Maine de Biran
Maine de Biran | |
---|---|
Born | |
Died | July 20, 1824 | (aged 57)
Other names | François-Pierre-Gonthier Maine de Biran (full name) |
Era | Modern philosophy |
Region | Western philosophy |
School | French Spiritualism |
Notable ideas | "Volo, ergo sum" |
François-Pierre-Gonthier Maine de Biran (November 29, 1766 – July 20, 1824), usually known simply as Maine de Biran, was a French philosopher.
Life
Maine de Biran was born at Bergerac. The name Maine he assumed (some time before 1787) from an estate called Le Maine, near Mouleydier. After studying with distinction at Périgueux, he entered the life guards of King Louis XVI of France, and was present at Versailles during the events of October 1789. He entered politics and was part of the Conseil des Cinq Cents.[3] On the breaking up of the gardes du corps Biran retired to his patrimonial inheritance of Grateloup, near Bergerac, where he avoided the excesses of the French Revolution.
It was at this period that, to use his own words, he "passed per saltum from frivolity to philosophy". He began with psychology, which he made the study of his life. After the Reign of Terror, Maine de Biran took part in politics. Having been excluded from the Council of the Five Hundred on suspicion of royalism, he took part with his friend Joseph Lainé in the commission of 1813, which first expressed direct opposition to the will of the emperor Napoleon. After the restoration of the monarchy, he became treasurer to the chamber of deputies, retiring during each autumn recess to study at home. The exact date of his death is uncertain.
Works
Maine de Biran's philosophical reputation has suffered because of his obscure and laboured style, and the fact that only a few of the least characteristic of his writings appeared during his lifetime: the essay on habit (Sur l'influence de l'habitude, 1803), a critical review of Pierre Laromiguière's lectures (1817), and the philosophical portion of the article "Leibnitz" in the Biographie universelle (1819). A treatise on the analysis of thought (Sur la décomposition de la pensée) was never printed. In 1834 these writings, together with the essay entitled Nouvelles considérations sur les rapports du physique et du moral de l'homme, were published by Victor Cousin, who in 1841 added three volumes, under the title Œuvres philosophiques de Maine de Biran. But the publication (in 1859) by Édouard Naville (from manuscripts placed at his father's disposal by Biran's son) of the Œuvres inédites de Maine de Biran, in three volumes, first rendered possible a connected view of his philosophical development.
At first a sensualist, like Condillac and John Locke, next an intellectualist, he finally became a mystical theosophist. The Essai sur les fondements de la psychologie represents the second stage of his philosophy, the fragments of the Nouveaux essais d'anthropologie the third. Maine de Biran's early essays in philosophy were written from the point of view of Locke and Condillac, but showed signs of his later interests. Dealing with the formation of habits, he is compelled to note that passive impressions do not furnish a complete or adequate explanation. With Laromiguière he distinguishes attention as an active effort, of no less importance than the passive receptivity of sense, and like Joseph Butler, he distinguishes passively formed customs from active habits. He concluded that Condillac's notion of passive receptivity as the one source of conscious experience was an error of method – in short, that the mechanical mode of viewing consciousness as formed by external influence was fallacious and deceptive. For it he proposed to substitute the genetic method, whereby human conscious experience might be exhibited as growing or developing from its essential basis in connection with external conditions. The essential basis he finds in the real consciousness, of self as an active striving power, and the stages of its development, corresponding to what one may call the relative importance of the external conditions and the reflective clearness of self-consciousness he designates as the affective, the perceptive and the reflective. In connexion with this Biran treats most of the obscure problems which arise in dealing with conscious experience, such as the mode by which the organism is cognized, the mode by which the organism is distinguished from extra-organic things, and the nature of those general ideas by which the relations of things are known to us – cause, power, force, etc.
In the last stage of his philosophy, Biran distinguished the animal existence from the human, under which the three forms above noted are classed. And both from the life of the spirit, in which human thought is brought into relation with the supersensible, divine system of things. This stage is left imperfect. Altogether Biran's work presents a very remarkable specimen of deep metaphysical thinking directed by preference to the psychological aspect of experience.
Criticism
Equating "cause" with "force"
Schopenhauer,[4] claimed that "No one has carried this confusion, or rather identification, of natural force with cause so far as Maine de Biran has in his Nouvelles considérations des rapports du physique au moral, since this is essential to his philosophy." This confusion of force of nature and cause occurred often throughout the book. “[W]hen he speaks of causes, he hardly ever puts cause alone, but almost always says cause ou force….” Schopenhauer believed that the confusion was intentional. Biran was "conscious of identifying two disparate concepts in order to be able to make use of either of them according to the circumstances." Therefore he purposely equated cause with force in order "to keep the identification present in the reader’s mind."
Notes
- ^ Frederick Charles Copleston, A History of Philosophy, Volume 9, Continuum International Publishing Group, 2003, p. 23.
- ^ Frederick Charles Copleston, A History of Philosophy: Maine de Biran to Sartre, Paulist Press, 1946, p. 30
- ^ Herbermann, Charles, ed. (1913). Catholic Encyclopedia. New York: Robert Appleton Company. .
- ^ On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason, § 20
See also
References
- The Œuvres inédites of Maine de Biran by E. Naville contains an introductory study
- in 1887 appeared Science et psychologie: nouvelles œuvres inédites, with introduction by A. Bertrand
- O. Merton, Étude critique sur Maine de Biran (1865)
- E Naville, Maine de Biran, sa vie et ses pensées (1874)
- J. Gerard, Maine de Biran, essai sur sa philosophie (1876)
- Mayonade, Pensées et pages inédites de Maine de Biran (Périgueux, 1896)
- G. Allievo, Maine de Biran e la sua dottrina antropologica (Turin, 1896, in Memorie dell' accademia delle scienze, 2nd ser., xlv, pt. 2)
- A. Lang, Maine de Biran und die neuere Philosophie (Cologne, 1901)
- monographs by A. Kühtmann (Bremen, 1901) and M. Couailhac (1905)
- A. de La Valette Monbrun, Maine de Biran (1766–1824): essai de biographie historique et psychologique..., Paris, 1914.
- N. E. Truman in Cornell Studies in Philosophy, No. 5 (f 904) on Maine de Biran's Philosophy of Will.
- Michel Henry. The Essence of Manifestation. The Hague: Nijoff, 1973
- Michel Henry. Philosophy and Phenomenology of the Body. The Hague: Nijoff, 1975
public domain: Chisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). Encyclopædia Britannica (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. {{cite encyclopedia}}
: Missing or empty |title=
(help)
Portraits
- Drawing by Jean Bernard Duvivier, 1798 and published by de La Valette Monbrun in 1914