Against Empathy
Author | Paul Bloom |
---|---|
Genre | Nonfiction |
Published | 2016 (Ecco) |
ISBN | 978-0-06-233934-8 |
Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion is a 2016 book written by psychologist Paul Bloom. The book draws on the distinctions between empathy, compassion, and moral decision making. Bloom argues that empathy is not the solution to problems that divide people and is a poor guide for decision making. However, he is not completely against empathy; he believes that empathy can motivate kindness to make the world a better place.[1]
Overall, the book received mixed reviews as some reviewers critiqued Bloom's case "against empathy," maintaining their belief that empathy is a useful tool.[2]
Definition of Empathy
Paul Bloom defines empathy the way that Adam Smith describes sympathy in Theory of Moral Sentiments.[3] For Bloom, "[e]mpathy is the act of coming to experience the world as you think someone else does."[3] [emphasis in original] He describes empathy as "a spotlight directing attention and aid to where it's needed".[4] It is an emotion that people mistake as a moral guide for their decision making, and Bloom suggests it can blind morality. He explains that empathy is limiting because it directs people's attentions to individuals or individual events, which can misguide certain acts of kindness. Therefore, he suggests that we overcome the problems created by empathy through the use of "conscious, deliberative reasoning in everyday life".[5]
Powers and Limitations of Empathy
In the book, Bloom develops his case for "rational compassion" by discussing acts of kindness and altruism. Bloom believes that people "can make decisions based on considerations of cost and benefits".[6] He analyzes why and how people act altruistically and explains that oftentimes, empathy motivates people to act for self-serving reasons. Bloom also explores the neurological differences between feeling and understanding, which are central to demonstrating the limitations of empathy. He describes compassion the same way as Buddhist moral philosopher, Charles Goodman, defines Theravāda compassion in the book Consequences of Compassion: An Interpretation and Defense of Buddhist Ethics.[7][8][9] With this understanding, Bloom describes empathy as feeling what others feel whereas compassion is "simply caring for people, [and] wanting them to thrive".[10][11]
Empathy vs. Compassion
Bloom also explains C. Daniel Batson's study on "empathy-altruism hypothesis" which highlights empathy's biases. This hypothesis argues that people do acts of kindness due to empathy, but those acts may result in unintended consequences. Part of this is because people's moral evaluations of the people and events around them are what determine whether one feels empathy towards them.[12] For example, "you feel more empathy for someone who is cooperating with you than for someone you are in competition with."[13] It's the feeling of empathy that may influence people to do acts of kindness, or according to Bloom, acts of destruction. On the flip-side, low empathy can merit bad behavior.[citation needed]
To further his argument, Bloom describes effective altruism and its relationship with cost-benefit analysis decision making. He explains that rationalizing acts of kindness is a more effective guide for moral decisions than empathy. However, according to Bloom and a number of psychologists, people still make decisions using empathy without using rationality.[citation needed]
Rational Decision Making
Bloom finalizes the book by explaining how empathy is related to anger and evil. He explains how violence and anger can be products of empathy and that these things lead to evil. Evil, according to Bloom, is caused by dehumanization and objectification which are caused by empathy. In the same vein, Bloom explains that sometimes people commit evil acts in support of their morality, which can be blinded by empathy. The last chapter discusses concepts also touched in Daniel Kahneman's book, Thinking, Fast and Slow, that suggest people make a series of rational and irrational decisions.[14] He criticizes the argument that "regardless of reason's virtues, we just aren't any good at it".[15] His point is that people are not as "stupid as scholars think they are".[16]
He explains that people are rational because they make thoughtful decisions in their everyday lives. For example, when someone has to make a big life decision they critically assess the outcomes, consequences, and alternative options.[17] Ultimately, Bloom argues for a utilitarian approach to acts of altruism instead of empathy.[citation needed]
Reception
This book received mixed reviews.[citation needed] The New York Times questioned some of Bloom's assertions, but called the book "an overt, joyful conversation with readers."[18] The Guardian agreed with Bloom's case for rational compassion on the basis that that rational compassion was more valuable than empathy.[19]
See also
References
- ^ Bloom, Paul (2016). Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. Ecco. p. 240. ISBN 9780062339348.
- ^ Illing, Sean (2017-01-19). "The case against empathy". Vox. Retrieved 2019-10-15.
- ^ a b Bloom, Paul (2016). Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. Ecco. p. 16. ISBN 9780062339348.
- ^ Bloom, Paul (2016). Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. ECCO. p. 31. ISBN 9780062339348.
- ^ Bloom, Paul (2016). Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. Ecco. p. 5. ISBN 9780062339348.
- ^ Bloom, Paul (2016). Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. Ecco. p. 87. ISBN 9780062339348.
- ^ Gross, Rita (2010). "Review of Charles Goodman, Consequences of Compassion: An Interpretation and Defense of Buddhist Ethics". Sophia.
- ^ Goodman, Charles (2009). Consequences of Compassion: An Interpretation and Defense of Buddhist Ethics. 198 Madison Avenue, New York, New York 10016: Oxford University Press, Inc. p. 50. ISBN 9780195375190.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: location (link) - ^ Bloom, Paul (2016). Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. Ecco. p. 138. ISBN 9780062339348.
- ^ Bloom, Paul (2016). Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. Ecco. p. 16. ISBN 9780062339348.
- ^ Bloom, Paul (2016). Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. Ecco. p. 50. ISBN 9780062339348.
- ^ Bloom, Paul (2016). Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. Ecco. p. 70. ISBN 9780062339348.
- ^ Bloom, Paul (2016). Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. Ecco. p. 68. ISBN 9780062339348.
- ^ Bloom, Paul (2016). Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. Ecco. p. 214. ISBN 9780062339348.
- ^ Bloom, Paul. Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. 9680062339348. p. 216.
- ^ Bloom, Paul (2016). Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. Ecco. p. 216. ISBN 9780062339348.
- ^ Bloom, Paul (2016). Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. Ecco. p. 230. ISBN 9780062339348.
- ^ Senior, Jennifer (2016-12-06). "Review: 'Against Empathy,' or the Right Way to Feel Someone's Pain". The New York Times. ISSN 0362-4331. Retrieved 2019-11-01.
- ^ Vickers, Sally (2017). "Against Empathy by Paul Bloom; The Empathy Instinct by Peter Bazalgette - review". The Guardian.