Jump to content

Antinatalism

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This is an old revision of this page, as edited by Sirhu (talk | contribs) at 00:28, 11 May 2019 (Hyperlink). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

Antinatalism, or anti-natalism, is a philosophical position that assigns a negative value to birth. Antinatalists argue that people should abstain from procreation because it is morally bad (some also recognize the procreation of other sentient beings as morally bad). In scholarly and in literary writings, various ethical foundations have been adduced for antinatalism.[1] Some of the earliest surviving formulations of the idea that it would be better not to have been born come from ancient Greece.[2] The term antinatalism is in opposition to the term natalism or pro-natalism, and was used probably for the first time as the name of the position by Théophile de Giraud (born 1968) in his book L'art de guillotiner les procréateurs: Manifeste anti-nataliste.[3]

In religions

The teaching of the Buddha (c. 400 BCE), among other Four Noble Truths and the beginning of Mahāvagga, is interpreted by Hari Singh Gour (1870–1949) as follows:

Buddha states his propositions in the pedantic style of his age. He throws them into a form of sorites; but, as such, it is logically faulty and all he wishes to convey is this: Oblivious of the suffering to which life is subject, man begets children, and is thus the cause of old age and death. If he would only realize what suffering he would add to by his act, he would desist from the procreation of children; and so stop the operation of old age and death.[4]

The Marcionites believed that the visible world is an evil creation of a crude, cruel, jealous, angry demiurge, Yahweh. According to this teaching, people should oppose him, abandon his world, not create people, and trust in the good God of mercy, foreign and distant.[5][6][7]

The Encratites observed that birth leads to death. In order to conquer death, people should desist from procreation: "not produce fresh fodder for death".[8][9][10]

The Manichaeans,[11][12][13] the Bogomils[14][15][16] and the Cathars[17][18][19] believed that procreation sentences the soul to imprisonment in evil matter. They saw procreation as an instrument of an evil god, demiurge, or of Satan that imprisons the divine element in matter and thus causes the divine element to suffer.

Theodicy and anthropodicy

Julio Cabrera considers the issue of being a creator in relation to theodicy and argues that just as it is impossible to defend the idea of a good God as creator, it is also impossible to defend the idea of a good man as creator. In parenthood, the human parent imitates the divine parent, in the sense that education could be understood as a form of pursuit of "salvation", the "right path" for a child. However, a human being could decide that it is better not to suffer at all than to suffer and be offered the later possibility of salvation from suffering. In Cabrera's opinion, evil is associated not with the lack of being, but with the suffering and dying of those that are alive. So, on the contrary, evil is only and obviously associated with being.[20]

Karim Akerma, due to the moral problem of man as creator, introduces anthropodicy, a twin concept for theodicy. He is of the opinion that the less faith in the Almighty Creator-God there is, the more urgent the question of anthropodicy becomes. Akerma thinks that for those who want to lead ethical lives, the causation of suffering requires a justification. Man can no longer shed responsibility for the suffering that occurs by appealing to an imaginary entity that sets moral principles. For Akerma, antinatalism is a consequence of the collapse of theodicy endeavours and the failure of attempts to establish an anthropodizee. According to him, there is no metaphysics nor moral theory that can justify the production of new people, and therefore anthropodicy is indefensible as well as theodicy.[21]

Peter Wessel Zapffe

Peter Wessel Zapffe (1899–1990) viewed humans as a biological paradox. According to him, consciousness has become over-evolved in humans, thereby making us incapable of functioning normally like other animals: cognition gives us more than we can carry. Our frailness and insignificance in the cosmos are visible to us. We want to live, and yet because of how we have evolved, we are the only species whose members are conscious that they are destined to die. We are able to analyze the past and the future of ourselves and others, as well as to imagine the suffering of billions of people (in addition to other living beings) and feel compassion for their suffering. We yearn for justice and meaning in a world where neither occur. This ensures that the lives of conscious individuals are tragic. We have desires: spiritual needs which reality is unable to satisfy, and our species still exists only because we limit our awareness of what that reality actually entails. Human existence amounts to a tangled network of defense mechanisms, which can be observed both individually and socially, in our everyday behavior patterns. According to Zapffe, humanity should cease this self-deception, and the natural consequence would be its extinction by abstaining from procreation.[22][23][24]

Negative ethics

Julio Cabrera proposes a concept of "negative ethics" in opposition to "affirmative" ethics, meaning ethics that affirm being.[20][25][26][27][28] He describes procreation as a unilateral and non-consensual sending of a human being into an immoral, painful and dangerous situation. For Cabrera, this situation, human life, is "structurally negative" in that its constitutive components are inherently adverse. The most prominent of these components are, according to him, the following:

