Let I be an ideal of a fixed infinite set X, containing all finite subsets of X. We define the following "cardinal coefficients" of I:
.
The "additivity" of I is the smallest number of sets from I whose union is not in I any more. As any ideal is closed under finite unions, this number is always at least ; if I is a σ-ideal, then add(I)≥.
.
The "covering number" of I is the smallest number of sets from I whose union is all of X. As X itself is not in I, we must have add(I) ≤ cov(I).
,
The "uniformity number" of I (sometimes also written ) is the size of the smallest set not in I. By our assumption on I, add(I) ≤ non(I).
The "cofinality" of I is the cofinality of the partial order (I, ⊆). It is easy to see that we must have non(I) ≤ cof(I) and cov(I) ≤ cof(I).
where "" means: "there are infinitely many natural numbers n such that...", and "" means "for all except finitely many natural numbers n we have...".
Diagram
Let be the σ-ideal of those subsets of the real line which are meager (or "of the first category") in the euclidean topology, and let
be the σ-ideal of those subsets of the real line which are of Lebesgue measure zero. Then the following inequalities hold (where an arrow from a to b is to be read as meaning that a ≤ b):
It turns out that the inequalities described by the diagram, together with the relations mentioned above, are all the relations between these cardinals that are provable in ZFC, in the following sense. Let A be any assignment of the cardinals and to the 10 cardinals in Cichoń's diagram. Then, if A is consistent with the diagram in that there is no arrow from to , and if A also satisfies the two additional relations, then A can be realized in some model of ZFC.
Some inequalities in the diagram (such as "add ≤ cov") follow immediately from the definitions. The inequalities and
are classical theorems
and follow from the fact that the real line can be partitioned into a meager set and a set of measure zero.