Being You: A New Science of Consciousness: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
m →‎Content: Changed word
Citation bot (talk | contribs)
Alter: url, title. URLs might have been anonymized. Add: newspaper, pages, doi-access, s2cid, pmid, authors 1-1. Removed proxy/dead URL that duplicated identifier. Removed parameters. Some additions/deletions were parameter name changes. | Use this bot. Report bugs. | Suggested by Headbomb | Linked from Wikipedia:WikiProject_Academic_Journals/Journals_cited_by_Wikipedia/Sandbox2 | #UCB_webform_linked 59/677
Line 16: Line 16:
Seth's interest in consciousness began when he was a child.<ref name="interalia">{{Cite web |last=Seth |first=Anil |date=2022-01-15 |title=On 'Being You' |url=https://www.interaliamag.org/interviews/anil-seth-on-being-you/ |access-date=2023-07-12 |website=Interalia Magazine |language=en-US}}</ref>
Seth's interest in consciousness began when he was a child.<ref name="interalia">{{Cite web |last=Seth |first=Anil |date=2022-01-15 |title=On 'Being You' |url=https://www.interaliamag.org/interviews/anil-seth-on-being-you/ |access-date=2023-07-12 |website=Interalia Magazine |language=en-US}}</ref>


In an interview with [[the Guardian]], Seth stated he wanted to understand himself and others.<ref name=":0">{{Cite news |last=Adams |first=Tim |date=2021-08-21 |title=Neuroscientist Anil Seth: ‘We risk not understanding the central mystery of life’ |language=en-GB |work=The Observer |url=https://www.theguardian.com/science/2021/aug/21/neuroscientist-anil-seth-we-risk-not-understanding-the-central-mystery-of-life |access-date=2023-07-12 |issn=0029-7712}}</ref> His multidisciplinary team in Sussex helped in writing the book, all wanting to develop a "satisfying scientific explanation of conscious experience."<ref name=":0" /> He described the book as a means to weave multiple threads of ideas together.<ref name=":1">{{Cite web |title=BI 117 Anil Seth: Being You {{!}} Brain Inspired |url=https://braininspired.co/podcast/117/ |access-date=2023-07-12 |language=en-US}}</ref>
In an interview with [[the Guardian]], Seth stated he wanted to understand himself and others.<ref name=":0">{{Cite news |last=Adams |first=Tim |date=2021-08-21 |title=Neuroscientist Anil Seth: 'We risk not understanding the central mystery of life' |language=en-GB |work=The Observer |url=https://www.theguardian.com/science/2021/aug/21/neuroscientist-anil-seth-we-risk-not-understanding-the-central-mystery-of-life |access-date=2023-07-12 |issn=0029-7712}}</ref> His multidisciplinary team in Sussex helped in writing the book, all wanting to develop a "satisfying scientific explanation of conscious experience."<ref name=":0" /> He described the book as a means to weave multiple threads of ideas together.<ref name=":1">{{Cite web |title=BI 117 Anil Seth: Being You {{!}} Brain Inspired |url=https://braininspired.co/podcast/117/ |access-date=2023-07-12 |language=en-US}}</ref>


The book itself took three years to write.<ref name=":1" /> Seth said the process was difficult due to other commitments, but the [[Wellcome Trust]] provided him with an Engagement Fellowship which helped him find time to write.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Cooke |first=Emily |date=2023-02-23 |title=How I wrote a popular science book about consciousness — and why (Interview with Anil Seth)|url=https://www.nature.com/articles/d41586-023-00541-z |journal=Nature |language=en |doi=10.1038/d41586-023-00541-z}}</ref>
The book itself took three years to write.<ref name=":1" /> Seth said the process was difficult due to other commitments, but the [[Wellcome Trust]] provided him with an Engagement Fellowship which helped him find time to write.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Cooke |first=Emily |date=2023-02-23 |title=How I wrote a popular science book about consciousness — and why (Interview with Anil Seth)|url=https://www.nature.com/articles/d41586-023-00541-z |journal=Nature |language=en |doi=10.1038/d41586-023-00541-z|pmid=36823269 |s2cid=257152610 }}</ref>


== Contents ==
== Contents ==
Line 32: Line 32:
This part discusses [[Thomas Nagel]]'s ''[[What Is It Like to Be a Bat?]],'' and gives brief introductions to [[global workspace theory|GWT]], [[higher-order theories of consciousness]], [[David Chalmers]]'s [[hard problem of consciousness]], [[philosophical zombies]], [[neural correlates of consciousness|NCC]] and various philosophical positions.{{refn|group=nb|Namely [[physicalism]], [[idealism]], [[Mind–body dualism|dualism]], [[functionalism (philosophy of mind)|functionalism]], [[panpsychism]], [[mysterianism]], and [[vitalism]].}} Seth ultimately identifies himself as a physicalist.<ref name="interalia" />
This part discusses [[Thomas Nagel]]'s ''[[What Is It Like to Be a Bat?]],'' and gives brief introductions to [[global workspace theory|GWT]], [[higher-order theories of consciousness]], [[David Chalmers]]'s [[hard problem of consciousness]], [[philosophical zombies]], [[neural correlates of consciousness|NCC]] and various philosophical positions.{{refn|group=nb|Namely [[physicalism]], [[idealism]], [[Mind–body dualism|dualism]], [[functionalism (philosophy of mind)|functionalism]], [[panpsychism]], [[mysterianism]], and [[vitalism]].}} Seth ultimately identifies himself as a physicalist.<ref name="interalia" />