  • (A) The being acquired by a human at birth is decreasing (or "waning"), as it begins to end since its emergence, following a single and irreversible direction of decay and decline, of which complete consummation can occur at any moment.
  • (B) From the beginning of its emergence the human being is affected by three types of friction: physical pain (in the form of illnesses, accidents and catastrophes to which it is always exposed); discouragement (a category that encompasses phenomena such as lack of will, fatigue, lack of strength, feeling of meaninglessness, lack of motivation, boredom and depression); and "moral impediment". According to negative ethics, humans are "morally disqualified": we are not able to act morally towards everyone in all circumstances. This impediment does not occur because of an intrinsic "evil" of human nature, but because of the structural situation in which the human being has always been. In this situation, humans are cornered by various kinds of pain, space for action is limited, and different interests often conflict with each other. We do not have to have bad intentions to treat others with disregard; we are compelled to do so in order to survive, pursue our projects and escape from suffering. For Cabrera, moral impediment is the worst thing in human life and in procreation: by procreating, one creates another human who will not be able to live morally. Cabrera also draws attention to the fact that life is associated with the constant risk of one experiencing strong physical pain, which is common in human life, for example as a result of a serious illness, and maintains that the mere existence of such possibility impedes us morally, as well as that because of it, we can at any time lose, as a result of its occurrence, the possibility of a dignified, moral functioning even to a minimal extent.
  • (C) The human being is equipped with mechanisms of creation of positive values of all kinds (moral, aesthetic, religious, scientific, erotic, artistic, etc.) that work as defense against A and B, mechanisms that the human must keep constantly active. According to Cabrera, all positive values that appear within human life are reactive and palliative; they are introduced by the permanent, anxious and uncertain struggle against the decreasing and attrited being gained at birth, and are ultimately defeated by its full consummation. Cabrera believes that a huge number of humans around the world cannot withstand this steep struggle against the terminal structure of their being, and this leads to destructive consequences for them and others: suicides, major or minor mental illnesses, or aggressive behavior. He accepts that life may, under normal circumstances and even in abnormal and dramatic circumstances, be bearable (though, for example, it may become unbearable in the face of a serious illness or great social injustice), and also that humans are capable – through their own merits and efforts – to make life not only bearable but even very pleasant (but not everyone's life, for according to Cabrera, the price of the pleasant life of some can often be the unpleasant life of others), however, he considers it problematic to procreate someone so that they can try to make their life pleasant by struggling against the difficult and oppressive situation we place them in by procreating. It seems more reasonable, in Cabrera's view, simply not to put them in the situation to which they will have to react, when its results are always uncertain. He concludes that: "whatever we say to ourselves so that we can continue to live, it has no sense for someone who does not yet exist".

Cabrera calls the set of these characteristics A–C "terminality of being".

Cabrera regards procreation as an ontological and total manipulation: one's very being is manufactured and used, so in contrast to intra-worldly cases where someone is placed in a harmful situation, in the case of procreation no chance of defense against that act is even available. According to Cabrera, manipulation in procreation is visible primarily in the unilateral and non-consensual character of the act, so that procreation is per se and inevitably asymmetrical; be it a product of forethought, or a product of carelessness, it is always connected with the interests (or disinterests) of other humans, not the created human. In addition, Cabrera points out that in his view the manipulation of procreation is generally not limited to the act of creation itself, but is continued in the process of raising the child, where they are shaped according to the preferences of the parents and for their satisfaction. He emphasizes that although it is not possible to avoid manipulation during procreation, it is perfectly possible to avoid procreation itself, and that then no moral rule is violated and the child is not harmed in any way. According to Cabrera, in ethics, including affirmative ethics, there is one overarching concept which he calls the "Minimal Ethical Articulation", "MEA" (previously translated into English as "Fundamental Ethical Articulation" and "FEA"): the consideration of other people's interests, not manipulating them and not harming them. Procreation for him is an obvious violation of MEA. In his view, values included in the MEA are widely accepted by affirmative ethics, they are even their basics, and if approached radically, they should lead to the refusal of procreation. Cabrera distinguishes between "structural death" ("SD", or simply mortality), the process of dying initiated by birth, and "punctual death" ("PD"), the moment one ceases to exist. In his view, recognizing death (in the sense of SD) as bad and regretting having to die, should be identical to recognizing birth as bad and regretting being born, since it is not possible to be born in a non-mortal way.

Kantian imperative

Julio Cabrera,[29] David Benatar (born 1966),[30] and Karim Akerma[31] all argue that procreation is contrary to Immanuel Kant's practical imperative (according to Kant, a man should never be used as a means to an end, but always be an end in himself). They argue that a person can be created for the sake of his parents or other people, but that it is impossible to create someone for his own good; and that therefore, following Kant's recommendation, we should not create new people. Heiko Puls argues that Kant's considerations regarding parental duties and human procreation in general imply arguments for an ethically justified antinatalism. Kant, however, according to Puls, rejects this position in his teleology for meta-ethical reasons.[32]

Julio Cabrera, Seana Shiffrin, Gerald Harrison, Julia Tanner and Asheel Singh argue that procreation is morally problematic because of the impossibility of obtaining consent to create from the human who is to be created.

