Jump to content

Salomon Maimon

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This is an old revision of this page, as edited by Jfdwolff (talk | contribs) at 15:56, 10 March 2014 (Reverted edits by TorahCafe (talk) to last version by Waacstats). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

Shlomo ben Yehoshua Maimon
Salomon Maimon
Born1753
Died22 November 1800
Era18th-century philosophy
RegionWestern Philosophy
SchoolGerman Idealism
Main interests
Epistemology, Metaphysics, Ethics
Notable ideas
Critique of Kant's Quid Juris and Quid Factis, the Doctrine of Differentials, the Principle of Determinability

Salomon ben Josua Maimon (Hebrew: שלמה מימון) was a German philosopher born of Jewish parentage in present-day Belarus.

Early years

Salomon Maimon was born in the town of Zhukov Borok near Mir in the Grand Duchy of Lithuania (modern Belarus), where his grandfather leased an estate from a Prince Karol Stanisław "Panie Kochanku" Radziwiłł[1]: 21–22 . He was taught Torah and Talmud, first by his father, and later by instructors in Mir. He was recognized as a prodigy in Talmudic studies, which he later described as "endless disputation without end or aim".[1]: 25  His parents fell on hard times, and betrothed him to two separate girls in order to take advantage of their dowries, leading to a bitter rivalry[1]: 26 . At the age of eleven he was married to one of the two prospects, a girl from Nesvizh. At the age 14 he was already a father and was making money by teaching Talmud. Later he learned some German from books and walked all the way to Slutsk, where he met a rabbi who had studied in Germany. He borrowed German books on physics, optics and medicine from him. After that he became determined to study further. He abandoned his family at the age of 22.

Interest in Kabbalah

Maimon describes how he took an interest in kabbalah, and made a pilgrimage to the court of the Maggid of Mezritch. He ridicules the Maggid's adherents for their enthusiasm, and charges the Maggid with manipulating his followers[1]: 30 . He also wrote that the Maggid's ideas are "closer to correct ideas of religion and morals" than those he was taught in cheder[1]: 30 ."

In Germany

At the age of 25 Maimon left his home area for Germany. Maimon's first attempt to take up residence in Berlin in 1778 failed. He was expelled for possession of the Moreh Nebukhim of Maimonides. A later attempt to convert into Christianity in Hamburg failed due to admitted lack of belief in Christian dogma.[2] His second attempt to settle in Berlin in 1781 succeeded. After first studying language in a gymnasium, Maimon devoted himself to the study of philosophy along the lines of Wolff and Moses Mendelssohn. The latter introduced him to some wealthy Jews in Berlin, upon whom Mamimon relied for patronage while he pursued his studies. After many vicissitudes he found a peaceful residence in the house of Count Kalkreuth at Nieder-Siegersdorf in 1790. In 1791 he published his Autobiography. Maimon never was able to gain full admittance to German society because of his poverty and his lack of language skills. It was not until 1788 that he became acquainted with Kantian philosophy, and in 1790 he published the Essay on Transcendental Philosophy, in which he formulates his objections to Kant's system. Kant seems to have considered Maimon one of his most astute critics.[3] Maimon also published a commentary on the Moreh Nebuchim of Maimonides in 1790. Maimon died at the age of 48 from apparent alcoholism.[4][5]

Thinking

Thing in itself

He seizes upon the fundamental incompatibility of a consciousness which can apprehend, and yet is separated from, the thing-in-itself. That which is object of thought cannot be outside consciousness; just as in mathematics "–1" is an unreal quantity, so things-in-themselves are ex hypothesi outside consciousness, i.e. are unthinkable. The Kantian paradox he explains as the result of an attempt to explain the origin of the given in consciousness. The form of things is admittedly subjective; the mind endeavours to explain the material of the given in the same terms, an attempt which is not only impossible but involves a denial of the elementary laws of thought. Knowledge of the given is, therefore, essentially incomplete. Complete or perfect knowledge is confined to the domain of pure thought, to logic and mathematics. Thus the problem of the thing-in-itself is dismissed from the inquiry, and philosophy is limited to the sphere of pure thought.