He also details [[Edme Mariotte]]'s experiments in the [[Paris Observatory]] cellar—which would later lead to the creation of the [[thermometer]]<ref>{{Cite book |last=Chang |first=Hasok |title=Inventing temperature: measurement and scientific progress |date=2007 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-533738-9 |edition=1. issued as paperback |series=Oxford studies in philosophy of science |location=Oxford}}</ref>—before talking about the various attempts at direct measurements of consciousness (a "thermometer" for consciousness), such as using [[Lempel–Ziv complexity|Lempel-Ziv complexity]] algorithms, the perturbational complexity index (PCI),{{refn|group=nb|Measures the complexity of [[EEG]] responses to [[transcranial magnetic stimulation|TMS]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Sinitsyn |first=Dmitry O. |last2=Poydasheva |first2=Alexandra G. |last3=Bakulin |first3=Ilya S. |last4=Legostaeva |first4=Liudmila A. |last5=Iazeva |first5=Elizaveta G. |last6=Sergeev |first6=Dmitry V. |last7=Sergeeva |first7=Anastasia N. |last8=Kremneva |first8=Elena I. |last9=Morozova |first9=Sofya N. |last10=Lagoda |first10=Dmitry Yu. |last11=Casarotto |first11=Silvia |last12=Comanducci |first12=Angela |last13=Ryabinkina |first13=Yulia V. |last14=Suponeva |first14=Natalia A. |last15=Piradov |first15=Michael A. |display-authors=2 |date=2020-11-27 |title=Detecting the Potential for Consciousness in Unresponsive Patients Using the Perturbational Complexity Index |url=https://www.mdpi.com/2076-3425/10/12/917 |journal=Brain Sciences |language=en |volume=10 |issue=12 |pages=917 |doi=10.3390/brainsci10120917 |issn=2076-3425 |pmc=7760168 |pmid=33260944}}</ref>}} the work of Martin Monti and [[Adrian Owen]], and the usage of [[Psychedelic drug|psychedelics]] by [[Albert Hofmann]]. He concludes that none of these methods are perfect, however found Tononi (1998)<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Tononi |first=G. |date=1998-12-04 |title=Consciousness and Complexity |url=https://www.sciencemag.org/lookup/doi/10.1126/science.282.5395.1846 |journal=Science |volume=282 |issue=5395 |pages=1846–1851 |doi=10.1126/science.282.5395.1846}}</ref> (which he later derived his own measure of consciousness he calls "casual density"<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Seth |first=Anil K. |last2=Barrett |first2=Adam B. |last3=Barnett |first3=Lionel |date=2011-10-13 |title=Causal density and integrated information as measures of conscious level |url=https://royalsocietypublishing.org/doi/10.1098/rsta.2011.0079 |journal=Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences |language=en |volume=369 |issue=1952 |pages=3748–3767 |doi=10.1098/rsta.2011.0079 |issn=1364-503X}}</ref>) to be a compelling route to pursue.
He also details [[Edme Mariotte]]'s experiments in the [[Paris Observatory]] cellar—which would later lead to the creation of the [[thermometer]]<ref>{{Cite book |last=Chang |first=Hasok |title=Inventing temperature: measurement and scientific progress |date=2007 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-533738-9 |edition=1. issued as paperback |series=Oxford studies in philosophy of science |location=Oxford}}</ref>—before talking about the various attempts at direct measurements of consciousness (a "thermometer" for consciousness), such as using [[Lempel–Ziv complexity|Lempel-Ziv complexity]] algorithms, the perturbational complexity index (PCI),{{refn|group=nb|Measures the complexity of [[EEG]] responses to [[transcranial magnetic stimulation|TMS]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Sinitsyn |first1=Dmitry O. |last2=Poydasheva |first2=Alexandra G. |last3=Bakulin |first3=Ilya S. |last4=Legostaeva |first4=Liudmila A. |last5=Iazeva |first5=Elizaveta G. |last6=Sergeev |first6=Dmitry V. |last7=Sergeeva |first7=Anastasia N. |last8=Kremneva |first8=Elena I. |last9=Morozova |first9=Sofya N. |last10=Lagoda |first10=Dmitry Yu. |last11=Casarotto |first11=Silvia |last12=Comanducci |first12=Angela |last13=Ryabinkina |first13=Yulia V. |last14=Suponeva |first14=Natalia A. |last15=Piradov |first15=Michael A. |display-authors=2 |date=2020-11-27 |title=Detecting the Potential for Consciousness in Unresponsive Patients Using the Perturbational Complexity Index |journal=Brain Sciences |language=en |volume=10 |issue=12 |pages=917 |doi=10.3390/brainsci10120917 |issn=2076-3425 |pmc=7760168 |pmid=33260944 |doi-access=free }}</ref>}} the work of Martin Monti and [[Adrian Owen]], and the usage of [[Psychedelic drug|psychedelics]] by [[Albert Hofmann]]. He concludes that none of these methods are perfect, however found Tononi (1998)<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Tononi |first=G. |date=1998-12-04 |title=Consciousness and Complexity |url=https://www.sciencemag.org/lookup/doi/10.1126/science.282.5395.1846 |journal=Science |volume=282 |issue=5395 |pages=1846–1851 |doi=10.1126/science.282.5395.1846|pmid=9836628 }}</ref> (which he later derived his own measure of consciousness he calls "casual density"<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Seth |first1=Anil K. |last2=Barrett |first2=Adam B. |last3=Barnett |first3=Lionel |date=2011-10-13 |title=Causal density and integrated information as measures of conscious level |url=https://royalsocietypublishing.org/doi/10.1098/rsta.2011.0079 |journal=Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences |language=en |volume=369 |issue=1952 |pages=3748–3767 |doi=10.1098/rsta.2011.0079 |pmid=21893526 |s2cid=12788294 |issn=1364-503X}}</ref>) to be a compelling route to pursue.