Julio Cabrera argues that procreation is a violation of autonomy because we are not able to obtain a human's consent when we act on this human's behalf through procreation, and that a rational agent, having reliable information about the human situation and the ability to speak about its possible coming into existence, might not want to be born and experience the harms associated with existence (this is a reference to a thought experiment proposed by Richard Hare, who claims that birth would be undoubtedly chosen).[33]

Seana Shiffrin lists four factors that in her opinion make the justification for having hypothetical consent to procreation a problem:

  • (1) great harm is not at stake if the action is not taken;
  • (2) if the action is taken, the harms suffered by the created person can be very severe;
  • (3) a person can not escape the imposed condition without very high cost (suicide is often a physically, emotionally, and morally excruciating option);
  • (4) the hypothetical consent procedure is not based on the values of the person who will bear the imposed condition.[34]

Gerald Harrison and Julia Tanner argue that when we want to significantly affect someone by our action and it is not possible to get their consent, then the default should be to not take such action. The exception is, according to them, actions by which we want to prevent greater harm of a person (for example, pushing someone out of the way of a falling piano). However, in their opinion, such actions certainly do not include procreation, because before taking this action a person does not exist.[35][36][37]

Asheel Singh emphasizes that one does not have to think that coming into existence is always an overall harm in order to recognize antinatalism as a correct view. In his opinion, it is enough to think that there is no moral right to inflict serious, preventable harms upon others without their consent.[38]

Death as a harm

Marc Larock presents a view which he calls "deprivationalism".[39] According to this view:

  • (1) Each person has an interest in acquiring a new satisfied preference.
  • (2) Whenever a person is deprived of a new satisfied preference this violates an interest and thus causes harm.

Larock argues that if a person is deprived of an infinite number of new satisfied preferences, they suffer an infinite number of harms and that such deprivation is death to which procreation leads.

All of us are brought into existence, without our consent, and over the course of our lives, we are acquainted with a multitude of goods. Unfortunately, there is a limit to the amount of good each of us will have in our lives. Eventually, each of us will die and we will be permanently cut off from the prospect of any further good. Existence, viewed in this way, seems to be a cruel joke.

Larock believes that it is not correct to neutralize his view by stating that death is also an infinitely great benefit for us, because it protects us from the infinite number of new frustrated preferences. He proposes a thought experiment in which we have two people, Mary and Tom. The first person, Mary, dies at the age of forty years as a result of complications caused by a degenerative disease. Mary would live for some more time, if not for the complications, but she would only experience bad things in her life, not good ones. The second person, Tom, dies the same age from the same illness, but in his case the disease is at such a stage of development that his body would no longer be able to function. According to Larock, it is bad when someone, like in the case of Tom, encounters the impossibility of continuing to derive good things from his life; everybody's life leads to such a point, if someone lives long enough and our intuitions do not tell us that it is generally good or even neutral. Therefore, we should reject the view that death is also an infinitely great benefit: because we think that Tom has been unlucky. In the case of Mary, our intuitions tell us that her misfortune is not as great as Tom's misfortune. Her misfortune is reduced by the fact that death saved her from the real prospect of experiencing bad things. We do not have the same intuition in Tom's case. No evil or good future was physically possible for him. Larock thinks that while the impossibility of experiencing future good things seems to us to be a harm, the mere lack of a logical possibility of experiencing future bad things does not seem to be a compensatory benefit to us. If so, there would be nothing strange in recognizing that Tom had not suffered any misfortune. But he is a victim of misfortune, just like Mary. However, Mary's misfortune does not seem to be so great because her death prevents great suffering. Larock is of the opinion that most people will see both cases in this way. This conclusion is supposed to lead to the fact that we recognize that there is an asymmetry between the harms and benefits that death brings.

Larock summarizes his view as follows:

The existence of every moral patient in our world rests on a crude moral miscalculation. As I see it, non-procreation is the best means of rectifying this mistake.

Negative utilitarianism

Negative utilitarianism argues that minimizing suffering has greater moral importance than maximizing happiness.

Hermann Vetter (born 1933) agrees with the assumptions of Jan Narveson (born 1936):[40]

  1. There is no moral obligation to produce a child even if we could be sure that it will be very happy throughout its life.
  2. There is a moral obligation not to produce a child if it can be foreseen that it will be unhappy.

However, he disagrees with the conclusion that Narveson draws:

  1. In general – if it can be foreseen neither that the child will be unhappy nor that it will bring disutility upon others – there is no duty to have or not to have a child.

Instead, he presents the following decision theoretic matrix:

child will be more or less happy child will be more or less unhappy
produce the child no duty fulfilled or violated duty violated
do not produce the child no duty fulfilled or violated duty fulfilled

Based on this, he concludes that we should not create people:[41][42]

It is seen immediately that the act "do not produce the child" dominates the act "produce the child" because it has equally good consequences as the other act in one case and better consequences in the other. So it is to be preferred to the other act as long as we cannot exclude with certainty the possibility that the child will be more or less unhappy; and we never can. So we have, instead of (3), the far-reaching consequence: (3') In any case, it is morally preferable not to produce a child.

