Jump to content

Coercion: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Wouldgyro (talk | contribs)
No edit summary
Mobius Bot (talk | contribs)
m ALL YOUR PAGE ARE BELONG TO US.
Line 1: Line 1:
ALL YOUR PAGE ARE BELONG TO US. RESISTANCE IS FUTILE.
{{otheruses}}
{{cleanup|date=March 2009}}
{{Citations missing|article|date=May 2008}}

'''Coercion''' ({{pron-en|koʊˈɜrʃən}}) is the practice of forcing another party to behave in an involuntary manner (whether through action or inaction) by use of threats, [[intimidation]] or some other form of pressure or force. Such actions are used as leverage, to force the victim to act in the desired way. Coercion may involve the actual infliction of physical pain/injury or psychological harm in order to enhance the [[credibility]] of a threat. The threat of further harm may lead to the [[co-operation|cooperation]] or [[obedience]] of the person being coerced. [[Torture]] is one of the most extreme examples of coercion i.e. severe pain is inflicted until the victim provides the desired information.

==Overview==
Any person’s set of feasible choices is obtained from the combination of two elements: the ''initial endowment'' (the perceived initial state of the world, which the chosen actions are going to affect) and the ''transformation rules'' (which state how any chosen action will change the initial endowment, according to the person’s perception).

This follows that coercion could take place by purposely manipulating either the transformation rules or the initial endowment (or both is maximised). Yet, the purpose of coercion is to substitute one’s aims to those of the victim. For this reason, many social philosophers have considered coercion as the polar opposite to [[Political freedom|freedom]].

Various forms of coercion are distinguished: first on the basis of the ''kind of injury'' threatened, second according to its ''aims'' and ''scope'', and finally according to its ''effects'', from which its legal, social, and ethical implications mostly depend.

==Means==
Looking at the content of the threat, one can distinguish between physical, psychological and economic coercion.

===Physical===
{{Wiktionarypar|at gunpoint|at knifepoint}}
Physical coercion is the most commonly considered form of coercion, where the content of the conditional threat is the use of force against a victim, their dear ones or property. An often used example is "putting a gun to someone's head" ('''at gunpoint''') or putting a "knife under the throat" ('''at knifepoint''' or cut-throat) to compel action. These are so common that they are also used as metaphors for other forms of coercion.

Armed forces in many countries use [[firing squad]]s to maintain [[discipline]] and intimidate the masses, or opposition, into submission or silent compliance. However, there also are nonphysical forms of coercion, where the threatened injury does not immediately imply the use of force. Byman and Waxman (2000) define coercion as "the use of threatened force, including the limited use of actual force to back up the threat, to induce an adversary to behave differently than it otherwise would."<ref>Byman, Daniel L.; Waxman, Matthew C.: ''Kosovo and the Great Air Power Debate'', ''[[International Security]], Vol. 24, No. 4 (Spring, 2000), pp. 5-38.</ref> However, coercion does not necessarily amount to destruction.

===Psychological===
In psychological coercion, the threatened injury regards the victim’s relationships with other people. The most obvious example is ''[[blackmail]]'', where the threat consists of the dissemination of damaging information. However, many other types are possible e.g. so-called "[[emotional blackmail]]", which typically involves threats of rejection from or disapproval by a peer-group, or creating feelings of guilt/obligation via a display of anger or hurt by someone whom the victim loves or respects. Another example is [[coercive persuasion]]. Government agencies may use highly intimidating methods during investigations e.g. the threat of harsh legal penalties. The usual incentive to cooperate is some form of [[plea bargain]] i.e. an offer to drop or reduce criminal charges against a suspect in return for full cooperation.

Psychological coercion – along with the other varieties - was extensively and systematically used by the government of the [[People’s Republic of China]] during the “Thought Reform” campaign of 1951-1952. The process – carried out partly at “revolutionary universities” and partly within prisons – was investigated and reported upon by [[Robert Jay Lifton]], then Research Professor of Psychiatry at Yale University: see Lifton (1961). The techniques used by the Chinese authorities included a technique derived from standard [[group psychotherapy]], which was aimed at forcing the victims (who were generally intellectuals) to produce detailed and sincere ideological “confessions”. For instance, a professor of [[formal logic]] called Chin Yueh-lin – who was then regarded as China’s leading authority on his subject – was induced to write: “The new philosophy [of [[Marxism-Leninism]]], being scientific, is the supreme truth”. [Lifton (1961) p.&nbsp;545].