Seth recalls a talk he had with Tononi in Las Vegas 2006 about [[integrated information theory]], which Seth describes as "deeply mathematical and unapologetically complex." He elaborates what IIT is, how some predictions may be testable, and gives various interpretations on the theory. Seth concludes that while skeptical about its larger claims, he is interested to see how the theory develops.
Seth recalls a talk he had with Tononi in Las Vegas 2006 about [[integrated information theory]], which Seth describes as "deeply mathematical and unapologetically complex." He elaborates what IIT is, how some predictions may be testable, and gives various interpretations on the theory. Seth concludes that while skeptical about its larger claims, he is interested to see how the theory develops.
Line 40: Line 40:
''Conscious content'' is said to be about what a person is conscious of: [[senses]], emotions, thoughts, and beliefs. This part focuses on Seth views the mind as a "prediction machine" and how the contents of consciousness are "controlled hallucinations."<ref>{{Cite web |date=2022-11-22 |title=Anil Seth: "Reality is a controlled hallucination" |url=https://lab.cccb.org/en/anil-seth-reality-is-a-controlled-hallucination/ |access-date=2023-07-15 |website=CCCB LAB |language=en-US}}</ref>
''Conscious content'' is said to be about what a person is conscious of: [[senses]], emotions, thoughts, and beliefs. This part focuses on Seth views the mind as a "prediction machine" and how the contents of consciousness are "controlled hallucinations."<ref>{{Cite web |date=2022-11-22 |title=Anil Seth: "Reality is a controlled hallucination" |url=https://lab.cccb.org/en/anil-seth-reality-is-a-controlled-hallucination/ |access-date=2023-07-15 |website=CCCB LAB |language=en-US}}</ref>


Seth begins by detailing what he calls the "how things seem view" where the brain receives information via sensory input. However, he quotes an exchange between [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]] and [[G. E. M. Anscombe]] where Wittgenstein, using Copernicus's heliocentrism, illustrates how things seem may not be how they actually are.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Anscombe |first=Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=xkAQAQAAIAAJ&newbks=0&hl=en |title=An Introduction to Wittgenstein's Tractatus |date=1971 |publisher=University of Pennsylvania Press |isbn=978-0-8122-1019-4 |page=151 |language=en}}</ref> He then talks about [[Hermann von Helmholtz]]'s [[unconscious inference]], which Seth relates to controlled hallucinations.{{refn|group=nb|The term "controlled hallucinations" was not coined by Seth, rather he attributes its origin back to a 1990's seminar by [[Ramesh Jain]]. See J. Tiehen (2022) for discussion of the term's origin.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Tiehen |first=Justin |date=2022-03-29 |title=Perception as controlled hallucination |url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/phib.12268 |journal=Analytic Philosophy |language=en |doi=10.1111/phib.12268 |issn=2153-9596}}</ref>}}
Seth begins by detailing what he calls the "how things seem view" where the brain receives information via sensory input. However, he quotes an exchange between [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]] and [[G. E. M. Anscombe]] where Wittgenstein, using Copernicus's heliocentrism, illustrates how things seem may not be how they actually are.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Anscombe |first=Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=xkAQAQAAIAAJ |title=An Introduction to Wittgenstein's Tractatus |date=1971 |publisher=University of Pennsylvania Press |isbn=978-0-8122-1019-4 |page=151 |language=en}}</ref> He then talks about [[Hermann von Helmholtz]]'s [[unconscious inference]], which Seth relates to controlled hallucinations.{{refn|group=nb|The term "controlled hallucinations" was not coined by Seth, rather he attributes its origin back to a 1990's seminar by [[Ramesh Jain]]. See J. Tiehen (2022) for discussion of the term's origin.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Tiehen |first=Justin |date=2022-03-29 |title=Perception as controlled hallucination |url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/phib.12268 |journal=Analytic Philosophy |language=en |doi=10.1111/phib.12268 |issn=2153-9596}}</ref>}}


A controlled hallucination, as Seth explains in the book, is made up of three "ingredients:" the brain making predictions, sensory signals that keep these predictions tied to their causes, and subjective experience via "top-down" predictions rather than "bottom-up."{{refn|group=nb|Referring to how brain signals go from the inner brain (top) to the outside world via our senses (bottom) rather than the previously mentioned "how things seem view" which is "bottom-up." See Kveraga (2007).<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Kveraga |first=Kestutis |last2=Ghuman |first2=Avniel S. |last3=Bar |first3=Moshe |date=2007-11-01 |title=Top-down predictions in the cognitive brain |url=https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0278262607000954 |journal=Brain and Cognition |language=en |volume=65 |issue=2 |pages=145–168 |doi=10.1016/j.bandc.2007.06.007 |issn=0278-2626 |pmc=2099308 |pmid=17923222}}</ref>}} He then makes references to this process using [[the dress]], [[checker shadow illusion|Adelson's Checkerboard]], and a [[Mooney Face Test|Mooney image]]. Seth follows this by listing two objections to the controlled hallucination concept, the first being it denies undeniable aspects of the real world and the second being that it means we are trapped in the perceptual world of the already expected. He, however, refutes these.
A controlled hallucination, as Seth explains in the book, is made up of three "ingredients:" the brain making predictions, sensory signals that keep these predictions tied to their causes, and subjective experience via "top-down" predictions rather than "bottom-up."{{refn|group=nb|Referring to how brain signals go from the inner brain (top) to the outside world via our senses (bottom) rather than the previously mentioned "how things seem view" which is "bottom-up." See Kveraga (2007).<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Kveraga |first1=Kestutis |last2=Ghuman |first2=Avniel S. |last3=Bar |first3=Moshe |date=2007-11-01 |title=Top-down predictions in the cognitive brain |journal=Brain and Cognition |language=en |volume=65 |issue=2 |pages=145–168 |doi=10.1016/j.bandc.2007.06.007 |issn=0278-2626 |pmc=2099308 |pmid=17923222}}</ref>}} He then makes references to this process using [[the dress]], [[checker shadow illusion|Adelson's Checkerboard]], and a [[Mooney Face Test|Mooney image]]. Seth follows this by listing two objections to the controlled hallucination concept, the first being it denies undeniable aspects of the real world and the second being that it means we are trapped in the perceptual world of the already expected. He, however, refutes these.