Karim Akerma argues that utilitarianism requires the least metaphysical assumptions and is therefore the most convincing ethical theory. He believes that negative utilitarianism is the right one because the good things in life do not compensate for the bad things; first and foremost, the best things do not compensate for the worst things such as, for example, the experiences of terrible pain, the agonies of the wounded, sick or dying. In his opinion we also rarely know what to do to make people happy, but we know what to do so that people do not suffer: it is enough that they do not be created. What is important for Akerma in ethics is the striving for the least amount of suffering people (ultimately no one), not striving for the most amount of happy people, which, according to him, takes place at the expense of immeasurable suffering.[43][21]

Bruno Contestabile cites the story "The Ones Who Walk Away from Omelas" by Ursula K. Le Guin. In this story, the existence of the utopian city of Omelas and the good fortune of its inhabitants depend on the suffering of one child tortured in an isolated place and who can not be helped. The majority accepts this state of affairs and stay in the city, but there are those who do not agree with it, who do not want to participate in it and thus they "walk away from Omelas". Contestabile draws a parallel here: for Omelas to exist, the child must be tortured, and in the same way, the existence of our world is related to the fact that someone is constantly harmed. According to Contestabile, antinatalists can be seen just as "the ones who walk away from Omelas", who do not accept such a world, and who do not approve of its perpetuation. He poses the question: is all happiness able to compensate for the extreme suffering of even one person?[44]

David Benatar

David Benatar argues that there is a crucial asymmetry between the good and the bad things, such as pleasure and pain:

  1. the presence of pain is bad;
  2. the presence of pleasure is good;
  3. the absence of pain is good, even if that good is not enjoyed by anyone;
  4. the absence of pleasure is not bad unless there is somebody for whom this absence is a deprivation.[45][46]
Scenario A (X exists) Scenario B (X never exists)
(1) Presence of pain (Bad) (3) Absence of pain (Good)
(2) Presence of pleasure (Good) (4) Absence of pleasure (Not bad)

Regarding procreation, the argument follows that coming into existence generates both good and bad experiences, pain and pleasure, whereas not coming into existence entails neither pain nor pleasure. The absence of pain is good, the absence of pleasure is not bad. Therefore, the ethical choice is weighed in favor of non-procreation.

Benatar explains the above asymmetry using four other asymmetries that he considers quite plausible:

  • We have a moral obligation not to create unhappy people, and we have no moral obligation to create happy people. The reason why we think there is a moral obligation not to create unhappy people is that the presence of this suffering would be bad (for the sufferers) and the absence of the suffering is good (even though there is nobody to enjoy the absence of suffering). By contrast, the reason we think there is no moral obligation to create happy people is that although their pleasure would be good for them, the absence of pleasure when they do not come into existence will not be bad, because there will be no one who will be deprived of this good.
  • It is strange to mention the interests of a potential child as a reason why we decide to create it, and it is not strange to mention the interests of a potential child as a reason why we decide not to create it. That the child may be happy is not a morally important reason to create it. By contrast, that the child may be unhappy is an important moral reason to not create it. If the absence of pleasure is bad even if someone does not exist to experience its absence, we would have a significant moral reason to create a child, and to create as many children as possible. If, however, the absence of pain wouldn't be good even if someone would not experience this good, we would not have a significant moral reason not to create a child.
  • Someday we can regret for the sake of the good of a man whose existence was conditional on our decision, that we created them – a man can be unhappy and the presence of his pain would be a bad thing. But we will never feel regret for the sake of the good of a man whose existence was conditional on our decision, that we did not create him – a man will not be deprived of happiness, because he will never exist, and the absence of happiness will not be bad, because there will be no one who will be deprived of this good.
  • We feel sadness by the fact that somewhere people come into existence and suffer, and we feel no sadness by the fact that somewhere people did not come into existence in a place where there are happy people. When we know that somewhere people came into existence and suffer, we feel compassion. The fact that on some deserted island or planet people did not come into existence and suffer is good. This is because the absence of pain is good even when there is not someone who is experiencing this good. On the other hand, we do not feel sadness by the fact that on some deserted island or planet people did not come into existence and are not happy. This is because the absence of pleasure is bad only when someone exists to be deprived of this good.

According to Benatar, by creating a child, we are responsible not only for this child's suffering, but we may also be co-responsible for the suffering of further offspring of this child.[47]

Assuming that each couple has three children, an original pair's cumulative descendants over ten generations amount to 88,572 people. That constitutes a lot of pointless, avoidable suffering. To be sure, full responsibility for it all does not lie with the original couple because each new generation faces the choice of whether to continue that line of descendants. Nevertheless, they bear some responsibility for the generations that ensue. If one does not desist from having children, one can hardly expect one's descendants to do so.[48]

Benatar cites statistics showing where the creation of people leads. It is estimated that:

