Jump to content

Transcendental humanism: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
about transcendence and humanistic naturalism
Added sections Lead, Background & Key Ideas, Influential Theorists & Philosophers, Related Concepts, Theories & Ideologies, and Criticisms & Academic Engagement. Each have subheadings.
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Distinguish|Transhumanism}}
{{Distinguish|Transhumanism}}


Transcendental Humanism in philosophy considers humans as simultaneously the originator of meaning, and subject to a larger ultimate truth that exists beyond the human realm (transcendence)<ref name=":0">{{Cite journal |last=Hansen |first=James T. |date=2007 |title=Relational and Transcendental Humanism: Exploring the Consequences of a Thoroughly Pragmatic Humanism |url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/j.2161-1939.2007.tb00031.x |journal=The Journal of Humanistic Counseling, Education and Development |language=en |volume=46 |issue=2 |pages=131–141 |doi=10.1002/j.2161-1939.2007.tb00031.x}}</ref>.  The philosophy suggests that the humanistic approach is guided by “accuracy, truth, discovery, and objectivity”<ref name=":0" /> that transcends or exists apart from subjectivity.
'''Transcendental humanism''' in philosophy considers what is proper treatment of humans outside of nature and decides they have inherent rights, simply from being human.<ref>Ferry, Luc. 2002. ''[https://books.google.com/books?id=_Z2tctBZg40C&lpg=PA139&dq=Transcendental%20Humanism&pg=PA135#v=onepage&q=Transcendental%20Humanism&f=false "Transcendental" Humanism]'' Man Made God: The Meaning of Life. University of Chicago Press. {{ISBN|0226244849}}</ref> It is also positive that man is capable of [[transcendence (philosophy)|transcending]] the material self and can also free himself from surrounding influences. An example of this is when he thinks about himself and his character traits as if two different people.<ref>Vanheste, Jeroen. 2007. ''Guardians of the Humanist Legacy: The Classicism of T.S. Eliot's Criterion Network and Its Relevance to Our Postmodern World, Volume 26 of Philosophy of History and Culture'', pp. [https://books.google.com/books?id=lITBxOMRJFQC&lpg=PA447&dq=Transcendental%20Humanism&pg=PA447#v=onepage&q=Transcendental%20Humanism&f=false 447] & [https://books.google.com/books?id=lITBxOMRJFQC&lpg=PA447&dq=Transcendental%20Humanism&pg=PA449#v=onepage&q=Transcendental%20Humanism&f=false 449] Brill. {{ISBN|9004161600}}</ref> Kant by the term meant humans are both a part of 'creation' and able to transcend reflexive obedience to the [[scientific law|laws of nature]].<ref>{{cite book|last=Allison|first=Henry E.|title=The Monist, Vol. 55, No. 2, Is Philosophy Human or Transcendental? |year=1971|publisher=Hegeler Institute|pages=182–207}}</ref>

The term is associated predominantly with the work of philosopher [[Immanuel Kant]] and his theory [[Copernican Revolution|Kant’s Copernican]]. However, the theory is both heavily influenced by and reflected in the work of other well-known theorists, including [[Jean-Jacques Rousseau|Rousseau]], [[Ralph Waldo Emerson|Emerson]], and [[Edmund Husserl|Husserl]]<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Warnke |first=Georgia |date=2002 |title=Book ReviewPaul Ricoeur, . <i>The Just</i>. Translated by David Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000. Pp. xxiv+155. $20.00 (cloth). |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/324242 |journal=Ethics |volume=112 |issue=2 |pages=406–408 |doi=10.1086/324242 |issn=0014-1704}}</ref>

Transcendental humanism can be largely traced back to [[Continental rationalism|Continental Rationalism]] and [[British Empiricism]]<ref>{{Citation |last=Scheibe |first=Erhard |title=Between Rationalism and Empiricism |date=2001 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4613-0183-7_1 |work=Between Rationalism and Empiricism |pages=1–86 |place=New York, NY |publisher=Springer New York |isbn=978-1-4612-6555-9 |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref> <ref name=":1">{{Cite journal |last=Allison |first=Henry E. |date=1971 |title=Kant's Transcendental Humanism |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/monist197155219 |journal=Monist |volume=55 |issue=2 |pages=182–207 |doi=10.5840/monist197155219 |issn=0026-9662}}</ref> in the [[17th century|17<sup>th</sup>]] and [[18th century|18<sup>th</sup>]] centuries. This formed the basis of philosophical thought that inspired transcendental humanist thinking through the amalgamation of [[Rationalism|logical rationalism]] and [[Empiricism|psychological empiricism]]<ref name=":1" /><ref>{{Cite book |last=Ludden Jr. |first=David C. |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.4135/9781452243979 |title=SAGE Brief Guide to Business Ethics |date=2012 |publisher=SAGE Publications, Inc. |isbn=978-1-4129-9721-8 |location=2455 Teller Road, Thousand Oaks California 91320 United States}}</ref>.

[[Immanuel Kant|Kant’s]] theory of transcendental humanism has been subject to criticism by academics for its paradoxical position that has caused misinterpretation of the theory. In the world of academia, critiques have engaged in profound discussion and debate around the meaning, relevance and historical context of the philosophical theory. The ample discussion surrounding the topic branches from the broad nature of the theory that responds to the nature and origin of knowledge and the human cognition.

=== Background & Key Ideas ===
Transcendental Humanism is a cross-section of both [[Humanism|humanist]] and [[Transcendentalism|transcendental]] philosophies<ref name=":1" />.  Humanism is a philosophy founded in a rationalist outlook that emphasises human agency as opposed to that of the divine<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Grech |first=Victor |date=2016 |title=Deicide in Star Trek: The Ultimate Expression of Humanism? |url=https://www.proquest.com/docview/1776114205?parentSessionId=cCnIupjuSVQTA7v%2BJyo9tfrv9icbop4cjPpKALhuXkg%3D&pq-origsite=primo&accountid=14757 |journal=Foundation (Dagenham) |volume=45 |issue=123 |via=Science Fiction Foundation}}</ref>. It recognises the centrality of moral values in human nature and experience. Thus, humans are believed to have the freedom to give meaning though independent thought and inquiry<ref>{{Citation |last=Manemann |first=Jürgen |title=How Could Humanists Become Solidary with the Non-Humanist World? Towards an Anamnestic Humanism |date=2017 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-57910-8_6 |work=Humanism in a Non-Humanist World |pages=117–132 |place=Cham |publisher=Springer International Publishing |isbn=978-3-319-57909-2 |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>.

The word [[transcendental]] describes that which lies beyond the limitations of physical experience and knowledge. In philosophy, transcendence refers to an understanding of the mind’s innate ability to process sensory evidence<ref>{{Citation |last=Brook |first=Andrew |title=Kant on the mind |date=2018-07-06 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780429508158-17 |work=Philosophy of Mind in the Early Modern and Modern Ages |pages=342–362 |place=New York : Routledge, 2018. {{!}} Series: The history of the philosophy of mind ; Volume 4 |publisher=Routledge |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>, employed as a theoretical perspective to define the structures of being as a framework to analyse the emergence and validation of knowledge<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Caygill |first=Howard |date=2017-08-11 |title=A Kant Dictionary |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781405164658 |doi=10.1002/9781405164658}}</ref>.

