Jump to content

Corax of Syracuse

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This is an old revision of this page, as edited by 195.195.249.9 (talk) at 13:40, 11 November 2022 (→‎Contributions to rhetorical study). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

Corax (Greek: Κόραξ, Korax; fl. 5th century BC) was one of the founders (along with Tisias) of ancient Greek rhetoric. Some scholars contend that both founders are merely legendary personages, others that Corax and Tisias were the same person, described in one fragment as "Tisias, the Crow" (corax is ancient Greek for "crow"). And according to Aristotle, Empedocles was the actual founder of rhetoric, but this is also unlikely.[1] It is believed that William Shakespeare derived the name Sycorax from Corax of Syracuse.[2] Corax is said to have lived in Sicily in the 5th century BC, when Thrasybulus, tyrant of Syracuse, was overthrown and a democracy formed.

Contributions to rhetorical study

Corax originated some of the basic principles and laid the groundwork for the Greek scholars to follow – particularly Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle. They tos teachings himself; they were all recorded and published by his pupil, Tisias.[3]

The famous but apocryphal story of how Tisias tried to cheat his teacher is passed down in the introductions to various rhetorical treatises.[4] According to this tale, Tisias convinced Corax to waive his customary teacher's fee until Tisias won his first lawsuit; however, Tisias conspicuously avoided going to court. Corax then sued Tisias for the fee, arguing that if Corax won the case, he would get his pay, but if Tisias won (his first lawsuit) he would then have to fulfill the terms of their original agreement. Some versions of the tale end here. Others attribute a counterargument to Tisias: that if he lost the case, he would escape paying under the terms of the original agreement (having not yet won a lawsuit), and if he won there would still be no penalty, since he would be awarded the money at issue. At this point, the judge throws both of them out of court, remarking "κακοῦ κόρακος κακὸν ᾠόν" ("a bad egg from a bad crow").[5]

Logic

Corax is probably best known for developing the "reverse-probability argument", also known as the Art of Corax. If a person is accused of a crime which he is not likely to have committed (for example, a small man physically attacking a large man, against whom he is almost certainly doomed to fail), his defense will be that it is unlikely that the crime occurred. His argument draws on the lack of means of the accused. However, if a person is accused of a crime which he is likely to have committed (in the case of a larger man attacking a smaller man), he can also use the defense that it is unlikely that he did it, for the very reason that it appears too probable. This man draws on the lack of prospect of getting away unsuspected. It works by anticipating the audience's expectations, and then combatting that expectation with a countermove. This pattern of anticipating and then contradicting an audience's expectation has continued to be a typical move in reverse probability arguments to this day.[6]

Of course, another countermove of this same type can also be employed (it could be argued that the large man could have committed the crime precisely because he thought he would be too obvious a suspect), and then another, and then another. For this reason, the Art of Corax has been labeled a "logical paradox". This method of argumentation has also been called quasi-logical: "it maintains that self-referential logic that is typical of the human mind even if it is circular."[7]

References

  1. ^ Hinks, D. A. G. (1940). "Tisias and Corax and the Invention of Rhetoric". The Classical Quarterly. 34.1 (2): 61. doi:10.1017/S0009838800009125. S2CID 170364394.
  2. ^ Harder, Dan (June 3, 2010). "The Origins of Sycorax". Retrieved August 25, 2010.
  3. ^ Cite error: The named reference auto was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  4. ^ e.g. R4 in H. Rabe, Prolegomenon Sylloge, Rhetores Graeci, XIV, Teubner, Leipzig 1931
  5. ^ Suda, #171 under "K"
  6. ^ Kraus, Manfred (2010). "Perelman's Interpretation of Reverse Probability Arguments as a Dialectical Mise En Abyme". Philosophy and Rhetoric. 43 (4): 362–382. doi:10.5325/philrhet.43.4.0362.
  7. ^ Goebel, George H. (1989). "Probability in the Earliest Rhetorical Theory". Mnemosyne. 42 (1): 41–53. doi:10.1163/156852589X00047.