  • more than fifteen million people are thought to have died from natural disasters in the last 1,000 years,
  • approximately 20,000 people die every day from hunger,
  • an estimated 840 million people suffer from hunger and malnutrition,
  • between 541 CE and 1912, it is estimated that over 102 million people succumbed to plague,
  • the 1918 influenza epidemic killed 50 million people,
  • nearly 11 million people die every year from infectious diseases,
  • malignant neoplasms take more than a further 7 million lives each year,
  • approximately 3.5 million people die every year in accidents,
  • approximately 56.5 million people died in 2001, that is more than 107 people per minute,
  • before the twentieth century over 133 million people were killed in mass killings,
  • in the first 88 years of the twentieth century 170 million (and possibly as many as 360 million) people were shot, beaten, tortured, knifed, burned, starved, frozen, crushed, or worked to death; buried alive, drowned, hanged, bombed, or killed in any other of the myriad ways governments have inflicted death on unarmed, helpless citizens and foreigners,
  • there were 1.6 million conflict-related deaths in the sixteenth century, 6.1 million in the seventeenth century, 7 million in the eighteenth, 19.4 million in the nineteenth, and 109.7 million in the twentieth,
  • war-related injuries led to 310,000 deaths in 2000,
  • about 40 million children are maltreated each year,
  • more than 100 million currently living women and girls have been subjected to genital cutting,
  • 815,000 people are thought to have committed suicide in 2000[49] (currently, it is estimated that someone commits suicide every 40 seconds, more than 800,000 people per year).[50]

In addition to the philanthropic arguments, which are based on a concern for the humans who will be brought into existence, Benatar also posits that another path to antinatalism is the misanthropic argument[51] that can be summarized in his opinion as follows:

Another route to anti-natalism is via what I call a "misanthropic" argument. According to this argument humans are a deeply flawed and a destructive species that is responsible for the suffering and deaths of billions of other humans and non-human animals. If that level of destruction were caused by another species we would rapidly recommend that new members of that species not be brought into existence.[52]

Harming other animals

David Benatar,[53][54] Gunter Bleibohm (born 1947),[55] Gerald Harrison and Julia Tanner,[56] are attentive to the harm caused to other sentient beings by humans. They would say that billions of non-human animals are abused and slaughtered each year by our species for the production of animal products, for experimentation and after the experiments (when they are no longer needed), as a result of the destruction of habitats or other environmental damage and for sadistic pleasure. They tend to agree with animal rights thinkers that the harm we do to them is immoral. They consider the human species the most destructive on the planet, arguing that without new humans, there will be no harm caused to other sentient beings by new humans.

Some antinatalists are also vegetarians or vegans for moral reasons, and postulate that such views should complement each other as having a common denominator: not causing harm to other sentient beings.[57][58] This attitude was already present in Manichaeism and Catharism.[59]

Impact on the environment

Volunteers of the Voluntary Human Extinction Movement argue that human activity is the primary cause of environmental degradation, and therefore refraining from reproduction is "the humanitarian alternative to human disasters".[60][61][62]

Adoption instead of procreation

Herman Vetter,[41] Théophile de Giraud,[63] Tina Rulli[64] and Karim Akerma[65] argue that presently rather than engaging in the morally problematic act of procreation, one could do good by adopting already existing children. De Giraud emphasizes that, across the world, there are millions of existing children who need care.

Realism

Some antinatalists believe that most people do not evaluate reality accurately, which affects the desire to have children.

Peter Wessel Zapffe identifies four repressive mechanisms we use, consciously or not, to restrict our consciousness of life and the world:

  • isolation – an arbitrary dismissal from our consciousness and the consciousness of others about all negative thoughts and feelings associated with the unpleasant facts of our existence. In daily life, this manifests as a tacit agreement to remain silent on certain subjects – especially around children, to prevent instilling in them a fear of the world and what awaits them in life, before they will be able to learn other mechanisms.
  • anchoring – the creation and use of personal values to ensure our attachment to reality, such as parents, home, the street, school, God, the church, the State, morality, fate, the law of life, the people, the future, accumulation of material goods or authority, etc. This can be characterized as creating a defensive structure, "a fixation of points within, or construction of walls around, the liquid fray of consciousness", and defending the structure against threats.
  • distraction – shifting focus to new impressions to flee from circumstances and ideas we consider harmful or unpleasant.
  • sublimation – refocusing the tragic parts of life into something creative or valuable, usually through an aesthetic confrontation for the purpose of catharsis. We focus on the imaginary, dramatic, heroic, lyric or comic aspects of life, to allow ourselves and others an escape from their true impact.

According to Zapffe, depressive disorders are often "messages from a deeper, more immediate sense of life, bitter fruits of a geniality of thought".[22] Some studies seem to confirm this, it is said about the phenomenon of depressive realism, and Colin Feltham writes about antinatalism as one of its possible consequences.[66]

David Benatar citing numerous studies lists three phenomena described by psychologists, which, according to him, are responsible for the fact that our self-assessments are unreliable:

  1. Tendency towards optimism (or Pollyanna principle) – we have a positively distorted picture of our lives in the past, present, and future.
  2. Adaptation (or accommodation, habituation) – we adapt to negative situations and adjust our expectations accordingly.
  3. Comparison – for our self-assessments, more important than how our lives go is how our lives go in comparison with the lives of others. One of the effects of this is that negative aspects of life that affect everyone are not taken into account when assessing our own well-being. We are also more likely to compare ourselves with those who are worse off than those who are better off.