According to [[Kantian philosophy]], transcendental philosophy is defined [[A priori and a posteriori|a priori]]<ref name=":1" />. Dating back to [[Ancient philosophy|Ancient Philosophy]] and the [[Hellenistic period|Hellenistic Period]]<ref>{{Citation |title=PLATIS’S SOCRATES’ ACCUSERS |date=2022-02-08 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv24rgc46.8 |work=Studies in Greek Philosophy, Volume II |pages=19–24 |publisher=Princeton University Press |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>, coined by [[Plato]] and [[Aristotle]], a priori is a Latin phrase used in philosophy to describe knowledge that exists in the mind prior to and independent of experience<ref>{{Citation |title=Dodge, John Vilas, (25 Sept. 1909–23 April 1991), Senior Editorial Consultant, Encyclopædia Britannica, since 1972; Chairman, Board of Editors, Encyclopædia Britannica Publishers, since 1977 |date=2007-12-01 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/ww/9780199540884.013.u172122 |work=Who Was Who |publisher=Oxford University Press |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>. It exists as a faculty or character trait, independent of observation or experimentation.

As such, transcendental humanism implies that humans are both of the creators of and receptors of meaning. Historically, the philosophy is thought to reconcile the transcendental positioning of Continental Rationalism and the humanistic approach of British Empiricism<ref name=":1" />. Continental Rationalism was established by [[René Descartes]] and covered the 17<sup>th</sup> and 18<sup>th</sup> century. It is based on the thesis that humans can be the source of all knowledge<ref>{{Citation |last=Markie |first=Peter J. |title=Rationalism |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780415249126-p041-1 |work=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |place=London |publisher=Routledge |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>. British Empiricism was also founded in the 17<sup>th</sup> and 18<sup>th</sup> century and proposed that all knowledge is gained though experience and thus all knowledge, with the exception of mathematics, empirical<ref>{{Cite web |title=9: Empiricism |url=http://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm |access-date=2022-06-02 |website=www.utm.edu}}</ref>.

=== '''Influential Theorists & Philosophers''' ===

==== Jean-Jacques Rousseau '''(1712 – 1778)''' ====
[[Jean-Jacques Rousseau]] (1712-1778) was a Swiss writer and philosopher. He is commonly recognised for his book ''[[The Social Contract|The Social Contract (1762)]]'', which was originally published as ''On the Social Contract,'' or ''Principles of Political Right''<ref>{{Cite web |title=Social Contract by Jean Jacques Rousseau 1762 |url=https://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/economics/rousseau/social-contract/ |access-date=2022-06-02 |website=www.marxists.org}}</ref>. The book, which theorises about community governed by an agreement that dictates both “moral and political rules of behaviour”<ref>{{Citation |last=Weale |first=Albert |title=A Method of Ethics? |date=2020-06-11 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198853541.003.0018 |work=Modern Social Contract Theory |pages=403–416 |publisher=Oxford University Press |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>, begins with a famous phrase that; “Man was/is born free, and everywhere he is in chains”<ref>{{Citation |title=Jean-Jacques Rousseau The Social Contract |date=2014-02-03 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9781315849201-20 |work=Philosophy: The Classics |pages=136–143 |publisher=Routledge |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>. Thus, Rousseau’s contribution to the philosophical theory of transcendental humanism can be found in his definition of human freedom<ref>{{Citation |last=Simpson |first=Matthew |title=Rousseau, Jean-Jacques |date=2013-02-01 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee553 |work=International Encyclopedia of Ethics |place=Oxford, UK |publisher=Blackwell Publishing Ltd |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref> as the autonomy to live according to the law one has prescribed to himself, and according to his own judgement about what is good.

==== '''Immanuel Kant (1724 – 1804)''' ====
[[Immanuel Kant]] (1724 – 1804) is a German philosopher that centred many of his studies and [[critical philosophy]] around human autonomy in the causes and origins of knowledge<ref>{{Citation |last=Watkins |first=Eric |title=Immanuel Kant: Theoretical Philosophy |date=2010-05-10 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/obo/9780195396577-0061 |work=Philosophy |publisher=Oxford University Press |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>. Kant’s “transcendental, logical investigation of the nature and limits of knowledge”<ref name=":1" />, which inherently lead to the analysis of human characteristics and cognitive faculties as “a priori”<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Pereboom |first=Derk |date=1990 |title=Kant on justification in transcendental philosophy |url=http://link.springer.com/10.1007/BF00873193 |journal=Synthese |language=en |volume=85 |issue=1 |pages=25–54 |doi=10.1007/BF00873193 |issn=0039-7857}}</ref>, form the key foundations of transcendental humanism<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Nizhnikov |first=Sergei |date=2018 |title=Foundations of Ethics and Education in the Philosophy of Transcendentalism |url=http://www.atlantis-press.com/php/paper-details.php?id=25900267 |journal=Proceedings of the 4th International Conference on Arts, Design and Contemporary Education (ICADCE 2018) |language=en |location=Zhengzhou, China |publisher=Atlantis Press |doi=10.2991/icadce-18.2018.127 |isbn=978-94-6252-548-1}}</ref>. [[Kant's Copernican revolution|Kant’s Copernican]] describes the human mind as the originator of experience rather than a recipient of perception<ref>{{Cite web |title=Comparative Religion studies & the Faith vs. Reason Debate - Aldous Huxley & "The Perennial Philosophy" |url=http://www.age-of-the-sage.org/ |access-date=2022-06-02 |website=www.age-of-the-sage.org}}</ref>. This lends to the core idea of transcendental humanism, which describes man as “a part of nature, subject to its laws”<ref name=":1" />, and on the other hand able to not only transcend these laws, “but who is actually the author of these laws”<ref name=":1" />.

==== Ralph Waldo Emerson (1803-1882) ====
[[Ralph Waldo Emerson|Ralph Waldo Emerso]]<nowiki/>n (1803 – 1882) was an American essayist, poet and philosopher best known for his contribution to the [[Transcendentalism|transcendentalism movement]] of the mid-[[19th century|19<sup>th</sup> century]]<ref>{{Cite web |title=Ralph Waldo Emerson {{!}} Biography, Poems, Books, Nature, Self-Reliance, & Facts {{!}} Britannica |url=https://www.britannica.com/biography/Ralph-Waldo-Emerson |access-date=2022-06-02 |website=www.britannica.com |language=en}}</ref>. Emerson’s spiritual transcendentalism re-emerged in [[New England]] following [[Immanuel Kant|Kant’s]] rational transcendentalism. He was a pivotal member of the [[Transcendental Club|Transcendental Club (1836)]]<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Uram-Ţuculescu |first=Sorin |last2=Constantinescu |first2=Marian-Vladimir |date=2017 |title=COMPLETE PROSTHESES TREATMENT – PRESENT AND FUTURE PERSPECTIVES |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.25241/stomaeduj.2017.4(4).art.5 |journal=Stomatology Edu Journal |volume=4 |issue=4 |pages=282–288 |doi=10.25241/stomaeduj.2017.4(4).art.5 |issn=2360-2406}}</ref> and thus had a significant impact on the rise of transcendental humanism. His philosophies are considered by many a blending of [[Kantianism|Kantian]] and [[Goethean]] themes that give “more to interpretation than to argumentation”<ref name=":2">{{Cite book |last=Gobar |first=Ash |title=Higher Humanism: A Neotranscendental Philosophy of Life |publisher=Peter Lang |year=2017}}</ref>.