Seth describes the brain as a [[Bayesian approaches to brain function|Bayesian-like prediction machine]]. Using [[Normal distribution|Gaussian probability distribution]], Seth defines a standard of optimality for perceptual interference, however cannot establish how a brain neurally gets these guesses. He details three core components of brain predictive error minimization to see how it does so: [[generative model]]s, perceptual hierarchies (from large scale to low scale characteristics of something), and precision weighting of sensory signals (influence adjustment of each sense).
Seth describes the brain as a [[Bayesian approaches to brain function|Bayesian-like prediction machine]]. Using [[Normal distribution|Gaussian probability distribution]], Seth defines a standard of optimality for perceptual interference, however cannot establish how a brain neurally gets these guesses. He details three core components of brain predictive error minimization to see how it does so: [[generative model]]s, perceptual hierarchies (from large scale to low scale characteristics of something), and precision weighting of sensory signals (influence adjustment of each sense).
Line 56: Line 56:
Seth then discusses the [[great chain of being]]. Talking about Descartes, Seth states that the aforementioned chain forced Descartes, whose philosophy investigated the idea of a soul and could thereby deny the anthropocentric doctrine of the church, to rationalize the existence of God in ''[[Meditations on First Philosophy]]'' and possibly led to his disregard of the suffering of animals due to his view of them as being mere soulless machines. Seth argues that [[Julien Offray de La Mettrie]], who included humans as animal machines, was closer to the truth.
Seth then discusses the [[great chain of being]]. Talking about Descartes, Seth states that the aforementioned chain forced Descartes, whose philosophy investigated the idea of a soul and could thereby deny the anthropocentric doctrine of the church, to rationalize the existence of God in ''[[Meditations on First Philosophy]]'' and possibly led to his disregard of the suffering of animals due to his view of them as being mere soulless machines. Seth argues that [[Julien Offray de La Mettrie]], who included humans as animal machines, was closer to the truth.


Seth's theory of animal machines (which he refers to as beast machines) differs from Descartes: he includes humans as beast machines and that instead of the machine being life irrelevant to mind, the self is all perceptions and experiences (which are controlled hallucinations) which originate in the fluctuating predictive machine called the mind.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Seth |first=Anil K. |last2=Tsakiris |first2=Manos |date=November 2018 |title=Being a Beast Machine: The Somatic Basis of Selfhood |url=https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2018.08.008 |journal=Trends in Cognitive Sciences |volume=22 |issue=11 |pages=969–981 |doi=10.1016/j.tics.2018.08.008 |issn=1364-6613}}</ref>
Seth's theory of animal machines (which he refers to as beast machines) differs from Descartes: he includes humans as beast machines and that instead of the machine being life irrelevant to mind, the self is all perceptions and experiences (which are controlled hallucinations) which originate in the fluctuating predictive machine called the mind.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Seth |first1=Anil K. |last2=Tsakiris |first2=Manos |date=November 2018 |title=Being a Beast Machine: The Somatic Basis of Selfhood |url=https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2018.08.008 |journal=Trends in Cognitive Sciences |volume=22 |issue=11 |pages=969–981 |doi=10.1016/j.tics.2018.08.008 |pmid=30224233 |s2cid=52287016 |issn=1364-6613}}</ref>


He spends a chapter writing about the [[free energy principle]], its effects on neuroscience, and its relation to IIT. He comparatively summarizes both and states his idea of animal machines and controlled hallucinations as being the middle-way between both theories.
He spends a chapter writing about the [[free energy principle]], its effects on neuroscience, and its relation to IIT. He comparatively summarizes both and states his idea of animal machines and controlled hallucinations as being the middle-way between both theories.


Seth then discusses the work of [[Benjamin Libet]] and his controversial volition experiment which some say disproved [[free will]].<ref>{{Cite web |last=Clarke |first=Peter G.H. |date=February 2013 |title=The Libet experiment and its implications for conscious will |url=https://www.faraday.cam.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/resources/Faraday%20Papers/Faraday%20Paper%2017%20Clarke_EN.pdf |access-date=July 16, 2023 |website=faraday.cam.ac.uk}}</ref> He then discusses Aaron Schurger's 2012 paper which proposes that Libet's readiness potential was instead fluctuating brain activity that passed a threshold, causing a voluntary action.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Schurger |first=Aaron |last2=Sitt |first2=Jacobo D. |last3=Dehaene |first3=Stanislas |date=2012-10-16 |title=An accumulator model for spontaneous neural activity prior to self-initiated movement |url=https://pnas.org/doi/full/10.1073/pnas.1210467109 |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences |language=en |volume=109 |issue=42 |doi=10.1073/pnas.1210467109 |issn=0027-8424 |pmc=3479453 |pmid=22869750}}</ref> When discussing his own view on free will, Seth references [[Daniel Wegner]]'s ''The Illusion of Conscious Will,'' and states that while he believes free will to be illusionary, expresses the need to live as if it does exist.<ref>{{Cite web |title=BBC Radio 4 - The Life Scientific, Anil Seth on consciousness, Do we have free will? |url=https://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/p02tsj3j/player |access-date=2023-07-16 |website=www.bbc.co.uk}}</ref>
Seth then discusses the work of [[Benjamin Libet]] and his controversial volition experiment which some say disproved [[free will]].<ref>{{Cite web |last=Clarke |first=Peter G.H. |date=February 2013 |title=The Libet experiment and its implications for conscious will |url=https://www.faraday.cam.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/resources/Faraday%20Papers/Faraday%20Paper%2017%20Clarke_EN.pdf |access-date=July 16, 2023 |website=faraday.cam.ac.uk}}</ref> He then discusses Aaron Schurger's 2012 paper which proposes that Libet's readiness potential was instead fluctuating brain activity that passed a threshold, causing a voluntary action.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Schurger |first1=Aaron |last2=Sitt |first2=Jacobo D. |last3=Dehaene |first3=Stanislas |date=2012-10-16 |title=An accumulator model for spontaneous neural activity prior to self-initiated movement |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences |language=en |volume=109 |issue=42 |pages=E2904-13 |doi=10.1073/pnas.1210467109 |issn=0027-8424 |pmc=3479453 |pmid=22869750 |doi-access=free }}</ref> When discussing his own view on free will, Seth references [[Daniel Wegner]]'s ''The Illusion of Conscious Will,'' and states that while he believes free will to be illusionary, expresses the need to live as if it does exist.<ref>{{Cite web |title=BBC Radio 4 - The Life Scientific, Anil Seth on consciousness, Do we have free will? |url=https://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/p02tsj3j/player |access-date=2023-07-16 |website=www.bbc.co.uk}}</ref>


