Jump to content

Extended cognition: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
consciousness
m →‎top: fix typo
Line 7: Line 7:
:''Extended'' into the organism's environment.
:''Extended'' into the organism's environment.


This contrasts with the view of the mind as a processing center that creates mental representations of reality and uses them to control the body's behaviour. The field of extended cognition focuses upon the processes involved in this creation, and subsumes these processes as part of consciousness. which is no longer confined to the brain or body, but involves interaction with the environment. At a 'low' level, like [[motor learning]] and [[haptic perception]],<ref name=Morasso/> the body is involved in cognition, but there is a 'high' level where cultural factors play a role.<ref name=Ratner/><ref name=McGann/> This view of [[cognition]]is sometimes referred to as ''enaction'' to emphasise the role of interplay between the organism and its environment and the feedback processes involved in developing an awareness of, and a reformation of, the environment.<ref name=Stewart/>
This contrasts with the view of the mind as a processing center that creates mental representations of reality and uses them to control the body's behaviour. The field of extended cognition focuses upon the processes involved in this creation, and subsumes these processes as part of consciousness. which is no longer confined to the brain or body, but involves interaction with the environment. At a 'low' level, like [[motor learning]] and [[haptic perception]],<ref name=Morasso/> the body is involved in cognition, but there is a 'high' level where cultural factors play a role.<ref name=Ratner/><ref name=McGann/> This view of [[cognition]] is sometimes referred to as ''enaction'' to emphasise the role of interplay between the organism and its environment and the feedback processes involved in developing an awareness of, and a reformation of, the environment.<ref name=Stewart/>


==See also==
==See also==

Revision as of 23:24, 14 July 2014

Extended cognition is the view that mental processes and mind extend beyond the body to include aspects of the environment in which an organism is embedded and the organism's interaction with that environment.[1] Cognition goes beyond the manipulation of symbols to include the emergence of order and structure evolving from active engagement with the world.[2] As described by Rowlands, mental processes are:[3]

Embodied involving more than the brain, including a more general involvement of bodily structures and processes.
Embedded functioning only in a related external environment.
Enacted involving not only neural processes, but also things an organism does.
Extended into the organism's environment.

This contrasts with the view of the mind as a processing center that creates mental representations of reality and uses them to control the body's behaviour. The field of extended cognition focuses upon the processes involved in this creation, and subsumes these processes as part of consciousness. which is no longer confined to the brain or body, but involves interaction with the environment. At a 'low' level, like motor learning and haptic perception,[4] the body is involved in cognition, but there is a 'high' level where cultural factors play a role.[5][6] This view of cognition is sometimes referred to as enaction to emphasise the role of interplay between the organism and its environment and the feedback processes involved in developing an awareness of, and a reformation of, the environment.[7]

See also

Template:Multicol

Template:Multicol-break

Template:Multicol-end

References

  1. ^ Robert D Rupert (August 2004). "Challenges to the Hypothesis of Extended Cognition" (PDF). The Journal of Philosophy. 101 (8): 389–428.
  2. ^ Tim van Gelder (1999). "Chapter 8: Wooden Iron? Husserlian Phenomenology Meets Cognitive Science". In Jean Petitot, Francisco J Varela, Bernard Pachoud, Jean-Michel Roy, eds (ed.). Naturalizing Phenomenology: Issues in Contemporary Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Stanford University Press. p. 252. ISBN 978-0804736107. {{cite book}}: |editor= has generic name (help)CS1 maint: multiple names: editors list (link)
  3. ^ Mark Rowlands (2010). "Chapter 3: The mind embedded". The new science of the mind: From extended mind to embodied phenomenology. MIT Press. pp. 51 ff. ISBN 0262014556.
  4. ^ Pietro Morasso (2005). "Consciousness as the emergent property of the interaction between brain, body, & environment: the crucial role of haptic perception" (PDF). Slides related to a chapter on haptic perception (recognition through touch): Pietro Morasso (2007). "Chapter 14: The crucial role of haptic perception". In Antonio Chella & Riccardo Manzotti, eds (ed.). Artificial Consciousness. Academic. pp. 234–255. ISBN 978-1845400705. {{cite book}}: |editor= has generic name (help)
  5. ^ Carl Ratner (2011). Macro Cultural Psychology: A Political Philosophy of Mind. Oxford University Press. p. 96. ISBN 0199706298. Culture produces the mind; brain circuitry does not. The mind-body problem of how the physical body/brain produces mental, subjective qualia, is the wrong way to frame the origin of consciousness.
  6. ^ McGann, Marek; De Jaegher, Hanne; Di Paolo, Ezequiel (June 2013). "Enaction and psychology". Review of General Psychology. 17 (2): 203–209. doi:10.1037/a0032935.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  7. ^ John Stewart, Oliver Gapenne, Ezequiel A DiPaolo (2014). "Introduction". In John Stewart, Oliver Gapenne, Ezequiel A DiPaolo, eds (ed.). Enaction (Paperback ed.). MIT Press. p. vii. ISBN 978-0-262-52601-2. {{cite book}}: |editor= has generic name (help)CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)

Further reading

This article incorporates material from the Citizendium article "Extended cognition", which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 3.0 Unported License but not under the GFDL.