=== Related Concepts, Theories & Ideologies ===

==== Transcendentalism ====
[[Transcendentalism]] is a philosophy defined by the [[A priori and a posteriori|a priori]] conditions of knowledge or experience<ref name=":3">{{Cite web |title=Info:Main Page - New World Encyclopedia |url=https://www.newworldencyclopedia.org/ |access-date=2022-06-02 |website=www.newworldencyclopedia.org}}</ref>. In philosophy, knowledge is considered transcendental if it is made up not of objects, but the way in which we know objects before prior to experiencing them<ref name=":4">{{Cite web |title=Definition of TRANSCENDENTALISM |url=https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/transcendentalism |access-date=2022-06-02 |website=www.merriam-webster.com |language=en}}</ref>.

Transcendental concepts (pure concepts of reason) include that of the soul ([[psychology]]), ultimate reality ([[cosmology]]), and God ([[theology]]). These ideas are transcendental as they cannot be proven empirically, and no empirical or observed concept of these ideas can adequately or holistically represent them. However, whilst their representations are not based on empirical cognition, the three transcendental ideas may still guide an understanding of the [[Empirical evidence|empirical world]]<ref>{{Citation |title=Kant’s Theoretical Philosophy : The Critique of Pure Reason |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781472553041.ch-001 |work=Kant’s Philosophy |publisher=Bloomsbury Academic |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>.

===== Spiritual Transcendentalism =====
Closely aligned with the study of [[theology]], spiritual transcendentalism describes a [[Worldview|religious worldview]] that acknowledges the existence of a [[Higher Power|higher power]] beyond human capabilities or experience<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Crowe |first=Benjamin D. |date=2010 |title=Fichte's Transcendental Theology |url=https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/AGPH.2010.003/html |journal=Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie |volume=92 |issue=1 |doi=10.1515/AGPH.2010.003 |issn=0003-9101}}</ref>. It can be referred to as the acknowledgement of an underlying unity within nature<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Dein |first=Simon |date=2020 |title=Transcendence, religion and social bonding |url=https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/full/10.1177/0084672420905018 |journal=Archive for the Psychology of Religion |volume=42 |issue=1}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Edara |first=Inna Reddy |date=2017 |title=Religion: A Subset of Culture and an Expression of Spirituality |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.4236/aa.2017.74015 |journal=Advances in Anthropology |volume=07 |issue=04 |pages=273–288 |doi=10.4236/aa.2017.74015 |issn=2163-9353}}</ref>.

===== Transcendental Idealism =====
[[Idealism]] in philosophy is defined by the subjectivity of space and time and concerns the limits of [[Cognition|human cognition]] in its claims to the knowledge of objects<ref>{{Cite journal |date=2015-02-19 |editor-last=Gardner |editor-first=Sebastian |editor2-last=Grist |editor2-first=Matthew |title=The Transcendental Turn |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198724872.001.0001 |doi=10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198724872.001.0001}}</ref>. Philosopher [[Immanuel Kant]] proposed that space and time, rather than being empirically mediated appearances in themselves, are the “very forms of intuition”<ref name=":3" /> in the way people perceive and interpret objects.

Kant distinguishes between that of the [[Phenomenon|phenomenal]] and [[Noumenon|noumenal]] world, in which phenomena are ‘appearances’, or those that are apparent to the senses, and noumena are ‘things in themselves’ that exist within the intelligible realm<ref name=":5">{{Cite web |last=Scott |first=Alex |date=2002 |title=Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason |url=https://www.angelfire.com/md2/timewarp/purereason.html |url-status=live |website=The Power of Language: Philosophy and Society}}</ref>. In the phenomenal world, objects are present to individuals through their [[sensibility]]. As such, one has knowledge of objects through the world of appearances and [[sense perception]], yet, the ascription of meaning comes from the noumenal world, or the transcendental realm<ref>{{Citation |last=Jauernig |first=Anja |title=Kant’s Transcendental Idealism and Empirical Realism |date=2021-02-18 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780199695386.003.0003 |work=The World According to Kant |pages=110–178 |publisher=Oxford University Press |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>.

[[Immanuel Kant|Immanuel Kant’s]] transcendental idealism is defined in the [[Critique of Pure Reason|“Fourth Paralogism”]]<ref>{{Citation |title=Mobile Internet |date=2017 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-981-287-588-4_100650 |work=Encyclopedia of Educational Philosophy and Theory |pages=1456–1456 |place=Singapore |publisher=Springer Singapore |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref><ref name=":6">{{Cite journal |last=Stern |first=Robert |date=1999 |title=Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. Pp. xi, 785. £50 (hbk). ISBN 0-521-65729-6. |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1369415400000418 |journal=Kantian Review |volume=3 |pages=137–140 |doi=10.1017/s1369415400000418 |issn=1369-4154}}</ref> of ''The Critique of Pure Reason (1781)'':

“Now all outer appearances are of this kind: their existence cannot be immediately perceived, but can be inferred only as the cause of given perceptions: Thus the existence of all objects of outer sense is doubtful. This uncertainty I call the ideality of outer appearances, and the doctrine of this ideality is called idealism, in comparison with which the assertion of a possible certainty of objects of our sense is call dualism.”<ref name=":6" />

[[Transcendental idealism]] is a philosophical stance established by Kant, who compares the philosophy with that of [[transcendental realism]] which:

“Considers space, time, and objects alike, to be real in themselves, quite independently from the human perception of them.”<ref name=":3" />

Instead, Kant proposes transcendental idealism as a philosophy that considers the “outer appearances”<ref name=":6" /> of objects as the “spatial-temporal objects of everyday experience – as imperfect shadows of a transcendent reality”<ref name=":3" />. Transcendental idealism affirms that the world and objects are real to the conditions of the human faculty and cognition. As such, objects of perception are conditioned by the mind in response to their form rather than contents<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Crowe |first=Benjamin D. |date=2010 |title=Fichte's Transcendental Theology |url=https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/AGPH.2010.003/html |journal=Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie |volume=92 |issue=1 |doi=10.1515/AGPH.2010.003 |issn=0003-9101}}</ref><ref name=":4" />.