=== Other ===
=== Other ===
Line 73: Line 73:


== Reception ==
== Reception ==
The book was well received. It was chosen as a Best Book of 2021 by [[Bloomberg News|Bloomberg]]<ref>{{Cite web |title=The 49 Most Fascinating, Mind-Blowing, Challenging, Hilarious, and Urgent Titles of the Year |url=https://www.bloomberg.com/tosv2.html?vid=&uuid=289b3ed3-217b-11ee-902d-5a6166735166&url=L2ZlYXR1cmVzLzIwMjEtYmVzdC1ib29rcy8= |access-date=2023-07-13 |website=Bloomberg}}</ref> and ''[[The Economist]]'',<ref>{{Cite news |title=The best books of 2021 |work=The Economist |url=https://www.economist.com/books-and-arts/2021/12/11/the-best-books-of-2021 |access-date=2023-07-13 |issn=0013-0613}}</ref> a Best Science Book of 2021 by ''The Guardian''<ref>{{Cite news |last=Sample |first=Ian |date=2021-12-07 |title=The best science books of 2021 |language=en-GB |work=The Guardian |url=https://www.theguardian.com/books/2021/dec/07/the-best-science-books-of-2021 |access-date=2023-07-13 |issn=0261-3077}}</ref> and the ''[[Financial Times]]'',<ref>{{Cite web |last=Cookson |first=Clive |title=Best books of 2021: Science |url=https://www.ft.com/content/52aee4e2-02f7-4a2d-bfe9-42e5ebf25017 |access-date=2023-07-13 |website=Financial Times}}</ref> and a Best Philosophy Book of 2021 by [[Nigel Warburton]].<ref>{{Cite web |last=Warburton |first=Nigel |title=The Best Philosophy Books of 2021 |url=https://fivebooks.com/best-books/the-best-philosophy-books-of-2021-nigel-warburton/ |access-date=2023-07-13 |website=Five Books |language=en}}</ref>
The book was well received. It was chosen as a Best Book of 2021 by [[Bloomberg News|Bloomberg]]<ref>{{Cite web |title=The 49 Most Fascinating, Mind-Blowing, Challenging, Hilarious, and Urgent Titles of the Year |url=https://www.bloomberg.com/features/2021-best-books/ |access-date=2023-07-13 |website=Bloomberg}}</ref> and ''[[The Economist]]'',<ref>{{Cite news |title=The best books of 2021 |newspaper=The Economist |url=https://www.economist.com/books-and-arts/2021/12/11/the-best-books-of-2021 |access-date=2023-07-13 |issn=0013-0613}}</ref> a Best Science Book of 2021 by ''The Guardian''<ref>{{Cite news |last=Sample |first=Ian |date=2021-12-07 |title=The best science books of 2021 |language=en-GB |work=The Guardian |url=https://www.theguardian.com/books/2021/dec/07/the-best-science-books-of-2021 |access-date=2023-07-13 |issn=0261-3077}}</ref> and the ''[[Financial Times]]'',<ref>{{Cite web |last=Cookson |first=Clive |title=Best books of 2021: Science |url=https://www.ft.com/content/52aee4e2-02f7-4a2d-bfe9-42e5ebf25017 |access-date=2023-07-13 |website=Financial Times}}</ref> and a Best Philosophy Book of 2021 by [[Nigel Warburton]].<ref>{{Cite web |last=Warburton |first=Nigel |title=The Best Philosophy Books of 2021 |url=https://fivebooks.com/best-books/the-best-philosophy-books-of-2021-nigel-warburton/ |access-date=2023-07-13 |website=Five Books |language=en}}</ref>


[[Gaia Vince]] described the book in her review as exhilarating.<ref>{{Cite news |last=Vince |first=Gaia |date=2021-08-25 |title=Being You by Professor Anil Seth review – the exhilarating new science of consciousness |language=en-GB |work=The Guardian |url=https://www.theguardian.com/books/2021/aug/25/being-you-by-professor-anil-seth-review-the-exhilarating-new-science-of-consciousness |access-date=2023-07-12 |issn=0261-3077}}</ref> Science journalist Maddie Bender, writing for ''[[Scientific American]]'', praised Seth's "imaginative and compelling" descriptions of experiments.<ref>Bender, M. (2021). Being You: A New Science of Consciousness. ''[[Scientific American]]'', ''325''(4), 87.</ref> Felix Haas described the book as a "fantastic exposition" of neuroscience and artificial intelligence research.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Haas |first=Felix |date=March 2022 |title=Being You: A New Science of Consciousness by Anil Seth |url=https://muse.jhu.edu/article/848173 |journal=[[World Literature Today]] |language=en |volume=96 |issue=2 |pages=72–73 |doi=10.1353/wlt.2022.0093 |issn=1945-8134}}</ref>
[[Gaia Vince]] described the book in her review as exhilarating.<ref>{{Cite news |last=Vince |first=Gaia |date=2021-08-25 |title=Being You by Professor Anil Seth review – the exhilarating new science of consciousness |language=en-GB |work=The Guardian |url=https://www.theguardian.com/books/2021/aug/25/being-you-by-professor-anil-seth-review-the-exhilarating-new-science-of-consciousness |access-date=2023-07-12 |issn=0261-3077}}</ref> Science journalist Maddie Bender, writing for ''[[Scientific American]]'', praised Seth's "imaginative and compelling" descriptions of experiments.<ref>Bender, M. (2021). Being You: A New Science of Consciousness. ''[[Scientific American]]'', ''325''(4), 87.</ref> Felix Haas described the book as a "fantastic exposition" of neuroscience and artificial intelligence research.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Haas |first=Felix |date=March 2022 |title=Being You: A New Science of Consciousness by Anil Seth |url=https://muse.jhu.edu/article/848173 |journal=[[World Literature Today]] |language=en |volume=96 |issue=2 |pages=72–73 |doi=10.1353/wlt.2022.0093 |s2cid=247162023 |issn=1945-8134}}</ref>