Application of the Categories

The Kantian categories are demonstrable and true, but their application to the given is meaningless and unthinkable. By this critical scepticism Maimon takes up a position intermediate between Kant and Hume. Hume's attitude to the empirical is entirely supported by Maimon. The causal concept, as given by experience, expresses not a necessary objective order of things, but an ordered scheme of perception; it is subjective and cannot be postulated as a concrete law apart from consciousness.

Kant's comments

The main argument of the Transcendentalphilosophie not only drew from Kant, who saw the first chapter in MS. and remarked that Maimon alone of his all critics had mastered the true meaning of his philosophy, but also directed the path of most subsequent criticism.

Footnotes

  1. ^ a b c d e Socher, Abraham P. (2006). The Radical Enlightenment of Solomon Maimon: Judaism, Heresy, and Philosophy. Stanford University Press. ISBN 0804751366.
  2. ^ Solomon Maimon: An Autobiography, trans. J. Clark Murray, University of Illinois Press, 2001
  3. ^ Thielke, Peter. "Salomon Maimon". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  4. ^ Elon, Amos. The pity of it all. A portrait of the German-Jewish Epoch, 1743–1933. Picador, A metropolitan book. NY, Henry Holt and Company, 2002. Page 59
  5. ^ Maimon, Solomon. Solomon Maimon: An autobiography, Introduction by Michael Shapiro, Translated by J. Clark Murray, Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 2001.

References

  • Atlas, Samuel. From Critical to Speculative Idealism: The Philosophy of Solomon Maimon. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1965.
  • Bansen, Jan. The Antinomy of Thought: Maimonian Skepticism and the Relation between Thoughts and Objects. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991.
  • Bergmann, Samuel, Hugo. The Philosophy of Salomon Maimon. Translated from the Hebrew by Noah J. Jacobs. Jerusalem: The Magnes Press, 1967.
  • Herrera, Hugo Eduardo. Salomon Maimon's Commentary on the Subject of the Given in Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, in: The Review of Metaphysics 63.3, 2010. pp. 593–613.
  • Elon, Amos. The pity of it all. A portrait of the German-Jewish Epoch, 1743–1933. Picador, A metropolitanan book. NY, Henry Holt and Company, 2002. pp. 54–59
  • Maimon, Solomon. Gesammelte Werke. Volumes 1–7. Edited by V. Verra. Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1970.
Attribution

English translations

  • Maimon, Salomon. The Autobiography of Salomon Maimon with an Essay on Maimon's Philosophy, Introduction by Michael Shapiro, Translated by J. Clark Murray, Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 2001 (original edition: London, Boston : A. Gardner, 1888).
  • Maimon, Salomon. Essay on transcendental philosophy. Translated by Nick Midgley, Henry Somers-Hall, Alistair Welchman, and Merten Reglitz, London, New York: Continuum International Publishing Group, 2010, ISBN 978-1-4411-1384-9.
  • Maimon, Salomon. Essay Towards a New Logic or Theory of Thought, Together Letters of Philaletes to Aenesidemus in: G. di Giovanni, H.S. Harris (eds.), Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism, Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 2001, pp. 158–203.
  • Maimon, Salomon. Essay on Transcendental Philosophy. A Short Overview of the Whole Work, translated by H. Somers-Hall and M. Reglitz, in Pli: The Warwick Journal of Philosophy 19 (2008), pp. 127–165.
  • Maimon, Salomon. The Philosophical Language-Confusion in: Jere Paul Surber, Metacritique. The Linguistic Assault on German Idealism, Amherst:Humanity Books, 2001, pp. 71–84

External links

Template:Persondata

Template:Link FA