==== Humanism ====
The term ''[[Humanism]]'' was first used by a German educationist in 1808<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Figdor |first=Carrie |date=2021 |title=The psychological speciesism of humanism |url=https://link.springer.com/10.1007/s11098-020-01495-y |journal=Philosophical Studies |language=en |volume=178 |issue=5 |pages=1545–1569 |doi=10.1007/s11098-020-01495-y |issn=0031-8116}}</ref><ref>{{Citation |last=Langer |first=Ullrich |title=Should We Practice Justice Toward Nonhuman Animals? Radical Animal Interests, Humanism, and Classical Justice |date=2016 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-32276-6_3 |work=Early Modern Humanism and Postmodern Antihumanism in Dialogue |pages=49–70 |place=Cham |publisher=Springer International Publishing |isbn=978-3-319-32275-9 |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>. Humanism is a rational philosophy that seeks to understand the universe through science and inquiry-logical reasoning<ref>{{Citation |last=Manemann |first=Jürgen |title=How Could Humanists Become Solidary with the Non-Humanist World? Towards an Anamnestic Humanism |date=2017 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-57910-8_6 |work=Humanism in a Non-Humanist World |pages=117–132 |place=Cham |publisher=Springer International Publishing |isbn=978-3-319-57909-2 |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>. Definitions of humanism have continued to evolve since its emergence as it is applied in different philosophical, cultural, and political contexts<ref>{{Citation |title=HUMANISTS BEFORE HUMANISM: THE RENAISSANCE |date=2006-10-19 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780203129722-6 |work=Humanism |pages=80–112 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-0-203-12972-2 |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>. Reactions against humanist ideologies have seen the emergence of movements such as [[structuralism]], [[postmodernism]] and [[postcolonialism]] <ref>{{Citation |title=Scott Cutler Shershow David Hawkes, Ideology (in ‘The New Critical Idiom’ series, ed. John Drakakis) (London and New York: Routledge, 1996), 210 pp., $49.95 (hardback), $9.95 (paperback) Paul Hamilton, Historicism (in ‘The New Critical Idiom’ series, ed. John Drakakis (London and New York: Routledge, 1996), 226 pp., $49.95 (hardback), $9.95 (paperback) |date=2005-06-27 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780203986332-14 |work=Textual Practice |pages=165–168 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-0-203-98633-2 |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>. In philosophy, humanism is defined as:

“…a belief in reason and autonomy as foundational aspects of human existence; a belief that reason, scepticism and the scientific method are the only appropriate instruments for discovering truth and structuring the human community; a belief that the foundations for ethics and society are to be found in autonomy and moral equality…”<ref>{{Cite book |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780203157909 |title=Concise Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |date=2013-01-11 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-134-59392-7 |editor-last=Craig |editor-first=Professor Edward |editor-last2=Craig |editor-first2=Edward}}</ref>.

===== Renaissance Humanism =====
[[Renaissance humanism|Renaissance Humanism]] originated in [[14th century|14<sup>th</sup> century]] Italy and spread throughout [[15th century|15<sup>th</sup> century]] Europe<ref>{{Citation |last=Grendler |first=Paul |title=Humanism |date=2010-05-10 |url=https://oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780195399301/obo-9780195399301-0002.xml |work=Renaissance and Reformation |publisher=Oxford University Press |language=en |doi=10.1093/obo/9780195399301-0002. |isbn=978-0-19-539930-1 |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>. Emerging off the back of the [[Middle Ages]], defined by its adherence to religion as the ultimate source of knowledge, Renaissance Humanism saw a rejection of the [[Divinity|divine]]. Refuting the existence of a transcendental realm, the philosophical movement considered humans as “irreducibly whole beings”<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Hansen |first=James T. |date=2007-09 |title=Relational and Transcendental Humanism: Exploring the Consequences of a Thoroughly Pragmatic Humanism |url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/j.2161-1939.2007.tb00031.x |journal=The Journal of Humanistic Counseling, Education and Development |language=en |volume=46 |issue=2 |pages=131–141 |doi=10.1002/j.2161-1939.2007.tb00031.x}}</ref>.

===== Classical Humanism =====
Classical humanism is a branch of education and type of consciousness<ref>{{Citation |last=Langer |first=Ullrich |title=Should We Practice Justice Toward Nonhuman Animals? Radical Animal Interests, Humanism, and Classical Justice |date=2016 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-32276-6_3 |work=Early Modern Humanism and Postmodern Antihumanism in Dialogue |pages=49–70 |place=Cham |publisher=Springer International Publishing |isbn=978-3-319-32275-9 |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>. It refers to the practice of engaging with a broader [[cultural heritage]] – that of [[Ancient Greece]] and [[Ancient Rome|Rome]] <ref name=":2" />. Classical humanism offers insights into the:


“…the realistic epistemological and metaphysical approaches, the wholeness of the human being and the notion of person, the unity of the human action, the understanding of the society, and the eudemonistic perspective to ethics.”<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Domingo |first=Vianney |date=2022 |title=Re‑Thinking Management: Insights from Western Classical Humanism |url=https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s41463-021-00115-z |journal=Humanistic Management Journal |volume=7 |issue=1-21}}</ref>

==== Kant's Critique of Pure Reason ====
''[[Critique of Pure Reason|The Critique of Pure Reason (1781)]]'' is a book written by German philosopher [[Immanuel Kant]]. The book is an investigation into the origins of human knowledge and the possibility of [[metaphysics]] <ref>{{Citation |last=Watkins |first=Eric |title=Immanuel Kant: Theoretical Philosophy |date=2010-05-10 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/obo/9780195396577-0061 |work=Philosophy |publisher=Oxford University Press |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>. Written in response to the intellectual crisis of the [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment Period]] (1685 – 1815), the ''Critique of Pure Reason'' examines the relationship between [[A priori and a posteriori|''a priori'' and ''a posteriori'']] knowledge<ref>{{Citation |last=Baehr |first=Jason |title=A Priori and a Posteriori |date=2013 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.4135/9781452276052.n1 |work=Encyclopedia of Philosophy and the Social Sciences |place=2455 Teller Road, Thousand Oaks California 91320 United States |publisher=SAGE Publications, Inc. |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>. Explaining that knowledge is “provided by a transcendental unity of reason and experience”<ref name=":6" />, Kant presents a cross section of rationalist and empiricist positions.


The book deals with three main questions: ''a) What can I know? (b) What ought I to do? (c) What may I hope?'' The first questions unpacks what the ''nature'' and ''limit'' of knowledge is<ref name=":2" /> Kant supports the empirical claim that all knowledge originates with experience but does not agree that experience must be the only form of knowledge<ref name=":6" />. The Mind, then, is understood not as a blank canvas impressionable by experience, but rather a “reservoir of ''a priori'' forms that mould the data of experience into an ordered whole”<ref name=":2" />.


In ''[[Critique of Pure Reason|The Critique of Pure Reason (1781)]]'', Kant dissects the philosophical concept of [[transcendental idealism]] through his argument that space, and time are not things in themselves, but are merely formal features of how one may perceive something. Kant defines space and time as “appearances” and argues that:

(a)   Space and time are not being that exist independently, but rather forms of our sensible intuition of objects.

(b)  Objects we understand or comprehend are ‘appearances’ and do not exist independently of our intuition.

(c)   Humans can only know an object that we can intuit. As such, humans can only comprehend objects in appearances (space and time) and cannot cognise things in themselves.