[[Naturalism (philosophy)|Naturalist]] philosopher Tom Clark, while praising the book's liveliness, disagreed with some of Seth's approaches and conclusions.<ref name=":2">{{Cite web |title=Naturalizing Consciousness: Review of "Being You" by Anil Seth {{!}} Naturalism.org |url=https://www.naturalism.org/resources/book-reviews/naturalizing-consciousness-review-of-being-you-by-anil-seth |access-date=2023-07-12 |website=Naturalism |language=en}}</ref> [[Julian Baggini]], writing in ''[[The Wall Street Journal]]'', describes the work as impressive, but criticizes Seth's use of words such as "hallucination" and "fantasy" as he says they invite misunderstandings.<ref>{{Cite news |last=Baggini |first=Julian |date=2021-12-09 |title=‘Being You’ Review: Why We Have a Sense of Self |language=en-US |work=Wall Street Journal |url=https://www.wsj.com/articles/being-you-review-why-we-have-a-sense-of-self-11639093233 |access-date=2023-07-12 |issn=0099-9660}}</ref>
[[Naturalism (philosophy)|Naturalist]] philosopher Tom Clark, while praising the book's liveliness, disagreed with some of Seth's approaches and conclusions.<ref name=":2">{{Cite web |title=Naturalizing Consciousness: Review of "Being You" by Anil Seth {{!}} Naturalism.org |url=https://www.naturalism.org/resources/book-reviews/naturalizing-consciousness-review-of-being-you-by-anil-seth |access-date=2023-07-12 |website=Naturalism |language=en}}</ref> [[Julian Baggini]], writing in ''[[The Wall Street Journal]]'', describes the work as impressive, but criticizes Seth's use of words such as "hallucination" and "fantasy" as he says they invite misunderstandings.<ref>{{Cite news |last=Baggini |first=Julian |date=2021-12-09 |title='Being You' Review: Why We Have a Sense of Self |language=en-US |work=Wall Street Journal |url=https://www.wsj.com/articles/being-you-review-why-we-have-a-sense-of-self-11639093233 |access-date=2023-07-12 |issn=0099-9660}}</ref>


== Further reading ==
== Further reading ==

Revision as of 00:05, 10 August 2023

Being You: A New Science of Consciousness
AuthorAnil Seth
LanguageEnglish
GenrePhilosophy, psychology, neuroscience
PublisherFaber and Faber
Publication date
September 2, 2021[1]
ISBN978-0-57133-770-5

Being You: A New Science of Consciousness is a 2021 non-fiction book by neuroscientist Anil Seth, published by Faber and Faber. It explores the author's theory about consciousness and the self which has three components: conscious level, conscious content, and conscious self.

Conception

Seth's interest in consciousness began when he was a child.[2]

In an interview with the Guardian, Seth stated he wanted to understand himself and others.[3] His multidisciplinary team in Sussex helped in writing the book, all wanting to develop a "satisfying scientific explanation of conscious experience."[3] He described the book as a means to weave multiple threads of ideas together.[4]

The book itself took three years to write.[4] Seth said the process was difficult due to other commitments, but the Wellcome Trust provided him with an Engagement Fellowship which helped him find time to write.[5]

Contents

The book has six parts, each giving a broad overview of various philosophical and scientific positions that Seth relates to his own conclusions. Personal stories are also used to illustrate his points. Conscious level, conscious content, and conscious self are what Seth consider to be the three core properties of consciousness.

Prologue

Seth discusses general anesthesia,[6] mechanical brains, Descartes's animal machine, and Sigmund Freud's "three strikes against human exceptionalism,"[7] that being Copernicus's heliocentric theory, Darwinian evolution, and Freud's own theory of the unconscious mind.

Level

Paris Observatory where in a cellar Edme Mariotte performed his experiments

Conscious level is Seth's measurement of how conscious a being is, from being comatose or brain dead to being fully awake and aware.

This part discusses Thomas Nagel's What Is It Like to Be a Bat?, and gives brief introductions to GWT, higher-order theories of consciousness, David Chalmers's hard problem of consciousness, philosophical zombies, NCC and various philosophical positions.[nb 1] Seth ultimately identifies himself as a physicalist.[2]

He also details Edme Mariotte's experiments in the Paris Observatory cellar—which would later lead to the creation of the thermometer[8]—before talking about the various attempts at direct measurements of consciousness (a "thermometer" for consciousness), such as using Lempel-Ziv complexity algorithms, the perturbational complexity index (PCI),[nb 2] the work of Martin Monti and Adrian Owen, and the usage of psychedelics by Albert Hofmann. He concludes that none of these methods are perfect, however found Tononi (1998)[10] (which he later derived his own measure of consciousness he calls "casual density"[11]) to be a compelling route to pursue.

Seth recalls a talk he had with Tononi in Las Vegas 2006 about integrated information theory, which Seth describes as "deeply mathematical and unapologetically complex." He elaborates what IIT is, how some predictions may be testable, and gives various interpretations on the theory. Seth concludes that while skeptical about its larger claims, he is interested to see how the theory develops.