Benatar concludes:

The above psychological phenomena are unsurprising from an evolutionary perspective. They militate against suicide and in favour of reproduction. If our lives are quite as bad as I shall still suggest they are, and if people were prone to see this true quality of their lives for what it is, they might be much more inclined to kill themselves, or at least not to produce more such lives. Pessimism, then, tends not to be naturally selected.[67]

Thomas Ligotti (born 1953) draws attention to the similarity between Zapffe's philosophy and terror management theory. Terror management theory argues that humans are equipped with unique cognitive abilities beyond what is necessary for survival, which includes symbolic thinking, extensive self-consciousness, and perception of themselves as temporal beings aware of the finitude of their existence. The desire to live alongside our awareness of the inevitability of death triggers terror in us. Opposition to this fear is among our primary motivations. To escape it, we build defensive structures around ourselves to ensure our symbolic or literal immortality, to feel like valuable members of a meaningful universe, and to focus on protecting ourselves from immediate external threats.[68]

Abortion

Antinatalism can lead to a particular position on the morality of abortion.

According to David Benatar, one comes into existence in the morally relevant sense when consciousness arises, when a fetus becomes sentient, and up until that time an abortion is moral, whereas continued pregnancy would be immoral. Benatar refers to EEG brain studies and studies on the pain perception of the fetus, which states that fetal consciousness arises no earlier than between twenty-eight and thirty weeks of pregnancy, before which it is incapable of feeling pain.[69] Contrary to that, the latest report from the Royal College of Obstetricians and Gynaecologists showed that the fetus gains consciousness no earlier than week twenty-four of the pregnancy.[70] Some assumptions of this report regarding sentience of the fetus after the second trimester were criticized.[71] In a similar way argues Karim Akerma. He distinguishes between organisms that do not have mental properties and living beings that have mental properties. According to his view, which he calls the mentalistic view, a living being begins to exist when an organism (or another entity) produces a simple form of consciousness for the first time.[72][73]

Julio Cabrera believes that the moral problem of abortion is significantly different from the moral problem of procreation, because in the case of abortion, there is already an existing being in some point of its development process, and no longer a non-being. He emphasizes that it is difficult to determine whether we kill someone when we have an abortion, but he believes that in its strictly manipulative aspect, abortion is closer to procreation than to abstention, and in his view, the abortion of a healthy fetus is killing a human being and is therefore morally unjustifiable. According to Cabrera it is a violation of autonomy and is immoral for the same reason as procreation.[74]

Antinatalism and other animals

Some antinatalists recognize the procreation of non-human sentient animals as morally bad, and sterilization as morally good in their case. Karim Akerma defines antinatalism, that includes non-human sentient animals, as universal antinatalism[75] and he assumes such a position himself:

By sterilising animals, we can free them from being slaves to their instincts and from bringing more and more captive animals into the cycle of being born, contracting parasites, ageing, falling ill and dying; eating and being eaten.[76]

David Benatar emphasizes that his asymmetry applies to all sentient beings, and mentions that humans play a role in deciding how many animals there will be: humans breed other species of animals and are able to sterilize other species of animals.[77]

Magnus Vinding argues that the life of wild animals in their natural environment is generally very bad. He draws attention to phenomena such as dying before adulthood, starvation, diseases, parasites, infanticide, predation, being eaten alive. He cites research on what animal life looks like in the wild. One of eight male lion cubs survives into adulthood. Others die as a result of starvation, disease, and often fall victims to the teeth and claws of other lions. Attaining adulthood is much rarer for fish. Only twenty per two thousand male chinook salmon survive into adulthood. Vinding is of the opinion that if human lives and the survival of human children looked like this, current human values would disallow procreation; however, this is not possible when it comes to non-human animals, who are guided by instinct. He takes the view that even if one does not agree that procreation is always morally bad, one should recognize procreation in wildlife as morally bad and something that ought to be prevented (at least in theory, not necessarily in practice). He maintains that non-intervention cannot be defended if we reject speciesism, and that we should reject the unjustifiable dogma stating that what is happening in nature is what should be happening in nature.

