Nonrecursive ordinal
This article includes a list of general references, but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations. (September 2021) |
In mathematics, particularly set theory, non-recursive ordinals are large countable ordinals greater than all the recursive ordinals, and therefore can not be expressed using recursive ordinal notations.
The Church–Kleene ordinal and variants
The smallest non-recursive ordinal is the Church Kleene ordinal, , named after Alonzo Church and S. C. Kleene; its order type is the set of all recursive ordinals. Since the successor of a recursive ordinal is recursive, the Church–Kleene ordinal is a limit ordinal. It is also the smallest ordinal that is not hyperarithmetical, and the smallest admissible ordinal after (an ordinal is called admissible if .) The -recursive subsets of are exactly the subsets of .[1]
The notation is in reference to , the first uncountable ordinal, which is the set of all countable ordinals, analogously to how the Church-Kleene ordinal is the set of all recursive ordinals. Some old sources use to denote the Church-Kleene ordinal.[2]
For a set , A set is x-computable if it is computable from a Turing machine with an oracle state that queries x. The relativized Church–Kleene ordinal is the supremum of the order types of x-computable relations. The Friedman-Jensen-Sacks theorem states that for every countable admissible ordinal , there exists a set x such that .[3]
, first defined by Stephen G. Simpson[citation needed] is an extension of the Church–Kleene ordinal. This is the smallest limit of admissible ordinals, yet this ordinal is not admissible. Alternatively, this is the smallest α such that is a model of -comprehension.
Recursively ordinals
The th admissible ordinal is sometimes denoted by .[4][5]
Recursively "x" ordinals, where "x" typically represents a large cardinal property, are kinds of nonrecursive ordinals.[6]
An ordinal is called recursively inaccessible if it is admissible and a limit of admissibles. Alternatively, is recursively inaccessible iff is the th admissible ordinal,[5] or iff , an extension of Kripke–Platek set theory stating that each set is contained in a model of Kripke–Platek set theory. Under the condition that ("every set is hereditarily countable"), is recursively inaccessible iff is a model of -comprehension.[7]
An ordinal is called recursively hyperinaccessible if it is recursively inaccessible and a limit of recursively inaccessibles, or where is the th recursively inaccessible. Like "hyper-inaccessible cardinal", different authors conflict on this terminology.
An ordinal is called recursively Mahlo if it is admissible and for any -recursive function there is an admissible such that (that is, is closed under ).[2] Mirroring the Mahloness hierarchy, is recursively -Mahlo for an ordinal if it is admissible and for any -recursive function there is an admissible ordinal such that is closed under , and is recursively -Mahlo for all .[6]
An ordinal is called recursively weakly compact if it is -reflecting, or equivalently,[2] 2-admissible. These ordinals have strong recursive Mahloness properties, if α is -reflecting then is recursively -Mahlo.[6]
Weakenings of stable ordinals
An ordinal is stable if is a -elementary-substructure of , denoted .[8] These are some of the largest named nonrecursive ordinals appearing in a model-theoretic context, for instance greater than for any computably axiomatizable theory .[9]Proposition 0.7. There are various weakenings of stable ordinals:[1]
- A countable ordinal is called -stable iff .
- The smallest -stable ordinal is much larger than the smallest recursively weakly compact ordinal: it has been shown that the smallest -stable ordinal is -reflecting for all finite .[2]
- In general, a countable ordinal is called -stable iff .
- A countable ordinal is called -stable iff , where is the smallest admissible ordinal . The smallest -stable ordinal is again much larger than the smallest -stable or the smallest -stable for any constant .
- A countable ordinal is called -stable iff , where are the two smallest admissible ordinals . The smallest -stable ordinal is larger than the smallest -reflecting.
- A countable ordinal is called inaccessibly-stable iff , where is the smallest recursively inaccessible ordinal . The smallest inaccessibly-stable ordinal is larger than the smallest -stable.
- A countable ordinal is called Mahlo-stable iff , where is the smallest recursively Mahlo ordinal . The smallest Mahlo-stable ordinal is larger than the smallest inaccessibly-stable.
- A countable ordinal is called doubly -stable iff . The smallest doubly -stable ordinal is larger than the smallest Mahlo-stable.
Larger nonrecursive ordinals
- The least ordinal such that where is the smallest nonprojectible ordinal.
- An ordinal is nonprojectible if is a limit of -stable ordinals, or; if the set is unbounded in .
- The ordinal of ramified analysis, often written as . This is the smallest such that is a model of second-order comprehension, or , without the powerset axiom.
- The least ordinal such that . This ordinal has been characterized by Toshiyasu Arai.[10]
- The least ordinal such that .
- The least stable ordinal.
References
- ^ a b D. Madore, A Zoo of Ordinals (2017). Accessed September 2021.
- ^ a b c d W. Richter, P. Aczel, Inductive Definitions and Reflecting Properties of Admissible Ordinals (1973, p.15). Accessed 2021 October 28.
- ^ Sacks, Gerald E. (1976), "Countable admissible ordinals and hyperdegrees", Advances in Mathematics, 19 (2): 213–262, doi:10.1016/0001-8708(76)90187-0
- ^ P. G. Hinman, Recursion-Theoretic Hierarchies (1978), pp.419--420. Perspectives in Mathematical Logic, ISBN 3-540-07904-1.
- ^ a b J. Barwise, Admissible Sets and Structures (1976), pp.174--176. Perspectives in Logic, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 3-540-07451-1.
- ^ a b c Rathjen, Michael (1994), "Proof theory of reflection" (PDF), Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 68 (2): 181–224, doi:10.1016/0168-0072(94)90074-4
- ^ W. Marek, Some comments on the paper by Artigue, Isambert, Perrin, and Zalc (1976), ICM. Accessed 19 May 2023.
- ^ J. Barwise, Admissible Sets and Structures (1976), Cambridge University Press, Perspectives in Logic.
- ^ W. Marek, K. Rasmussen, Spectrum of L in libraries (WorldCat catalog) (EuDML page), Państwowe Wydawn. Accessed 2022-12-01.
- ^ T. Arai, A Sneak Preview of Proof Theory of Ordinals (1997, p.17). Accessed 2021 October 28.
- Church, Alonzo; Kleene, S. C. (1937), "Formal definitions in the theory of ordinal numbers.", Fundamenta Mathematicae, 28: 11–21, doi:10.4064/fm-28-1-11-21, JFM 63.0029.02
- Church, Alonzo (1938), "The constructive second number class", Bull. Amer. Math. Soc., 44 (4): 224–232, doi:10.1090/S0002-9904-1938-06720-1
- Kleene, S. C. (1938), "On Notation for Ordinal Numbers", Journal of Symbolic Logic, 3 (4), Vol. 3, No. 4: 150–155, doi:10.2307/2267778, JSTOR 2267778, S2CID 34314018
- Rogers, Hartley (1987) [1967], The Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability, First MIT press paperback edition, ISBN 978-0-262-68052-3
- Simpson, Stephen G. (2009) [1999], Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic, Perspectives in Logic, vol. 2, Cambridge University Press, pp. 246, 267, 292–293, ISBN 978-0-521-88439-6
- Richter, Wayne; Aczel, Peter (1974), Inductive Definitions and Reflecting Properties of Admissible Ordinals, pp. 312–313, 333, ISBN 0-7204-2276-0