Jump to content

Antireductionism: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Vanished user (talk | contribs)
Better article here.
Undid revision 168312839 by Adam Cuerden (talk)rvt these are not the same subject
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Wikify|date=April 2007}}
#REDIRECT[[holism in science]]
'''Antireductionism''' is the opposite of reductionism.<ref>[http://www.drury.edu/ess/philsci/KleeCh5.html ''Reductionism, Antireductionism, and Supervenience'']</ref> Although ''"breaking complex phenomena into parts, is a key method in science,"''<ref>[http://www.geocities.com/lclane2/reductionism.html ''Reductionism vs. obscurantism''] by Les Lane</ref> there are those complex phenomena (e.g. in [[psychology]], [[sociology]], [[ecology]]) where some resistance to or rebellion against this approach arises, primarily due to the perceived shortcomings of [[reductionism]]. When such situations arise, people quite naturally search for ideas that supply ''"an effective antidote against reductionism, [[scientism]], and psychiatric hubris.'"''<ref>
Jennifer Radden (Ed.) [http://www.oup.com/uk/catalogue/?ci=9780195149531 ''The Philosophy of Psychiatry: A Companion'']</ref> This in essence forms the philosophical basis for antireductionism. Such rebellions against [[reductionism]] also implicitly carry some critique of the [[scientific method]] itself, which engenders suspicion among scientists that antireductionism must inherently be flawed.

Antireductionism objections to reductionism often arise in academic fields such as [[history]], [[economics]], [[anthropology]], [[medicine]], and [[biology]] as disattisfaction with attempts to explain complex phenomena through being reduced to simplistic, ill-fitting models, which do not provide much insight about the matter in hand.
<ref>[http://www.novartisfound.org.uk/catalog/213abs.htm ''Reductionism and Antireductionism''] by Thomas Nagel</ref> Some objections propose that reductionism might even be more generally a flawed approach.{{Views needing attribution|date=June 2007}} Clearly then, there is a spectrum of positions on this issue even within the above disciplines. Generally speaking, reductionism has only enjoyed limited success in sociology, history and ecology and there is some scepticism in those fields that overtly mathematical and [[quantitative]] approaches can yield much useful sense or insight; descriptive approaches appear to be preferred.{{Views needing attribution|date=June 2007}}

An example in psychology is the ''"[[ontology]] of events to provide an anti-reductionist answer to the mind/matter debate [and]...the impossibility of intertranslating the two [[idioms]] by means of psychophysical laws blocks any analytically reductive relation between...the mental and the physical."''<ref>[http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/oso/public/content/philosophy/0199246270/toc.html Essays on Actions and Events] by Donald Davidson</ref>

As Alex Rosenberg and Kaplan point out, ''"physicalism and antireductionism are the ruling [[orthodoxy]] in the philosophy of biology...[yet] both reductionists and antireductionists accept that given our [[cognitive]] interests and limitations, non-molecular explanations may not be improved, corrected or grounded in molecular ones."''<ref>[http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/PHILSCI/journal/issues/v72n1/720114/brief/720114.abstract.html ''How to Reconcile Physicalism and Antireductionism about Biology''] by Alex Rosenberg and D. M. Kaplan</ref>

This is ''"one of the central problems in the philosophy of psychology...an updated version of the old mind-body problem: how levels of theories in the behavioral and brain sciences relate to one another. Many contemporary philosophers of mind believe that cognitive-psychological theories are not reducible to neurological theories...most nonreductive [[physicalist]]s prefer the idea of a one-way dependence of the mental on the physical."''<ref>[http://mitpress.mit.edu/catalog/item/default.asp?ttype=2&tid=7434 ''Psychoneural Reduction The New Wave''] by John Bickle</ref>

==References==
{{reflist}}

==See also==
* [[Alexander Rosenberg]]
* [[E.F. Schumacher]]
* [[A Guide for the Perplexed]]
* [[Antiscience]]
* [[Philosophy of Mind]]
* [[Nonreductive physicalism]]
* [[Evolution]]

==External links==
* [http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/oso/public/content/philosophy/0199246270/toc.html Donald Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events, OUP, 2001, ISBN-10: 0-19-924627-0]
* [http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/PHILSCI/journal/issues/v72n1/720114/brief/720114.abstract.html Alex Rosenberg and D. M. Kaplan, How to Reconcile Physicalism and Antireductionism about Biology, Philosophy of Science, Volume 72.1, January 2005, pp.43-68, abstract]
* [http://cogprints.org/4042/ Laubichler, M.D./Wagner, G.P. 2001. How molecular is molecular developmental biology? A reply to (Rosenberg 1997). Biology and Philosophy 16: 53—68 Rosenberg, A. 1997. Reductionism redux: Computing the embryo. Biology and Philosophy 12: 445—470...and..Bolender, John (1995) Is Multiple Realizability Compatible with Antireductionism?. The Southern Journal of Philosophy XXXIII:pp. 129-142.]
* [http://mitpress.mit.edu/catalog/item/default.asp?ttype=2&tid=7434 Psychoneural Reduction The New Wave, John Bickle, Bradford Books, March 1998, ISBN 0-262-02432-2 Abstract]
[[Category:Philosophy of science]]

Revision as of 15:40, 31 October 2007

Antireductionism is the opposite of reductionism.[1] Although "breaking complex phenomena into parts, is a key method in science,"[2] there are those complex phenomena (e.g. in psychology, sociology, ecology) where some resistance to or rebellion against this approach arises, primarily due to the perceived shortcomings of reductionism. When such situations arise, people quite naturally search for ideas that supply "an effective antidote against reductionism, scientism, and psychiatric hubris.'"[3] This in essence forms the philosophical basis for antireductionism. Such rebellions against reductionism also implicitly carry some critique of the scientific method itself, which engenders suspicion among scientists that antireductionism must inherently be flawed.

Antireductionism objections to reductionism often arise in academic fields such as history, economics, anthropology, medicine, and biology as disattisfaction with attempts to explain complex phenomena through being reduced to simplistic, ill-fitting models, which do not provide much insight about the matter in hand. [4] Some objections propose that reductionism might even be more generally a flawed approach.[attribution needed] Clearly then, there is a spectrum of positions on this issue even within the above disciplines. Generally speaking, reductionism has only enjoyed limited success in sociology, history and ecology and there is some scepticism in those fields that overtly mathematical and quantitative approaches can yield much useful sense or insight; descriptive approaches appear to be preferred.[attribution needed]

An example in psychology is the "ontology of events to provide an anti-reductionist answer to the mind/matter debate [and]...the impossibility of intertranslating the two idioms by means of psychophysical laws blocks any analytically reductive relation between...the mental and the physical."[5]

As Alex Rosenberg and Kaplan point out, "physicalism and antireductionism are the ruling orthodoxy in the philosophy of biology...[yet] both reductionists and antireductionists accept that given our cognitive interests and limitations, non-molecular explanations may not be improved, corrected or grounded in molecular ones."[6]

This is "one of the central problems in the philosophy of psychology...an updated version of the old mind-body problem: how levels of theories in the behavioral and brain sciences relate to one another. Many contemporary philosophers of mind believe that cognitive-psychological theories are not reducible to neurological theories...most nonreductive physicalists prefer the idea of a one-way dependence of the mental on the physical."[7]

References

See also

External links