(d)  Humans can distinguish and cognise objects in categories.<ref name=":5" />

==== Kant's Copernican Revolution ====
[[Copernican Revolution|Kant’s Copernican Revolution]] in philosophy deals with the causes and origins of our knowledge, as well as the limits and objective validity<ref name=":1" /><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Creighton |first=J. E. |date=1913 |title=The Copernican Revolution in Philosophy |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2178367 |journal=The Philosophical Review |volume=22 |issue=2 |pages=133 |doi=10.2307/2178367 |issn=0031-8108}}</ref>. Aligned with [[Nicolaus Copernicus|Nicholas Copernicus’]] proposal of a [[Heliocentrism|heliocentric solar system]] <ref>{{Cite web |title=Nicolaus Copernicus {{!}} Biography, Facts, Nationality, Discoveries, Accomplishments, & Theory {{!}} Britannica |url=https://www.britannica.com/biography/Nicolaus-Copernicus |access-date=2022-06-02 |website=www.britannica.com |language=en}}</ref>, Kant’s philosophy discerns humans as the originator experience and knowledge<ref name=":1" /> – “that the subject doing the knowing constitutes, to a considerable extent, the object”<ref>{{Cite web |title=Kantianism {{!}} philosophy {{!}} Britannica |url=https://www.britannica.com/topic/Kantianism |access-date=2022-06-02 |website=www.britannica.com |language=en}}</ref>. Kant explained knowledge as part transcendental [[A priori and a posteriori|(a priori)]], which the mind imposes on a set of data – or experience.

“Concepts without percepts may be empty, but percepts without concepts are blind. Yet the transcendental world of ideas harbor their own contents of abstract forms, constituting a system of a priori truths, accessible through pure reason alone”<ref name=":2" />

=== Criticisms & Academic Engagement ===
Criticisms of transcendental humanism focus on its paradoxical nature<ref name=":1" /> <ref>{{Cite journal |last=Braidotti |first=Rosi |date=2019 |title=A Theoretical Framework for the Critical Posthumanities |url=http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/0263276418771486 |journal=Theory, Culture & Society |language=en |volume=36 |issue=6 |pages=31–61 |doi=10.1177/0263276418771486 |issn=0263-2764}}</ref>. Critics have claimed there is a lack of clarity in its argumentation, suggesting that Kant’s “perspectival dualism”<ref name=":6" /> was successful only in creating a transcendental [[psychologism]] which is considered incapable of solving “largely imaginary”<ref name=":1" /> issues. There are differing arguments and interpretations of Kant’s transcendental philosophy as either a form of [[phenomenalism]], or not a [[Metaphysics|metaphysical]] or [[Ontology|ontological]] theory at all<ref>{{Citation |last=Jauernig |first=Anja |title=Kant’s Transcendental Idealism and Empirical Realism |date=2021-02-18 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780199695386.003.0003 |work=The World According to Kant |pages=110–178 |publisher=Oxford University Press |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>.


English philosopher and Professor, [[P. F. Strawson]], critiqued Kant’s transcendental humanism in his body of work [[The Bounds of Sense|''The Bounds of Sense:'' ''An Essay on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason'']] <ref>{{Cite journal |last=Strawson |first=Peter |date=2018-09-14 |title=The Bounds of Sense |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780429447075 |doi=10.4324/9780429447075}}</ref>. Strawson was the [[Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy]] at the University of Oxford from 1968 to 1987. Strawson states the theory is “completely unintelligible” and dismisses the “imaginary subject of transcendental psychology” as belonging to neither “empirical …, nor to an analytic philosophy of mind” <ref>{{Citation |title=On naturalizing Kant's transcendental psychology |date=1996 |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/idealism-and-freedom/on-naturalizing-kants-transcendental-psychology/3AECEAD482B28D9FF30AE708D91C3BFB |work=Idealism and Freedom: Essays on Kant's Theoretical and Practical Philosophy |pages=53–66 |editor-last=Allison |editor-first=Henry E. |place=Cambridge |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-48337-7 |access-date=2022-06-02}}</ref>.


[[James Hansen|James T. Hansen]] in ''[[The Journal of Humanistic Counseling|The Journal of Humanistic Counselling, Education and Development]]'' states that “the transcendental portion of humanism is like an anchor that severely limits the growth and power of humanistic ideology”<ref name=":0" /> . The journal instead discusses a need for non-transcendental humanism that disengages from the idea of ultimate truths. The critic considers [[Darwinism]] as the alternate ideology that rejects transcendence and equates humans and animals as more relevant and influential in philosophical thinking <ref>{{Cite journal |last=Gartner |first=Murray |last2=Cairns |first2=Huntington |date=1950 |title=Legal Philosophy from Plato to Hegel |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/1226129 |journal=Stanford Law Review |volume=2 |issue=4 |pages=818 |doi=10.2307/1226129 |issn=0038-9765}}</ref>.


== References ==
== References ==

Revision as of 01:51, 2 June 2022

Transcendental Humanism in philosophy considers humans as simultaneously the originator of meaning, and subject to a larger ultimate truth that exists beyond the human realm (transcendence)[1].  The philosophy suggests that the humanistic approach is guided by “accuracy, truth, discovery, and objectivity”[1] that transcends or exists apart from subjectivity.

The term is associated predominantly with the work of philosopher Immanuel Kant and his theory Kant’s Copernican. However, the theory is both heavily influenced by and reflected in the work of other well-known theorists, including Rousseau, Emerson, and Husserl[2]

Transcendental humanism can be largely traced back to Continental Rationalism and British Empiricism[3] [4] in the 17th and 18th centuries. This formed the basis of philosophical thought that inspired transcendental humanist thinking through the amalgamation of logical rationalism and psychological empiricism[4][5].

Kant’s theory of transcendental humanism has been subject to criticism by academics for its paradoxical position that has caused misinterpretation of the theory. In the world of academia, critiques have engaged in profound discussion and debate around the meaning, relevance and historical context of the philosophical theory. The ample discussion surrounding the topic branches from the broad nature of the theory that responds to the nature and origin of knowledge and the human cognition.

Background & Key Ideas

Transcendental Humanism is a cross-section of both humanist and transcendental philosophies[4].  Humanism is a philosophy founded in a rationalist outlook that emphasises human agency as opposed to that of the divine[6]. It recognises the centrality of moral values in human nature and experience. Thus, humans are believed to have the freedom to give meaning though independent thought and inquiry[7].

The word transcendental describes that which lies beyond the limitations of physical experience and knowledge. In philosophy, transcendence refers to an understanding of the mind’s innate ability to process sensory evidence[8], employed as a theoretical perspective to define the structures of being as a framework to analyse the emergence and validation of knowledge[9].

According to Kantian philosophy, transcendental philosophy is defined a priori[4]. Dating back to Ancient Philosophy and the Hellenistic Period[10], coined by Plato and Aristotle, a priori is a Latin phrase used in philosophy to describe knowledge that exists in the mind prior to and independent of experience[11]. It exists as a faculty or character trait, independent of observation or experimentation.

As such, transcendental humanism implies that humans are both of the creators of and receptors of meaning. Historically, the philosophy is thought to reconcile the transcendental positioning of Continental Rationalism and the humanistic approach of British Empiricism[4]. Continental Rationalism was established by René Descartes and covered the 17th and 18th century. It is based on the thesis that humans can be the source of all knowledge[12]. British Empiricism was also founded in the 17th and 18th century and proposed that all knowledge is gained though experience and thus all knowledge, with the exception of mathematics, empirical[13].