====Usage====
Some people speak of '''cultural coercion''' when the fear of falling out with the group may force people into wearing a certain style of dress, publicly reciting a [[creed]] or a pledge of allegiance which they find ethically reprehensible or starting to smoke when they would have preferred not to etc. Within the definitional framework adopted here, all such things amount to (psychological) coercion if and only if the fear of falling out with the group is the result of ''purposeful'' threats by someone. See [[Peer pressure]], [[Sociology of religion]], [[Pledge of Allegiance]].

Some people include [[deception]] in their definition of (psychological) coercion. Yet deception does not generally involve ''any'' threat at all, as it works by creating a mere ''false perception'' by the victim of his or her ''given'' transformation rules. Although its effects may sometimes be very similar to those of a conditional threat, it may hence be useful to treat deception as separate phenomenon.

==Aims==
The aims of coercion can vary widely from totally "selfish" to totally ''altruistic'' ones: from attempts to gain personal wealth and power at the expense of others to efforts aimed at inflating ones own ego under the pretext of 'saving other people’s souls'{{or}}.

===Predatory===
The purely selfish kinds of coercion are a form of predatory behaviour by the coercing party, whose aim is to narrow down the scope of other people’s actions so as to make them instrumental to its own personal interests. According to many social philosophers, this sort of predatory behaviour will become the prevailing one{{citation needed|date=October 2010}}.

===Pedagogic and thought===
At the other extreme of the spectrum one finds attempts to use coercion altruistically, as a pedagogical device to improve – in some supposedly objective sense – the way other people ''think'', with particular regard to their basic attitudes and values. Pedagogic coercion may be applied within a strictly educational context, and it is then mostly directed towards children. In this article, however, attention will focus on ''thought coercion'', i.e. the attempt to use coercion to affect the basic values of grown-up people in general.

In all forms of ''thought coercion'' the immediate objective is to force other people to act ''as if'' their basic choice rules were identical to those of the coercing party. However, this mere conformity of “outward” behaviour is but a first step. The true and final aim of thought coercion is to induce a change in the victim’s objective function itself, i.e. the basic set of values and rules by which the victim determines his or her own choice among the alternatives of ''any'' feasible set. Thought coercion is thus generally meant to be only ''temporary''. Once the desired change in values has been brought about, the victim is expected to conform spontaneously, without any need for further coercion.

Whether and under what conditions this final aim can in fact be stably achieved is a difficult question, and it will be considered in the section devoted to the effects of coercion. Here it is necessary to point out that, whatever its effectiveness, thought coercion has in fact been used very extensively throughout history.

====Ideological====
''Ideological coercion'' is the use of thought coercion in the attempt to modify people’s [[social philosophy|social]] and [[political philosophy]]. This is of course quite different from plain propaganda, or even the simple persecution of political opponents, because its objective is to force individual ideological conversions. Unlike religious coercion, it is a quite recent phenomenon, confined to some of the [[totalitarian]] regimes of the twentieth century.

The most notable example of ideological coercion was the already mentioned Chinese “Thought Reform” campaign of 1951-52, which was unique due to both thoroughness and number of people involved. Yet, it must be noted that Chinese authorities found it necessary to follow that up with a new, albeit slightly milder, campaign as part of the [[Maoist]] “Cultural Revolution” of 1966-1968.

Starting from the political purges in the [[Soviet Union]] during the Thirties, similar “brainwashing” techniques were intermittently and less systematically used by most [[Stalinist]] regimes of the twentieth century. By contrast, the [[Fascist]] and [[Nazism|Nazi]] regimes of [[Italy]] and [[Germany]] tended to confine their coercive activities to purely [[political]] aims, without any serious attempt to force the ideological conversion of their opponents. The use of (physical) ideological coercion was however theorised by some Fascist philosophers, like [[Giovanni Gentile]] and Jared Harfield.

===Disciplinary===
Somewhere in the middle between predatory and pedagogic coercion one finds the forms of coercion that are used as the main coordination tools of command systems. These are organisations that use coercion to enforce on their members patterns of division of labour aimed at reaching the organisation’s goals, which for a variety of reasons may not always be consistent with each member’s personal aims. The most typical example of a command system is a military organisation, which is typically called a government, but any large production team may easily fall into this category.

Through the punishment system of disciplinary coercion, each individual member is typically forced into altruistic behaviour in the interest of the whole group. This is why this kind of coercion is not predatory, and – unlike thought coercion – may often be accepted in advance by the members of the group.

==Scope==
The scope of coercion has to do with who uses a conditional threat against whom. It is closely linked with some of the other aspects already surveyed above, and may be of paramount importance in determining coercion’s effects and implications.

===Specific===
Specific or ''personal'' coercion is the most commonly considered kind. It takes place when the conditional threat is decided upon by one particular individual or small group, and/or directed against some other individual or small group. All forms of predatory and thought coercion fall into this category.