We cannot allow ourselves to spuriously rationalize away the suffering that takes place in nature, and to forget the victims of the horrors of nature merely because that reality does not fit into our convenient moral theories, theories that ultimately just serve to make us feel consistent and good about ourselves in the face of an incomprehensibly bad reality.[78]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ K. Akerma, Antinatalismus – Ein Handbuch, epubli, 2017.
  2. ^ W. Tatarkiewicz, O szczęściu (On Happiness), Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe, 1979, pp. 420-421.
  3. ^ K. Akerma, Antinatalismus... op. cit., p. 301.
  4. ^ H. Singh Gour, The Spirit of Buddhism, Whitefish, Montana: Kessinger Publishing, 2005, pp. 286–288.
  5. ^ H. Jonas, The Gnostic Religion: The Message of the Alien God and the Beginnings of Christianity, Boston: Beacon Press, 1958, pp. 144–145.
  6. ^ P. Karavites, Evil, Freedom, and the Road to Perfection in Clement of Alexandria, Leiden: Brill, 1999, p. 94.
  7. ^ Clement of Alexandria, Stromateis, Books 1–3 (The Fathers of the Church, volume 85), Washington D.C.: CUA Press, 2010, pp. 263–271.
  8. ^ P. Brown, The Body and Society: Men, Women, and Sexual Renunciation in Early Christianity, New York: Columbia University Press, 1988, p. 96.
  9. ^ G. Quispel, Gnostica, Judaica, Catholica: Collected Essays of Gilles Quispel, Leiden: Brill, 2008, p. 228.
  10. ^ Clement of Alexandria, Stromateis, op. cit., pp. 295–296.
  11. ^ H. Jonas, The Gnostic..., op. cit., pp. 228 and 231.
  12. ^ I. Gardner and S.N.C. Lieu, Manichaean Texts from the Roman Empire, New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004, pp. 7 and 22.
  13. ^ S.G. Kochuthara, The Concept of Sexual Pleasure in the Catholic Moral Tradition, Rome: Gregorian Biblical BookShop, 2007, p. 165.
  14. ^ D. Obolensky, The Bogomils: A Study in Balkan Neo-Manichaeism, New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004, p. 114.
  15. ^ F. Curta, Southeastern Europe in the Middle Ages, 500–1250, New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006, p. 236.
  16. ^ J. Lacarrière, The Gnostics, London: Owen, 1977, p. 116.
  17. ^ M.J. Fromer, Ethical issues in Sexuality and Reproduction, St. Louis: Mosby, 1983, p. 110.
  18. ^ S. Runciman, The Medieval Manichee: A Study of the Christian Dualist Heresy, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1947, pp. 151–152.
  19. ^ D. Elliott, Spiritual Marriage: Sexual Abstinence in Medieval Wedlock, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995, pp. 133–134.
  20. ^ a b J. Cabrera, Projeto de Ética Negativa, São Paulo: Edicões Mandacaru, 1989 (second edition: A Ética e Suas Negações, Não nascer, suicídio e pequenos assassinatos, Rio De Janeiro: Rocco, 2011). [1] English translation of the first chapter.
  21. ^ a b K. Akerma, Verebben der Menschheit?: Neganthropie und Anthropodizee, Verlag Karl Alber, Freiburg im Breisgau: Verlag Karl Alber, 2000.
  22. ^ a b P.W. Zapffe, The Last Messiah, Philosophy Now, 2004, number 45, pp. 35–39.
  23. ^ P. W. Zapffe, Om det tragiske, Oslo: Pax Forlag, 1996.
  24. ^ P. W. Zapffe, H. Tønnessen, Jeg velger sannheten: En dialog mellom Peter Wessel Zapffe og Herman Tønnessen, Oslo: Universitets forlaget, 1983.
  25. ^ [2] J. Cabrera, A critique of affirmative morality (A reflection on death, birth and the value of life), Brasília: Julio Cabrera Editions, 2014 (English edition). J. Cabrera, Crítica de la moral afirmativa: Una reflexión sobre nacimiento, muerte y valor de la vida, Barcelona: Gedisa, 1996 (original Spanish edition, second edition in 2014).
  26. ^ J. Cabrera (editor), Ética Negativa: problemas e discussões, Goiânia: UFG, 2008.
  27. ^ [3] J. Cabrera, T. Lenharo di Santis, Porque te amo, Não nascerás!: Nascituri te salutant, Brasília: LGE, 2009. [4] English translation.
  28. ^ J. Cabrera, Discomfort and Moral Impediment: The Human Situation, Radical Bioethics and Procreation, Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2019. [5] A thirty-page extract on the publisher's website. J. Cabrera, Mal-estar e moralidade: situação humana, ética e procriação responsável, Brasília: UnB, 2018 (original Portuguese edition).
  29. ^ [6] J. Cabrera, T. Lenharo di Santis, Porque..., op. cit, pp. 52–67.
  30. ^ D. Benatar, Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006, pp. 129–131.
  31. ^ [7] K. Akerma, Theodicy shading off into Anthropodicy in Milton, Twain and Kant, Tabula Rasa. Die Kulturzeitung aus Mitteldeutschland, 2010, number 49.
  32. ^ H. Puls, Kant’s Justification of Parental Duties, Kantian Review 21 (1), 2016, pp. 53–75.
  33. ^ [8] J. Cabrera, T. Lenharo di Santis, Porque..., op. cit, pp. 66–79.