Content

Photo of Ludwig Wittgenstein.
Ludwig Wittgenstein (1929), who drew the comparison between Copernican heliocentrism and how perception does not dictate what reality is

Conscious content is said to be about what a person is conscious of: senses, emotions, thoughts, and beliefs. This part focuses on Seth views the mind as a "prediction machine" and how the contents of consciousness are "controlled hallucinations."[12]

Seth begins by detailing what he calls the "how things seem view" where the brain receives information via sensory input. However, he quotes an exchange between Ludwig Wittgenstein and G. E. M. Anscombe where Wittgenstein, using Copernicus's heliocentrism, illustrates how things seem may not be how they actually are.[13] He then talks about Hermann von Helmholtz's unconscious inference, which Seth relates to controlled hallucinations.[nb 3]

A controlled hallucination, as Seth explains in the book, is made up of three "ingredients:" the brain making predictions, sensory signals that keep these predictions tied to their causes, and subjective experience via "top-down" predictions rather than "bottom-up."[nb 4] He then makes references to this process using the dress, Adelson's Checkerboard, and a Mooney image. Seth follows this by listing two objections to the controlled hallucination concept, the first being it denies undeniable aspects of the real world and the second being that it means we are trapped in the perceptual world of the already expected. He, however, refutes these.

Seth describes the brain as a Bayesian-like prediction machine. Using Gaussian probability distribution, Seth defines a standard of optimality for perceptual interference, however cannot establish how a brain neurally gets these guesses. He details three core components of brain predictive error minimization to see how it does so: generative models, perceptual hierarchies (from large scale to low scale characteristics of something), and precision weighting of sensory signals (influence adjustment of each sense).

Self

The Great Chain of Being (1579) by Fray Diego de Valades, which illustrates the traditional cosmological hierarchical system held by the Catholic Church

Conscious self is defined as the sense of being you, that is having a conscious awareness of the self.

Seth talks about when his mother was admitted to the hospital due to undiagnosed encephalopathy which some years later led to her being in a state of hospital-induced delirium. It's through this recollection that the reader is directed to the questioning of their own self-hood, which Seth considers a special kind of controlled hallucination. Here he references Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason where Kant states that the self is not just a "simple substance,"[16] David Hume who called it a "bundle of perceptions,"[17] and Thomas Metzinger's Being No One which Seth describes as "brilliant." The split-brain phenomena is also briefly discussed.

He later writes about Clive Wearing and the effect amnesia has over personal identity. In referencing the relationship Clive has with his wife, Seth talks about the influence of social perception one has on the social self which he says is created through generative models. He then says the reason we perceive ourselves in the first place is not to know ourselves (as evidentially that perception is easily warped), but is to control ourselves.

Seth then discusses the great chain of being. Talking about Descartes, Seth states that the aforementioned chain forced Descartes, whose philosophy investigated the idea of a soul and could thereby deny the anthropocentric doctrine of the church, to rationalize the existence of God in Meditations on First Philosophy and possibly led to his disregard of the suffering of animals due to his view of them as being mere soulless machines. Seth argues that Julien Offray de La Mettrie, who included humans as animal machines, was closer to the truth.

Seth's theory of animal machines (which he refers to as beast machines) differs from Descartes: he includes humans as beast machines and that instead of the machine being life irrelevant to mind, the self is all perceptions and experiences (which are controlled hallucinations) which originate in the fluctuating predictive machine called the mind.[18]

He spends a chapter writing about the free energy principle, its effects on neuroscience, and its relation to IIT. He comparatively summarizes both and states his idea of animal machines and controlled hallucinations as being the middle-way between both theories.

Seth then discusses the work of Benjamin Libet and his controversial volition experiment which some say disproved free will.[19] He then discusses Aaron Schurger's 2012 paper which proposes that Libet's readiness potential was instead fluctuating brain activity that passed a threshold, causing a voluntary action.[20] When discussing his own view on free will, Seth references Daniel Wegner's The Illusion of Conscious Will, and states that while he believes free will to be illusionary, expresses the need to live as if it does exist.[21]

Other

Chapters dedicated to non-humans; animals and artificial intelligence.

Discussing Edward Payson Evans's The Criminal Prosecution and Capital Punishment of Animals,[22] he talks about the history of animal trials and the research into the consciousness of animals. He iterates that we should be skeptical of equating intelligence with consciousness as such a view promotes anthropocentrism, anthropomorphism, and "methodological laziness." Consciousness and the ability to suffer are independent of intelligence, he says, and that something can be intelligent but not conscious.

That last point is further delved into in the second to last chapter titled Machine Minds where he discusses at what point AI can be considered conscious. He talks about the technological singularity and reiterates the disconnect between intelligence and sentience. Seth is ultimately skeptical about the ability to make a conscious machine, at least in the near future. ChatGPT and flesh-based computers are also mentioned in this chapter.

Epilogue

The book ends with Seth describing the first time he saw a living human brain as a guest during a child's hemispherectomy, which he describes as "leaving him in-awe of the magical organ before him." He then summarizes his three-part theory of consciousness before concluding with a message about making peace with the nothingness of death.

Reception

The book was well received. It was chosen as a Best Book of 2021 by Bloomberg[23] and The Economist,[24] a Best Science Book of 2021 by The Guardian[25] and the Financial Times,[26] and a Best Philosophy Book of 2021 by Nigel Warburton.[27]

Gaia Vince described the book in her review as exhilarating.[28] Science journalist Maddie Bender, writing for Scientific American, praised Seth's "imaginative and compelling" descriptions of experiments.[29] Felix Haas described the book as a "fantastic exposition" of neuroscience and artificial intelligence research.[30]

Naturalist philosopher Tom Clark, while praising the book's liveliness, disagreed with some of Seth's approaches and conclusions.[6] Julian Baggini, writing in The Wall Street Journal, describes the work as impressive, but criticizes Seth's use of words such as "hallucination" and "fantasy" as he says they invite misunderstandings.[31]

Further reading

Notes

  1. ^ Namely physicalism, idealism, dualism, functionalism, panpsychism, mysterianism, and vitalism.
  2. ^ Measures the complexity of EEG responses to TMS.[9]
  3. ^ The term "controlled hallucinations" was not coined by Seth, rather he attributes its origin back to a 1990's seminar by Ramesh Jain. See J. Tiehen (2022) for discussion of the term's origin.[14]
  4. ^ Referring to how brain signals go from the inner brain (top) to the outside world via our senses (bottom) rather than the previously mentioned "how things seem view" which is "bottom-up." See Kveraga (2007).[15]