===Unspecific===
Under unspecific or ''impersonal'' coercion the conditional threats come from well-known and socially accepted general rules and – rather than any individual or sub-group – and are directed against anybody in the stated conditions, according to clearly stated principles of due process. In practice, the narrowing down of individual choice may be here principally aimed at reducing the incidence of specific coercion, rather than forcing on everybody some special sub-set of positive goals. More generally, unspecific coercion may be the form taken by disciplinary coercion, and this appears to be in fact the case within the most effective command systems of the modern world.

Unspecific coercion is thus the same thing as the [[rule of law]] in its widest sense. This must not however be confused with the ''monopoly of coercion by the State''. First, State coercion may very easily be arbitrary – indeed technically very ''specific'', according to the above definition. Second, there are well-documented historical examples of (small) societies that have practiced unspecific coercion ''without'' the help of State institutions – like [[Iceland]] in the early [[Middle Ages]]. The identification between State and law is but a special ''normative'' principle introduced by (public) Roman law, which according to some, like [[Maitland]], was for this very reason to be treated as the quintessential “law of tyranny”.

somehow inspired by the “general will” should be entitled to enforce it through revolutionary coercion on the will of all. Later on, during the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, this French revolutionary principle – though not of course its specific way to identify the “general will” – percolated into first [[Socialist]] and then [[Fascist]] political thinking.

===Ethical effects regarding freedom===
To most people, the ethical implications of individual predatory coercion are straightforward. In recent times, some have attempted to extend a similar ethical judgement to non-predatory forms of coercion by individuals. Thus, for instance, the [[Taking Children Seriously]] movement has criticised pedagogic coercion by adults, including parents, on children, holding that it is possible and desirable to act with a child in such a way that all activities are consensual.

The ethical standing of wider forms of supposedly “altruistic” specific coercion – like political and thought coercion – is however much more controversial, along lines relating to the assumed relationship between coercion and [[Free will|freedom]], which is often regarded as an ethical value in itself.

====Negation of freedom====
The Whig-liberal tradition has led to the well-known notion of (negative) freedom as lack of specific coercion. According to this view, any form of specific coercion is then unethical in itself as an injury to freedom, quite apart from its damaging effects on social progress. Indeed, the ethical value of (negative) freedom is grounded on the idea that conscience cannot be coerced, and is thus the ultimate standard of morality. It hence follows that – from an ethical point of view – coercion cannot even be regarded as a lesser evil: since it cannot produce conscientious behaviour, it can never bring about the fulfilment of ''any'' ethical value.

==See also==
*[[Fear mongering]]
*[[Mind control]]
*[[Brainwashing]]
*[[Propaganda]]
*[[Duress]]

==References==
{{reflist}}

*Anderson, Scott A. (undated), "Towards a Better Theory of Coercion, and a Use for It", The University of Chicago [http://ptw.uchicago.edu/Anderson02.pdf]
*Hayek, Friedrich A. (1960) ''The Constitution of Liberty'', University of Chicago Press.
*Hodgkin, Thomas (1886) (trans.) ''Letters of Cassiodorus'', London: H. Frowde.
*Lifton, Robert J. (1961) ''Thought Reform and the Psychology of Totalism'', Penguin Books.
*Popper, Karl R. (1945) ''The Open Society and Its Enemies''
*Rhodes, Michael R. (2000), "The Nature of Coercion", ''Journal of Value Inquiry'', 34 (2/3)
*Rothbard, Murray N. (1982), "F. A. Hayek and the Concept of Coercion", in ''The Ethics of Liberty'', Humanities Press [http://www.mises.org/rothbard/ethics/twentyeight.asp]

==External links==
*{{sep entry|coercion|Coercion|Scott Anderson}}.

{{Psychological manipulation}}

[[Category:Legal terms]]
[[Category:Liberalism]]
[[Category:Political theories]]
[[Category:Psychological abuse]]
[[Category:Social philosophy]]
[[Category:Warfare by type]]

[[da:Tvang]]
[[de:Nötigung]]
[[el:Εξαναγκασμός]]
[[es:Coerción]]
[[fa:اجبار]]
[[fr:Coercition]]
[[it:Coercizione]]
[[arz:ابتزاز سياسى]]
[[ja:強制]]
[[pt:Coerção]]
[[sr:Принуда]]
[[fi:Pakkovalta]]
[[sv:Tvång]]
[[tr:Baskı]]

Revision as of 12:54, 13 November 2010

ALL YOUR PAGE ARE BELONG TO US. RESISTANCE IS FUTILE.