143-7|publisher=Massachusetts Institute of Technology|year=2003|editor=Travis, Cheryl Brown|author=Kimmel, Michael|chapter=An Unnatural History of Rape|pages=228}}</ref> Palmer and Thornhill responded in an article in the journal ''Evolutionary Psychology''.<ref>{{cite web|last=Palmer, Craig T., & Thornhill, Randy (2003)|title=A posse of good citizens bring outlaw evolutionists to justice|url=http://www.epjournal.net/filestore/ep011027.pdf|publisher=Evolutionary Psychology 1, p. 10-27}}</ref>

Wilson et al. (2003) argue that Thornhill and Palmer use the [[naturalistic fallacy]] inappropriately to forestall legitimate discussion about the ethical implications of their theory. According to Thornhill and Palmer, a naturalistic fallacy is to infer ethical conclusions (e.g., rape is good) from (true or false) statements of fact (e.g., rape is natural). Wilson et al. point out that combining a factual statement with an ethical statement to derive an ethical conclusion is standard ethical reasoning, not a naturalistic fallacy, because the moral judgment is not deduced ''exclusively'' from the factual statement. They further argue that if one combines Thornhill and Palmer's factual premise that rape increases the fitness of a woman's offspring with the ethical premise that it is right to increase fitness of offspring, the resulting deductively valid conclusion is that rape has also positive effects and that its ethical status is ambiguous. Wilson et al. state that Thonhill and Palmer dismiss all ethical objections with the phrase 'naturalistic fallacy' although "it is Thornhill and Palmer who are thinking fallaciously by using the naturalistic fallacy in this way."<ref name="wilson2003">{{cite journal |last1= Wilson |first1= David Sloan |last2= Dietrich |first2= Eric |last3= Clark |first3= Anne B. |year= 2003 |title= On the inappropriate use of the naturalistic fallacy in evolutionary psychology |journal= Biology and Philosophy |volume= 18 |issue= 5 |pages= 669&ndash;681 |publisher= |doi= 10.1023/A:1026380825208 |url= http://evolution.binghamton.edu/dswilson/wp-content/uploads/2010/01/DSW14.pdf |accessdate= March 23, 2013}}</ref>


==See also==
==See also==

Revision as of 18:02, 27 March 2013

A Natural History of Rape: Biological Bases of Sexual Coercion
The 2000 MIT Press edition
AuthorRandy Thornhill, Craig T. Palmer
CountryUnited States
LanguageEnglish
GenreEvolutionary psychology
PublisherThe MIT Press
Publication date
2000
Media typePrint
Pages251
ISBN0-262-20125-9

A Natural History of Rape: Biological Bases of Sexual Coercion is a 2000 book about rape by biologist Randy Thornhill and anthropologist Craig T. Palmer. It proposes that rape should be understood through evolutionary psychology,[1] and criticizes the argument, popularized by Susan Brownmiller's Against Our Will, that rape is not sexually motivated.[2] Thornhill and Palmer believe that the capacity for rape is either an adaptation or a byproduct of adaptative traits such as sexual desire and aggressiveness.[1]

The argument

The book argues that rape should be understood through evolutionary psychology, and that the capacity for rape is either an adaptation or a byproduct of adaptative traits such as sexual desire and aggressiveness, which have evolved for reasons that have no direct connection with the benefits or costs of rape.[1] Thornhill and Palmer criticize Brownmiller's Against Our Will, which popularized the view that rape is an expression of male domination that is not sexually motivated. They criticize arguments that rape is not sexually motivated on several grounds.[2] In their view, concluding that rape must be motivated by the desire to commit acts of violence because it involves force or the threat of force is as illogical as concluding that men who pay prostitutes for sex are motivated by charity.[1]

Scholarly reception

Thornhill and Palmer's hypothesis is controversial.[3] The authors added a new preface replying to critics of their book in the second edition of A Natural History of Rape published in 2001,[4] and have claimed that some of the criticism it has received consists of straw man arguments, contradictions, and flawed logic.[5]