Influential Theorists & Philosophers

Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712 – 1778)

Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778) was a Swiss writer and philosopher. He is commonly recognised for his book The Social Contract (1762), which was originally published as On the Social Contract, or Principles of Political Right[14]. The book, which theorises about community governed by an agreement that dictates both “moral and political rules of behaviour”[15], begins with a famous phrase that; “Man was/is born free, and everywhere he is in chains”[16]. Thus, Rousseau’s contribution to the philosophical theory of transcendental humanism can be found in his definition of human freedom[17] as the autonomy to live according to the law one has prescribed to himself, and according to his own judgement about what is good.

Immanuel Kant (1724 – 1804)

Immanuel Kant (1724 – 1804) is a German philosopher that centred many of his studies and critical philosophy around human autonomy in the causes and origins of knowledge[18]. Kant’s “transcendental, logical investigation of the nature and limits of knowledge”[4], which inherently lead to the analysis of human characteristics and cognitive faculties as “a priori”[19], form the key foundations of transcendental humanism[20]. Kant’s Copernican describes the human mind as the originator of experience rather than a recipient of perception[21]. This lends to the core idea of transcendental humanism, which describes man as “a part of nature, subject to its laws”[4], and on the other hand able to not only transcend these laws, “but who is actually the author of these laws”[4].

Ralph Waldo Emerson (1803-1882)

Ralph Waldo Emerson (1803 – 1882) was an American essayist, poet and philosopher best known for his contribution to the transcendentalism movement of the mid-19th century[22]. Emerson’s spiritual transcendentalism re-emerged in New England following Kant’s rational transcendentalism. He was a pivotal member of the Transcendental Club (1836)[23] and thus had a significant impact on the rise of transcendental humanism. His philosophies are considered by many a blending of Kantian and Goethean themes that give “more to interpretation than to argumentation”[24].

Transcendentalism

Transcendentalism is a philosophy defined by the a priori conditions of knowledge or experience[25]. In philosophy, knowledge is considered transcendental if it is made up not of objects, but the way in which we know objects before prior to experiencing them[26].

Transcendental concepts (pure concepts of reason) include that of the soul (psychology), ultimate reality (cosmology), and God (theology). These ideas are transcendental as they cannot be proven empirically, and no empirical or observed concept of these ideas can adequately or holistically represent them. However, whilst their representations are not based on empirical cognition, the three transcendental ideas may still guide an understanding of the empirical world[27].

Spiritual Transcendentalism

Closely aligned with the study of theology, spiritual transcendentalism describes a religious worldview that acknowledges the existence of a higher power beyond human capabilities or experience[28]. It can be referred to as the acknowledgement of an underlying unity within nature[29][30].

Transcendental Idealism

Idealism in philosophy is defined by the subjectivity of space and time and concerns the limits of human cognition in its claims to the knowledge of objects[31]. Philosopher Immanuel Kant proposed that space and time, rather than being empirically mediated appearances in themselves, are the “very forms of intuition”[25] in the way people perceive and interpret objects.

Kant distinguishes between that of the phenomenal and noumenal world, in which phenomena are ‘appearances’, or those that are apparent to the senses, and noumena are ‘things in themselves’ that exist within the intelligible realm[32]. In the phenomenal world, objects are present to individuals through their sensibility. As such, one has knowledge of objects through the world of appearances and sense perception, yet, the ascription of meaning comes from the noumenal world, or the transcendental realm[33].

Immanuel Kant’s transcendental idealism is defined in the “Fourth Paralogism”[34][35] of The Critique of Pure Reason (1781):

“Now all outer appearances are of this kind: their existence cannot be immediately perceived, but can be inferred only as the cause of given perceptions: Thus the existence of all objects of outer sense is doubtful. This uncertainty I call the ideality of outer appearances, and the doctrine of this ideality is called idealism, in comparison with which the assertion of a possible certainty of objects of our sense is call dualism.”[35]

Transcendental idealism is a philosophical stance established by Kant, who compares the philosophy with that of transcendental realism which:

“Considers space, time, and objects alike, to be real in themselves, quite independently from the human perception of them.”[25]

Instead, Kant proposes transcendental idealism as a philosophy that considers the “outer appearances”[35] of objects as the “spatial-temporal objects of everyday experience – as imperfect shadows of a transcendent reality”[25]. Transcendental idealism affirms that the world and objects are real to the conditions of the human faculty and cognition. As such, objects of perception are conditioned by the mind in response to their form rather than contents[36][26].

Humanism

The term Humanism was first used by a German educationist in 1808[37][38]. Humanism is a rational philosophy that seeks to understand the universe through science and inquiry-logical reasoning[39]. Definitions of humanism have continued to evolve since its emergence as it is applied in different philosophical, cultural, and political contexts[40]. Reactions against humanist ideologies have seen the emergence of movements such as structuralism, postmodernism and postcolonialism [41]. In philosophy, humanism is defined as:

“…a belief in reason and autonomy as foundational aspects of human existence; a belief that reason, scepticism and the scientific method are the only appropriate instruments for discovering truth and structuring the human community; a belief that the foundations for ethics and society are to be found in autonomy and moral equality…”[42].

Renaissance Humanism

Renaissance Humanism originated in 14th century Italy and spread throughout 15th century Europe[43]. Emerging off the back of the Middle Ages, defined by its adherence to religion as the ultimate source of knowledge, Renaissance Humanism saw a rejection of the divine. Refuting the existence of a transcendental realm, the philosophical movement considered humans as “irreducibly whole beings”[44].

Classical Humanism

Classical humanism is a branch of education and type of consciousness[45]. It refers to the practice of engaging with a broader cultural heritage – that of Ancient Greece and Rome [24]. Classical humanism offers insights into the:


“…the realistic epistemological and metaphysical approaches, the wholeness of the human being and the notion of person, the unity of the human action, the understanding of the society, and the eudemonistic perspective to ethics.”[46]

Kant's Critique of Pure Reason

The Critique of Pure Reason (1781) is a book written by German philosopher Immanuel Kant. The book is an investigation into the origins of human knowledge and the possibility of metaphysics [47]. Written in response to the intellectual crisis of the Enlightenment Period (1685 – 1815), the Critique of Pure Reason examines the relationship between a priori and a posteriori knowledge[48]. Explaining that knowledge is “provided by a transcendental unity of reason and experience”[35], Kant presents a cross section of rationalist and empiricist positions.


The book deals with three main questions: a) What can I know? (b) What ought I to do? (c) What may I hope? The first questions unpacks what the nature and limit of knowledge is[24] Kant supports the empirical claim that all knowledge originates with experience but does not agree that experience must be the only form of knowledge[35]. The Mind, then, is understood not as a blank canvas impressionable by experience, but rather a “reservoir of a priori forms that mould the data of experience into an ordered whole”[24].


In The Critique of Pure Reason (1781), Kant dissects the philosophical concept of transcendental idealism through his argument that space, and time are not things in themselves, but are merely formal features of how one may perceive something. Kant defines space and time as “appearances” and argues that:

(a)   Space and time are not being that exist independently, but rather forms of our sensible intuition of objects.

(b)  Objects we understand or comprehend are ‘appearances’ and do not exist independently of our intuition.