References

  1. ^ "Being You (Hardback)". Faber. Retrieved 2023-07-12.
  2. ^ a b Seth, Anil (2022-01-15). "On 'Being You'". Interalia Magazine. Retrieved 2023-07-12.
  3. ^ a b Adams, Tim (2021-08-21). "Neuroscientist Anil Seth: 'We risk not understanding the central mystery of life'". The Observer. ISSN 0029-7712. Retrieved 2023-07-12.
  4. ^ a b "BI 117 Anil Seth: Being You | Brain Inspired". Retrieved 2023-07-12.
  5. ^ Cooke, Emily (2023-02-23). "How I wrote a popular science book about consciousness — and why (Interview with Anil Seth)". Nature. doi:10.1038/d41586-023-00541-z. PMID 36823269. S2CID 257152610.
  6. ^ a b "Naturalizing Consciousness: Review of "Being You" by Anil Seth | Naturalism.org". Naturalism. Retrieved 2023-07-12.
  7. ^ Freud, Sigmund (2011-12-04). "Traumatic Fixation—The Unconscious". A General Introduction to Psychoanalysis. Translated by Hall, G. Stanley (Granville Stanley).
  8. ^ Chang, Hasok (2007). Inventing temperature: measurement and scientific progress. Oxford studies in philosophy of science (1. issued as paperback ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-533738-9.
  9. ^ Sinitsyn, Dmitry O.; Poydasheva, Alexandra G.; et al. (2020-11-27). "Detecting the Potential for Consciousness in Unresponsive Patients Using the Perturbational Complexity Index". Brain Sciences. 10 (12): 917. doi:10.3390/brainsci10120917. ISSN 2076-3425. PMC 7760168. PMID 33260944.
  10. ^ Tononi, G. (1998-12-04). "Consciousness and Complexity". Science. 282 (5395): 1846–1851. doi:10.1126/science.282.5395.1846. PMID 9836628.
  11. ^ Seth, Anil K.; Barrett, Adam B.; Barnett, Lionel (2011-10-13). "Causal density and integrated information as measures of conscious level". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences. 369 (1952): 3748–3767. doi:10.1098/rsta.2011.0079. ISSN 1364-503X. PMID 21893526. S2CID 12788294.
  12. ^ "Anil Seth: "Reality is a controlled hallucination"". CCCB LAB. 2022-11-22. Retrieved 2023-07-15.
  13. ^ Anscombe, Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret (1971). An Introduction to Wittgenstein's Tractatus. University of Pennsylvania Press. p. 151. ISBN 978-0-8122-1019-4.
  14. ^ Tiehen, Justin (2022-03-29). "Perception as controlled hallucination". Analytic Philosophy. doi:10.1111/phib.12268. ISSN 2153-9596.
  15. ^ Kveraga, Kestutis; Ghuman, Avniel S.; Bar, Moshe (2007-11-01). "Top-down predictions in the cognitive brain". Brain and Cognition. 65 (2): 145–168. doi:10.1016/j.bandc.2007.06.007. ISSN 0278-2626. PMC 2099308. PMID 17923222.
  16. ^ Kant, Immanuel (2003-07-01). "Chapter I. Of the Paralogisms of Pure Reason". The Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Meiklejohn, J. M. D. (John Miller Dow).
  17. ^ Hume, David (2003-12-01). "SECT. VI. OF PERSONAL IDENTITY". A Treatise of Human Nature.
  18. ^ Seth, Anil K.; Tsakiris, Manos (November 2018). "Being a Beast Machine: The Somatic Basis of Selfhood". Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 22 (11): 969–981. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2018.08.008. ISSN 1364-6613. PMID 30224233. S2CID 52287016.
  19. ^ Clarke, Peter G.H. (February 2013). "The Libet experiment and its implications for conscious will" (PDF). faraday.cam.ac.uk. Retrieved July 16, 2023.
  20. ^ Schurger, Aaron; Sitt, Jacobo D.; Dehaene, Stanislas (2012-10-16). "An accumulator model for spontaneous neural activity prior to self-initiated movement". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 109 (42): E2904-13. doi:10.1073/pnas.1210467109. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 3479453. PMID 22869750.
  21. ^ "BBC Radio 4 - The Life Scientific, Anil Seth on consciousness, Do we have free will?". www.bbc.co.uk. Retrieved 2023-07-16.
  22. ^ Evans, E. P. (Edward Payson) (1906). The criminal prosecution and capital punishment of animals. University of California Libraries. London : W. Heinemann.
  23. ^ "The 49 Most Fascinating, Mind-Blowing, Challenging, Hilarious, and Urgent Titles of the Year". Bloomberg. Retrieved 2023-07-13.
  24. ^ "The best books of 2021". The Economist. ISSN 0013-0613. Retrieved 2023-07-13.
  25. ^ Sample, Ian (2021-12-07). "The best science books of 2021". The Guardian. ISSN 0261-3077. Retrieved 2023-07-13.
  26. ^ Cookson, Clive. "Best books of 2021: Science". Financial Times. Retrieved 2023-07-13.
  27. ^ Warburton, Nigel. "The Best Philosophy Books of 2021". Five Books. Retrieved 2023-07-13.
  28. ^ Vince, Gaia (2021-08-25). "Being You by Professor Anil Seth review – the exhilarating new science of consciousness". The Guardian. ISSN 0261-3077. Retrieved 2023-07-12.
  29. ^ Bender, M. (2021). Being You: A New Science of Consciousness. Scientific American, 325(4), 87.
  30. ^ Haas, Felix (March 2022). "Being You: A New Science of Consciousness by Anil Seth". World Literature Today. 96 (2): 72–73. doi:10.1353/wlt.2022.0093. ISSN 1945-8134. S2CID 247162023.
  31. ^ Baggini, Julian (2021-12-09). "'Being You' Review: Why We Have a Sense of Self". Wall Street Journal. ISSN 0099-9660. Retrieved 2023-07-12.