Psychology professor Frans de Waal argues that rape involves both sex and violence, and that while A Natural History of Rape serves as a corrective to the dogmatic view that rape is primarily about power, its view that rape is primarily sexually motivated is equally dogmatic. In de Waal's view, Thornhill and Palmer's theory could only be true if men who rape differ genetically from men who do not rape and sire more children than they could without committing rape, and there is no evidence that either of these things is true. He believes Thornhill and Palmer wrongly describe premature ejaculation as a rape adaptation, when other explanations for it exist.[6]

Evolution, Gender, and Rape, a 2003 book written in response to A Natural History of Rape, compiles the views of twenty-eight scholars opposed to sociobiological theories of rape. One contributor, Michael Kimmel, criticizes Thornhill and Palmer's argument that female rape victims tend to be sexually attractive young women, rather than children or older women, contrary to what would be expected if rapists selected victims based on inability to resist. Kimmel argues that younger women are the least likely to be married and the most likely to be out on dates with men, and therefore are the most likely to be raped because of opportunity arising from social exposure and marital status.[7] Palmer and Thornhill responded in an article in the journal Evolutionary Psychology.[8]

Wilson et al. (2003) argue that Thornhill and Palmer use the naturalistic fallacy inappropriately to forestall legitimate discussion about the ethical implications of their theory. According to Thornhill and Palmer, a naturalistic fallacy is to infer ethical conclusions (e.g., rape is good) from (true or false) statements of fact (e.g., rape is natural). Wilson et al. point out that combining a factual statement with an ethical statement to derive an ethical conclusion is standard ethical reasoning, not a naturalistic fallacy, because the moral judgment is not deduced exclusively from the factual statement. They further argue that if one combines Thornhill and Palmer's factual premise that rape increases the fitness of a woman's offspring with the ethical premise that it is right to increase fitness of offspring, the resulting deductively valid conclusion is that rape has also positive effects and that its ethical status is ambiguous. Wilson et al. state that Thonhill and Palmer dismiss all ethical objections with the phrase 'naturalistic fallacy' although "it is Thornhill and Palmer who are thinking fallaciously by using the naturalistic fallacy in this way."[9]

See also

References

  1. ^ a b c d LeVay, Simon and Baldwin, Janice (2009). Human Sexuality, Third edition. Sinauer Associates, Inc. pp. 598, 602. ISBN 978-0-87893-424-9.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  2. ^ a b Thornhill, Randy & Palmer, Craig T. A Natural History of Rape: Biological Bases of Sexual Coercion. The MIT Press, 2000, pp. 126, 133-135, 138-139.
  3. ^ Coyne, Jerry (9 March 2000). "Rape as an adaptation". Nature. 404 (6774): 121–122. doi:10.1038/35004636. {{cite journal}}: Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help)
  4. ^ http://mitpress.mit.edu/catalog/item/default.asp?ttype=2&tid=8666
  5. ^ Palmer, Craig T. & Thornhill, Randy (2003). "Straw men and fairy tales: Evaluating reactions to a natural history of rape". Journal of Sex Research. 40 (3): pages 249–255. doi:10.1080/00224490309552189. {{cite journal}}: |pages= has extra text (help)CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  6. ^ http://www.nytimes.com/books/00/04/02/reviews/000402.002waalt.html
  7. ^ Kimmel, Michael (2003). "An Unnatural History of Rape". In Travis, Cheryl Brown (ed.). Evolution, Gender, and Rape. Massachusetts Institute of Technology. p. 228. ISBN 0-262-20143-7.
  8. ^ Palmer, Craig T., & Thornhill, Randy (2003). "A posse of good citizens bring outlaw evolutionists to justice" (PDF). Evolutionary Psychology 1, p. 10-27.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link) CS1 maint: numeric names: authors list (link)
  9. ^ Wilson, David Sloan; Dietrich, Eric; Clark, Anne B. (2003). "On the inappropriate use of the naturalistic fallacy in evolutionary psychology" (PDF). Biology and Philosophy. 18 (5): 669–681. doi:10.1023/A:1026380825208. Retrieved March 23, 2013.

External links