(c)   Humans can only know an object that we can intuit. As such, humans can only comprehend objects in appearances (space and time) and cannot cognise things in themselves.

(d)  Humans can distinguish and cognise objects in categories.[32]

Kant's Copernican Revolution

Kant’s Copernican Revolution in philosophy deals with the causes and origins of our knowledge, as well as the limits and objective validity[4][49]. Aligned with Nicholas Copernicus’ proposal of a heliocentric solar system [50], Kant’s philosophy discerns humans as the originator experience and knowledge[4] – “that the subject doing the knowing constitutes, to a considerable extent, the object”[51]. Kant explained knowledge as part transcendental (a priori), which the mind imposes on a set of data – or experience.

“Concepts without percepts may be empty, but percepts without concepts are blind. Yet the transcendental world of ideas harbor their own contents of abstract forms, constituting a system of a priori truths, accessible through pure reason alone”[24]

Criticisms & Academic Engagement

Criticisms of transcendental humanism focus on its paradoxical nature[4] [52]. Critics have claimed there is a lack of clarity in its argumentation, suggesting that Kant’s “perspectival dualism”[35] was successful only in creating a transcendental psychologism which is considered incapable of solving “largely imaginary”[4] issues. There are differing arguments and interpretations of Kant’s transcendental philosophy as either a form of phenomenalism, or not a metaphysical or ontological theory at all[53].


English philosopher and Professor, P. F. Strawson, critiqued Kant’s transcendental humanism in his body of work The Bounds of Sense: An Essay on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason [54]. Strawson was the Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy at the University of Oxford from 1968 to 1987. Strawson states the theory is “completely unintelligible” and dismisses the “imaginary subject of transcendental psychology” as belonging to neither “empirical …, nor to an analytic philosophy of mind” [55].


James T. Hansen in The Journal of Humanistic Counselling, Education and Development states that “the transcendental portion of humanism is like an anchor that severely limits the growth and power of humanistic ideology”[1] . The journal instead discusses a need for non-transcendental humanism that disengages from the idea of ultimate truths. The critic considers Darwinism as the alternate ideology that rejects transcendence and equates humans and animals as more relevant and influential in philosophical thinking [56].

