Jump to content

General will

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This is an old revision of this page, as edited by 24.105.152.153 (talk) at 19:42, 9 March 2009. The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.


The general will (volonté générale), made famous by Jean-Jacques Rousseau, is a concept in political philosophy referring to the desire or interest of a people as a whole, or, as the U.S. constitution puts it, the "general welfare". As used by Rousseau, the "general will" is identical to the rule of law[1], and to Spinoza's mens una.[2]

The notion of the general will is wholly central to Rousseau's theory of political legitimacy . . . . It is, however, an unfortunately obscure and controversial notion. Some commentators see it as no more than the dictatorship of the proletariat or the tyranny of the urban poor (such as may perhaps be seen in the French Revolution). Such was not Rousseau's meaning. This is clear from the Discourse on Political Economy, where Rousseau emphasizes that the general will exists to protect individuals against the mass, not to require them to be sacrificed to it. He is, of course, sharply aware that men have selfish and sectional interests which will lead them to try to oppress others. It is for this reason that loyalty to the good of all alike must be a supreme (although not exclusive) commitment by everyone, not only if a truly general will is to be heeded but also if it is to be formulated successfully in the first place".[3]

The phrase, "general will" as Rousseau intended it, occurs in Article 6 of the Declaration of the Rights of Man and the Citizen (French: Déclaration des droits de l'Homme et du citoyen), composed in 1789 during the French Revolution:

"The law is the expression of the general will. All citizens have the right to contribute personally, or through their representatives, to its formation. It must be the same for all, whether it protects or punishes. All citizens, being equal in its eyes, are equally admissible to all public dignities, positions, and employments, according to their capacities, an without any other distinction than that of their virtues and their talents." quoted in James Swenson, On Jean-Jacques Rousseau (Stanford University Press 2000), p. 163. In On Jean-Jacques Rousseau, James Swenson writes: "To my knowledge, the only time Rousseau actually uses the formulation "expression of the general will" is in a passage of the Discours sur l'économie politique, whose content renders it little susceptible of celebrity.. . . But it is indeed a faithful summary of his doctrine, faithful enough that commentators frequently adopt it without any hesitation. Among Rousseau's definitions of law, the textually closest variant can be found in a passage of the Lettres écrites de la montagne summarizing the argument of Du contrat social, in which law is defined as "a public and solemn declaration of the general will on an object of common interest." (Lettres de la montagne, pp. 807-808.) [4]


In 1952 Jacob Talmon characterized Rousseau's "general will" as leading to a Totalitarian Democracy because, Talmon argued, the state subjected its citizens to the supposedly infallible will of the tyranny of the majority. Another writer during the Cold War period, liberal theorist Karl Popper, also interpreted Rousseau in this way. Modern Rousseau scholars, however, such as his Rousseau's biographer and editor Maurice Cranston, and Ralph Leigh, editor of Rousseau's correspondence, to name a few, do not consider Talmon's 1950s "totalitarian thesis" as sustainable.[5]

It should be kept in mind that Rousseau was not alone among republican political theorists in thinking that small, homogeneous states were best suited to maintaining the freedom of their citizens. Montesquieu and Machiavelli were also of this opinion. Furthermore, Rousseau envisioned his Social Contract as as part of a projected larger work on political philosophy, which would have dealt with issues in larger states. Some of his later writings, such as his article on "Political Economy", his proposals for a Constitution of Poland, and his essay on maintaining perpetual peace, in which he recommends a federated European Union, give an idea of the future direction of his thought.

Rousseau is one of the great prose stylists and because of his penchant for the paradoxical effect obtained by stating something strongly and then going on to qualify or negate it, it is easy to misrepresent his ideas by taking them out of context.

Rousseau was also a great synthesizer who was deeply engaged in a dialog with his contemporaries and with the writers of the past, such as Hobbes and Grotius. The "general will" was a term of art and was not invented by Rousseau, though admittedly Rousseau did not acknowledge his debt to the jurists and theologians who influenced him. Prior to Rousseau, the phrase "general will" occurs in the theological writings of Malebranche (who had picked it up from Pascal) and in the writings of his Malebranche's pupil, Denis Diderot (in his Encyclopedie article on "Droit Naturel"). Diderot and Rousseau's innovation was to use the term in a secular rather than theological sense.


Quotations

"AS long as several men assembled together consider themselves as a single body, they have only one will which is directed towards their common preservation and general well-being. Then, all the animating forces of the state are vigorous and simple, and its principles are clear and luminous; it has no incompatible or conflicting interests; the common good makes itself so manifestly evident that only common sense is needed to discern it. Peace, unity and equality are the enemies of political sophistication. Upright and simple men are difficult to deceive precisely because of their simplicity; stratagems and clever arguments do not prevail upon them, they are not indeed subtle enough to be dupes. When we see among the happiest people in the world bands of peasants regulating the affairs of state under an oak tree, and always acting wisely, can we help feeling a certain contempt for the refinements of other nations, which employ so much skill and effort to make themselves at once illustrious and wretched?

A state thus governed needs very few laws ..."[6]

"However, when the social tie begins to slacken and the state to weaken, when particular interests begin to make themselves felt and sectional societies begin to exert an influence over the greater society, the common interest then becomes corrupted and meets opposition, voting is no longer unanimous; the general will is no longer the will of all; contradictions and disputes arises, and even the best opinion is not allowed to prevail unchallenged." [7]

"For this reason the sensible rule for regulating public assemblies is one intended not so much to uphold the general will there as to ensure that it is always questioned and always responds."[8]

Notes

  1. ^ See Maurice Cranston's introduction to the Social Contract, Penguin Classics, 1968, pp. 9-42.
  2. ^ for Spinoza's mens una, see Jonathan Israel, Radical Enlightenment (Oxford University Press, 2002), p. 274.
  3. ^ Entry, "Rousseau" in the Routelege Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward Craig, editor, Volume Eight, p. 371
  4. ^ Swenson (2000), p. 164. See also: Patrick Riley, The General Will before Rousseau (Princeton University Press, 1988) and Mark Hulliung "Rousseau, Voltaire and the Revenge of Pascal" in the Cambridge Companion to Rousseau, Patrick Riley, ed. (Cambridge University Press: 2000)pp. 57-77.
  5. ^ For a rejoinder to Talmon see R. A. Leigh, "Liberté et autorité dans le Contrat Social" in Jean-Jacques Rousseau et son oeuvre, (Paris, 1963).
  6. ^ Of the Social Contract, Book IV, Chapter 1, Paragraphs 1 & 2
  7. ^ (The Social Contract, Book IV, Chapter 1 Paragraph 5
  8. ^ Ibid. Ibid. Paragraph 7


See also

References