  34. ^ [9] S. Shiffrin, Wrongful Life, Procreative Responsibility, and the Significance of Harm, Cambridge University Press, 1999, p. 133.
  35. ^ [10] G. Harrison, J. Tanner, Better Not To Have Children, Think 2011, volume 10, issue 27, p. 113.
  36. ^ [11] G. Harrison, Antinatalism, Asymmetry, and an Ethic of Prima Facie Duties, South African Journal of Philosophy, volume 31, issue 1, 2012.
  37. ^ [12] G. Harrison, Antinatalism and Moral Particularism, Essays in Philosophy, volume 20, issue 1, Is Procreation Immoral?, article 5, 2019.
  38. ^ [13] A. Singh, Assessing anti-natalism: a philosophical examination of the morality of procreation, University of Johannesburg, 2012, p. 5.
  39. ^ [14] M. Larock, Possible preferences and the harm of existence, University of St. Andrews, 2009.
  40. ^ J. Narveson, Utilitarianism and New Generations, Mind 1967, LXXVI (301), pp. 62-67.
  41. ^ a b H. Vetter, The production of children as a problem for utilitarian ethics, Inquiry 12, 1969, pp. 445–447.
  42. ^ H. Vetter, Utilitarianism and New Generations, Mind, 1971, LXXX (318), pp. 301–302.
  43. ^ K. Akerma, Soll eine Menschheit sein? Eine fundamentalethische Frage, Cuxhaven-Dartford: Traude Junghans, 1995.
  44. ^ B. Contestabile, The Denial of the World from an Impartial View, Contemporary Buddhism: An Interdisciplinary Journal, volume 17, issue 1, Taylor and Francis, 2016.
  45. ^ D. Benatar, Why it is Better Never to Come Into Existence, American Philosophical Quarterly, 1997, volume 34, number 3, pp. 345–355.
  46. ^ D. Benatar, Better..., op. cit., pp. 30–40.
  47. ^ D. Benatar, Better..., op. cit., pp. 6–7.
  48. ^ D. Benatar, Better..., op. cit., pp. 6–7 (introduction).
  49. ^ D. Benatar, Better..., op. cit., pp. 88–92.
  50. ^ [15] International Association for Suicide Prevention, World Suicide Prevention Day.
  51. ^ D. Benatar, D. Wasserman, Debating Procreation: Is It Wrong To Reproduce?, Oxford University Press, New York 2015, pp. 87-121.
  52. ^ [16] D. Benatar, "We Are Creatures That Should Not Exist": The Theory of Anti-Natalism, The Critique, July 15, 2015.
  53. ^ D. Benatar, Better..., op. cit., p. 109.
  54. ^ D. Benatar, D. Wasserman, Debating..., op. cit., pp. 93– 99.
  55. ^ G. Bleibohm, Fluch der Geburt – Thesen einer Überlebensethik, Landau-Godramstein: Gegensich, 2011.
  56. ^ G. Harrison, J. Tanner, Better..., op. cit., pp. 113–121.
  57. ^ [17] K. Akerma, Ist der Vegetarismus ein Antinatalismus?, Pro iure animalis, March 24, 2014. [18] English translation.
  58. ^ [19] V. Pelley, This Extreme Sect of Vegans Thinks Your Baby Will Destroy the Planet, Marie Claire, January 29, 2018.
  59. ^ K. Akerma, Antinatalismus... op. cit., s. 305.
  60. ^ V. Baird, The No-nonsense Guide to World Population, Oxford: New Internationalist, 2011, p. 119.
  61. ^ [20] An NBC interview with Les U. Knight, founder of the Voluntary Human Extinction Movement.
  62. ^ [21] The official Voluntary Human Extinction Movement website.
  63. ^ [22] T. de Giraud, L'art de guillotiner les procréateurs: Manifeste anti-nataliste, Nancy: Le Mort-Qui-Trompe, 2006, p. 51.
  64. ^ T. Rulli, The Ethics of Procreation and Adoption, Philosophy Compass 11/6, 2016, pp. 305–315.
  65. ^ K. Akerma, Antinatalismus..., op. cit., p. 74.
  66. ^ C. Feltham, Depressive Realism: Interdisciplinary perspectives, Routledge, Abingdon 2016.
  67. ^ D. Benatar, Better..., op. cit., pp. 64–69.
  68. ^ T. Ligotti, The Conspiracy against the Human Race: A Contrivance of Horror, New York: Hippocampus Press, 2010, pp. 112–113.
  69. ^ D. Benatar, Better..., op. cit., pp. 132–162.
  70. ^ [23] Royal College of Obstetricians and Gynaecologists, Fetal Awareness – Review of Research and Recommendations for Practice, London: RCOG Press, 2010.
  71. ^ [24] M. W. Platt, Fetal awareness and fetal pain: the Emperor's new clothes, Archives of Disease in Childhood, 2011, volume 96, issue 4.
  72. ^ K. Akerma, Lebensende und Lebensbeginn: Philosophische Implikationen und mentalistische Begründung des Hirn-Todeskriterium, Lit: Hamburg 2006.
  73. ^ K. Akerma, Antinatalismus... op. cit., p. 404.
  74. ^ [25] J. Cabrera, T. Lenharo di Santis, op. cit, pp. 68–69, 77.
  75. ^ K. Akerma, Antinatalismus... op. cit., pp. 100-101.
  76. ^ [26] K. Akerma, Manifest zum antinatalismus. Zur Ethik des Antinatalismus. Für Nachkommenlosigkeit bei Mensch und Tier, pro-iure-animalis, July 2014. [27] English translation.
  77. ^ D. Benatar, Better..., op. cit., pp. 2–3 (introduction), 163.
  78. ^ [28] M. Vinding, The Speciesism of Leaving Nature Alone, and the Theoretical Case for "Wildlife Anti-Natalism", 2017, Apeiron, 8, pp. 169-183..