References

  1. ^ a b c Hansen, James T. (2007). "Relational and Transcendental Humanism: Exploring the Consequences of a Thoroughly Pragmatic Humanism". The Journal of Humanistic Counseling, Education and Development. 46 (2): 131–141. doi:10.1002/j.2161-1939.2007.tb00031.x.
  2. ^ Warnke, Georgia (2002). "Book ReviewPaul Ricoeur, . The Just. Translated by David Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000. Pp. xxiv+155. $20.00 (cloth)". Ethics. 112 (2): 406–408. doi:10.1086/324242. ISSN 0014-1704.
  3. ^ Scheibe, Erhard (2001), "Between Rationalism and Empiricism", Between Rationalism and Empiricism, New York, NY: Springer New York, pp. 1–86, ISBN 978-1-4612-6555-9, retrieved 2022-06-02
  4. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l Allison, Henry E. (1971). "Kant's Transcendental Humanism". Monist. 55 (2): 182–207. doi:10.5840/monist197155219. ISSN 0026-9662.
  5. ^ Ludden Jr., David C. (2012). SAGE Brief Guide to Business Ethics. 2455 Teller Road, Thousand Oaks California 91320 United States: SAGE Publications, Inc. ISBN 978-1-4129-9721-8. {{cite book}}: no-break space character in |location= at position 18 (help)CS1 maint: location (link)
  6. ^ Grech, Victor (2016). "Deicide in Star Trek: The Ultimate Expression of Humanism?". Foundation (Dagenham). 45 (123) – via Science Fiction Foundation.
  7. ^ Manemann, Jürgen (2017), "How Could Humanists Become Solidary with the Non-Humanist World? Towards an Anamnestic Humanism", Humanism in a Non-Humanist World, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 117–132, ISBN 978-3-319-57909-2, retrieved 2022-06-02
  8. ^ Brook, Andrew (2018-07-06), "Kant on the mind", Philosophy of Mind in the Early Modern and Modern Ages, New York : Routledge, 2018. | Series: The history of the philosophy of mind ; Volume 4: Routledge, pp. 342–362, retrieved 2022-06-02{{citation}}: CS1 maint: location (link)
  9. ^ Caygill, Howard (2017-08-11). "A Kant Dictionary". doi:10.1002/9781405164658. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  10. ^ "PLATIS'S SOCRATES' ACCUSERS", Studies in Greek Philosophy, Volume II, Princeton University Press, pp. 19–24, 2022-02-08, retrieved 2022-06-02
  11. ^ "Dodge, John Vilas, (25 Sept. 1909–23 April 1991), Senior Editorial Consultant, Encyclopædia Britannica, since 1972; Chairman, Board of Editors, Encyclopædia Britannica Publishers, since 1977", Who Was Who, Oxford University Press, 2007-12-01, retrieved 2022-06-02
  12. ^ Markie, Peter J., "Rationalism", Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, London: Routledge, retrieved 2022-06-02
  13. ^ "9: Empiricism". www.utm.edu. Retrieved 2022-06-02.
  14. ^ "Social Contract by Jean Jacques Rousseau 1762". www.marxists.org. Retrieved 2022-06-02.
  15. ^ Weale, Albert (2020-06-11), "A Method of Ethics?", Modern Social Contract Theory, Oxford University Press, pp. 403–416, retrieved 2022-06-02
  16. ^ "Jean-Jacques Rousseau The Social Contract", Philosophy: The Classics, Routledge, pp. 136–143, 2014-02-03, retrieved 2022-06-02
  17. ^ Simpson, Matthew (2013-02-01), "Rousseau, Jean-Jacques", International Encyclopedia of Ethics, Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing Ltd, retrieved 2022-06-02
  18. ^ Watkins, Eric (2010-05-10), "Immanuel Kant: Theoretical Philosophy", Philosophy, Oxford University Press, retrieved 2022-06-02
  19. ^ Pereboom, Derk (1990). "Kant on justification in transcendental philosophy". Synthese. 85 (1): 25–54. doi:10.1007/BF00873193. ISSN 0039-7857.
  20. ^ Nizhnikov, Sergei (2018). "Foundations of Ethics and Education in the Philosophy of Transcendentalism". Proceedings of the 4th International Conference on Arts, Design and Contemporary Education (ICADCE 2018). Zhengzhou, China: Atlantis Press. doi:10.2991/icadce-18.2018.127. ISBN 978-94-6252-548-1.
  21. ^ "Comparative Religion studies & the Faith vs. Reason Debate - Aldous Huxley & "The Perennial Philosophy"". www.age-of-the-sage.org. Retrieved 2022-06-02.
  22. ^ "Ralph Waldo Emerson | Biography, Poems, Books, Nature, Self-Reliance, & Facts | Britannica". www.britannica.com. Retrieved 2022-06-02.
  23. ^ Uram-Ţuculescu, Sorin; Constantinescu, Marian-Vladimir (2017). "COMPLETE PROSTHESES TREATMENT – PRESENT AND FUTURE PERSPECTIVES". Stomatology Edu Journal. 4 (4): 282–288. doi:10.25241/stomaeduj.2017.4(4).art.5. ISSN 2360-2406.
  24. ^ a b c d e Gobar, Ash (2017). Higher Humanism: A Neotranscendental Philosophy of Life. Peter Lang.
  25. ^ a b c d "Info:Main Page - New World Encyclopedia". www.newworldencyclopedia.org. Retrieved 2022-06-02.
  26. ^ a b "Definition of TRANSCENDENTALISM". www.merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 2022-06-02.
  27. ^ "Kant's Theoretical Philosophy : The Critique of Pure Reason", Kant’s Philosophy, Bloomsbury Academic, retrieved 2022-06-02
  28. ^ Crowe, Benjamin D. (2010). "Fichte's Transcendental Theology". Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie. 92 (1). doi:10.1515/AGPH.2010.003. ISSN 0003-9101.
  29. ^ Dein, Simon (2020). "Transcendence, religion and social bonding". Archive for the Psychology of Religion. 42 (1).
  30. ^ Edara, Inna Reddy (2017). "Religion: A Subset of Culture and an Expression of Spirituality". Advances in Anthropology. 07 (04): 273–288. doi:10.4236/aa.2017.74015. ISSN 2163-9353.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: unflagged free DOI (link)
  31. ^ Gardner, Sebastian; Grist, Matthew, eds. (2015-02-19). "The Transcendental Turn". doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198724872.001.0001. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  32. ^ a b Scott, Alex (2002). "Kant's Critique of Pure Reason". The Power of Language: Philosophy and Society.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: url-status (link)
  33. ^ Jauernig, Anja (2021-02-18), "Kant's Transcendental Idealism and Empirical Realism", The World According to Kant, Oxford University Press, pp. 110–178, retrieved 2022-06-02
  34. ^ "Mobile Internet", Encyclopedia of Educational Philosophy and Theory, Singapore: Springer Singapore, pp. 1456–1456, 2017, retrieved 2022-06-02
  35. ^ a b c d e f Stern, Robert (1999). "Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. Pp. xi, 785. £50 (hbk). ISBN 0-521-65729-6". Kantian Review. 3: 137–140. doi:10.1017/s1369415400000418. ISSN 1369-4154.
  36. ^ Crowe, Benjamin D. (2010). "Fichte's Transcendental Theology". Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie. 92 (1). doi:10.1515/AGPH.2010.003. ISSN 0003-9101.
  37. ^ Figdor, Carrie (2021). "The psychological speciesism of humanism". Philosophical Studies. 178 (5): 1545–1569. doi:10.1007/s11098-020-01495-y. ISSN 0031-8116.
  38. ^ Langer, Ullrich (2016), "Should We Practice Justice Toward Nonhuman Animals? Radical Animal Interests, Humanism, and Classical Justice", Early Modern Humanism and Postmodern Antihumanism in Dialogue, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 49–70, ISBN 978-3-319-32275-9, retrieved 2022-06-02
  39. ^ Manemann, Jürgen (2017), "How Could Humanists Become Solidary with the Non-Humanist World? Towards an Anamnestic Humanism", Humanism in a Non-Humanist World, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 117–132, ISBN 978-3-319-57909-2, retrieved 2022-06-02
  40. ^ "HUMANISTS BEFORE HUMANISM: THE RENAISSANCE", Humanism, Routledge, pp. 80–112, 2006-10-19, ISBN 978-0-203-12972-2, retrieved 2022-06-02
  41. ^ "Scott Cutler Shershow David Hawkes, Ideology (in 'The New Critical Idiom' series, ed. John Drakakis) (London and New York: Routledge, 1996), 210 pp., $49.95 (hardback), $9.95 (paperback) Paul Hamilton, Historicism (in 'The New Critical Idiom' series, ed. John Drakakis (London and New York: Routledge, 1996), 226 pp., $49.95 (hardback), $9.95 (paperback)", Textual Practice, Routledge, pp. 165–168, 2005-06-27, ISBN 978-0-203-98633-2, retrieved 2022-06-02
  42. ^ Craig, Professor Edward; Craig, Edward, eds. (2013-01-11). Concise Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-59392-7.
  43. ^ Grendler, Paul (2010-05-10), "Humanism", Renaissance and Reformation, Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/obo/9780195399301-0002., ISBN 978-0-19-539930-1, retrieved 2022-06-02 {{citation}}: Check |doi= value (help)
  44. ^ Hansen, James T. (2007-09). "Relational and Transcendental Humanism: Exploring the Consequences of a Thoroughly Pragmatic Humanism". The Journal of Humanistic Counseling, Education and Development. 46 (2): 131–141. doi:10.1002/j.2161-1939.2007.tb00031.x. {{cite journal}}: Check date values in: |date= (help)
  45. ^ Langer, Ullrich (2016), "Should We Practice Justice Toward Nonhuman Animals? Radical Animal Interests, Humanism, and Classical Justice", Early Modern Humanism and Postmodern Antihumanism in Dialogue, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 49–70, ISBN 978-3-319-32275-9, retrieved 2022-06-02
  46. ^ Domingo, Vianney (2022). "Re‑Thinking Management: Insights from Western Classical Humanism". Humanistic Management Journal. 7 (1–21).
  47. ^ Watkins, Eric (2010-05-10), "Immanuel Kant: Theoretical Philosophy", Philosophy, Oxford University Press, retrieved 2022-06-02
  48. ^ Baehr, Jason (2013), "A Priori and a Posteriori", Encyclopedia of Philosophy and the Social Sciences, 2455 Teller Road, Thousand Oaks California 91320 United States: SAGE Publications, Inc., retrieved 2022-06-02 {{citation}}: no-break space character in |place= at position 18 (help)CS1 maint: location (link)
  49. ^ Creighton, J. E. (1913). "The Copernican Revolution in Philosophy". The Philosophical Review. 22 (2): 133. doi:10.2307/2178367. ISSN 0031-8108.
  50. ^ "Nicolaus Copernicus | Biography, Facts, Nationality, Discoveries, Accomplishments, & Theory | Britannica". www.britannica.com. Retrieved 2022-06-02.
  51. ^ "Kantianism | philosophy | Britannica". www.britannica.com. Retrieved 2022-06-02.
  52. ^ Braidotti, Rosi (2019). "A Theoretical Framework for the Critical Posthumanities". Theory, Culture & Society. 36 (6): 31–61. doi:10.1177/0263276418771486. ISSN 0263-2764.
  53. ^ Jauernig, Anja (2021-02-18), "Kant's Transcendental Idealism and Empirical Realism", The World According to Kant, Oxford University Press, pp. 110–178, retrieved 2022-06-02
  54. ^ Strawson, Peter (2018-09-14). "The Bounds of Sense". doi:10.4324/9780429447075. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  55. ^ Allison, Henry E., ed. (1996), "On naturalizing Kant's transcendental psychology", Idealism and Freedom: Essays on Kant's Theoretical and Practical Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 53–66, ISBN 978-0-521-48337-7, retrieved 2022-06-02
  56. ^ Gartner, Murray; Cairns, Huntington (1950). "Legal Philosophy from Plato to Hegel". Stanford Law Review. 2 (4): 818. doi:10.2307/1226129. ISSN 0038-9765.

See also