Goodstein's theorem

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This is an old revision of this page, as edited by Trovatore (talk | contribs) at 07:05, 1 January 2006 (correct link for "undecidable"). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

In mathematical logic, Goodstein's theorem is a statement about the natural numbers that is undecidable in Peano arithmetic but can be proven to be true using the stronger axiom system of set theory, in particular using the axiom of infinity. The theorem states that every Goodstein sequence eventually terminates at 0. It stands as an example that not all undecidable theorems are peculiar or contrived, as those constructed by Gödel's incompleteness theorem are sometimes considered.

Definition of a Goodstein sequence

In order to define a Goodstein sequence, first define hereditary base-n notation. To write a natural number in hereditary base-n notation, first write it in the form , where each is an integer between 0 and n − 1; then break up each term into individual powers of n: becomes . Then write all the exponents k in hereditary base n notation, and continue recursively until every digit appearing in the expression is n or 0 - every non-exponent is n and every exponent in a tower of exponents is n or 0 (note that ).

For example, 35 in ordinary base-2 notation is , and in hereditary base-2 notation is

.

The Goodstein sequence on a number m, notated G(m), is defined as follows: the first element of the sequence is m. To get the next element, write m in hereditary base 2 notation, change all the 2's to 3's, and then subtract 1 from the result; this is the second element of G(m). To get the third element of G(m), write the previous number in hereditary base 3 notation, change all 3's to 4's, and subtract 1 again. Continue until the result is zero, at which point the sequence terminates.

Examples of Goodstein sequences

Early Goodstein sequences terminate quickly; for example G(3):

BaseHereditary notationValueNotes
2 21 + 1 3 The 1 represents 20.
3 31 + 1 − 1 = 3 3 Switch to 2 to a 3, then subtract 1
4 41 − 1 = 1 + 1 + 1 3 Switch the 3 to a 4, and subtract 1. Because the value to be expressed, 3, is less than 4, the representation switches from 41 to 40 + 40 + 40, or 1 + 1 + 1
5 1 + 1 + 1 − 1 = 1 + 1 2 Since each of the 1s represents 50, changing the base no longer has an effect. The sequence is now doomed to hit 0.
6 1 + 1 − 1 = 1 1
7 1 − 1 = 0 0

Many later Goodstein sequences increase for a very large number of steps. For example, G(4) starts as follows (in the second line, 2·32 is an abbreviation for and so in other cases) :

Hereditary notation Value
22 4
2·32 + 2·3 + 2 26
2·42 + 2·4 + 1 41
2·52 + 2·5 60
2·62 + 6 + 5 83
2·72 + 7 + 4 109
...
2·112 + 11 253
2·122 + 11 299
...

Elements of G(4) continue to increase for a while, but at base 3 · 2402653209, they reach the maximum of 3 · 2402653210 − 1, stay there for the next 3 · 2402653209 steps, and then begin their first and final descent.

The value 0 is reached at base 3 · 2402653211 − 1, which, curiously, is a Woodall number, just as all other final bases for starting values greater than 4. However, the example of G(4) doesn't give a good idea of just how quickly the elements of a Goodstein sequence can increase. G(19) increases much more rapidly, and starts as follows:

Hereditary notation Value
19
7625597484990
approximately 1.3 × 10154
approximately 1.8 × 102184
approximately 2.6 × 1036305
approximately 3.8 × 10695974

approximately 6 × 1015151335

approximately 4.3 × 10369693099
...

In spite of this rapid growth, Goodstein's theorem states that every Goodstein sequence eventually terminates at 0, no matter what the start value m is.

Proof

Goodstein's theorem can be proved (using techniques outside Peano arithmetic, see below) as follows: Given a Goodstein sequence G(m), we will construct a parallel sequence of ordinal numbers whose elements are no smaller than those in the given sequence. If the elements of the parallel sequence go to 0, the elements of the Goodstein sequence must also go to 0.

To construct the parallel sequence, take the hereditary base n representation of the (n − 1)-th element of the Goodstein sequence, and replace every instance of n with the first infinite ordinal number ω. Addition, multiplication and exponentiation of ordinal numbers is well defined, and the resulting ordinal number clearly cannot be smaller than the original element.

The 'base-changing' operation of the Goodstein sequence does not change the element of the parallel sequence: replacing all the 4s in 4^(4^4) + 4 with ω is the same as replacing all the 4s with 5s and then replacing all the 5s with ω. The 'subtracting 1' operation, however, corresponds to decreasing the infinite ordinal number in the parallel sequence; for example, ω^(ω^ω) + ω decreases to ω^(ω^ω) + 4 if the step above is performed. Because the ordinals are well-ordered, there are no infinite strictly decreasing sequences of ordinals. Thus the parallel sequence must terminate at 0 after a finite number of steps. The Goodstein sequence, which is bounded above by the parallel sequence, must terminate at 0 also.

While this proof of Goodstein's theorem is fairly easy, the Kirby-Paris theorem which says that Goodstein's theorem is not a theorem of Peano arithmetic, is technical and considerably more difficult. It makes use of countable nonstandard models of Peano arithmetic.

References

Goodstein, R., On the restricted ordinal theorem, Journal of Symbolic Logic, 9 (1944), 33-41.

Kirby, L. and Paris, J., Accessible independence results for Peano arithemtic, Bull. London. Math. Soc., 14 (1982), 285-93.

External links

Some elements of a proof that Goodstein's theorem is not a theorem of PA can be found here: http://www.u.arizona.edu/~miller/thesis/node11.html

Definitions of Goodstein sequences in the programming languages Ruby and Haskell, as well as a large-scale plot, may be found at http://www.cwi.nl/~tromp/pearls.html#goodstein