Jump to content

Pluralism (philosophy): Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Brews ohare (talk | contribs)
mNo edit summary
rv WP:RS
Line 3: Line 3:
'''Pluralism''' is a term used in [[philosophy]], meaning "doctrine of multiplicity", often used in opposition to ''[[monism]]'' ("doctrine of unity") and ''[[dualism]]'' ("doctrine of duality"). The term has different meanings in [[metaphysics]], [[ontology]], and [[epistemology]].
'''Pluralism''' is a term used in [[philosophy]], meaning "doctrine of multiplicity", often used in opposition to ''[[monism]]'' ("doctrine of unity") and ''[[dualism]]'' ("doctrine of duality"). The term has different meanings in [[metaphysics]], [[ontology]], and [[epistemology]].


In metaphysics, pluralism is a doctrine that there is more than one [[reality]], while realism holds that there is but one reality, that may have single objective ontology or plural ontology. In one form, it is a doctrine that no single explanatory system or view of reality can account for all the phenomena of life,<ref name=OnLine1/> in contrast with monism which holds reality is a unified whole and that all existing things can be ascribed to or described by a single concept or system,<ref name=OnLine2/> often formulated in terms only of matter ([[materialism]]) or mind ([[idealism]]), while [[dualism]] holds that two substances, such as both matter and mind, are necessary.
In metaphysics, pluralism is a doctrine that there is more than one [[reality]], while realism holds that there is but one reality, that may have single objective ontology or plural ontology. In one form, it is a doctrine that many [[Substance theory|substances]] exist, in contrast with monism which holds [[existence]] to be a single substance, often either matter ([[materialism]]) or mind ([[idealism]]), and [[dualism]] believes two substances, such as matter and mind, to be necessary.


In ontology, pluralism refers to different ways, kinds, or modes of being. For example, a topic in ontological pluralism is the comparison of the modes of existence of things like 'humans' and 'cars' with things like 'numbers' and some other concepts as they are used in science.<ref name=Spencer/>
In ontology, pluralism refers to different ways, kinds, or modes of being. For example, a topic in ontological pluralism is the comparison of the modes of existence of things like 'humans' and 'cars' with things like 'numbers' and some other concepts as they are used in science.<ref name=Spencer/>
Line 77: Line 77:
<ref name=Kellert>
<ref name=Kellert>
{{cite book |chapter=Introduction: The pluralist stance |author=Stephen H Kellert, Helen E Longino, C Kenneth Waters |url=http://www.mcps.umn.edu/assets/pdf/19intro_scipluralism.pdf |page = ''vii'' |title=Scientific pluralism; volume XIX in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science |isbn= 978-0-8166-4763-7 |year=2006 |publisher=The University of Minnesota Press}}
{{cite book |chapter=Introduction: The pluralist stance |author=Stephen H Kellert, Helen E Longino, C Kenneth Waters |url=http://www.mcps.umn.edu/assets/pdf/19intro_scipluralism.pdf |page = ''vii'' |title=Scientific pluralism; volume XIX in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science |isbn= 978-0-8166-4763-7 |year=2006 |publisher=The University of Minnesota Press}}
</ref>

<ref name=OnLine1>
{{cite web |title=pluralism |work=The Free Dictionary |url=http://www.thefreedictionary.com/pluralism |accessdate=2013-08-31}}
</ref>

<ref name=OnLine2>
{{cite web |title=monism |work=The Free Dictionary |url=http://www.thefreedictionary.com/monism |accessdate=2013-08-31}}
</ref>
</ref>



Revision as of 15:40, 31 August 2013

Pluralism is a term used in philosophy, meaning "doctrine of multiplicity", often used in opposition to monism ("doctrine of unity") and dualism ("doctrine of duality"). The term has different meanings in metaphysics, ontology, and epistemology.

In metaphysics, pluralism is a doctrine that there is more than one reality, while realism holds that there is but one reality, that may have single objective ontology or plural ontology. In one form, it is a doctrine that many substances exist, in contrast with monism which holds existence to be a single substance, often either matter (materialism) or mind (idealism), and dualism believes two substances, such as matter and mind, to be necessary.

In ontology, pluralism refers to different ways, kinds, or modes of being. For example, a topic in ontological pluralism is the comparison of the modes of existence of things like 'humans' and 'cars' with things like 'numbers' and some other concepts as they are used in science.[1]

In epistemology, pluralism is the position that there is not one consistent means of approaching truths about the world, but rather many. Often this is associated with pragmatism, or conceptual, contextual, or cultural relativism.

Metaphysical pluralism

Metaphysical pluralism in philosophy is the multiplicity of metaphysical models of the structure and content of reality, both as it appears and as logic dictates that it might be,[2] as is exhibited by the four related models in Plato's Republic,[3] and as developed in the contrast between phenomenalism and physicalism. Pluralism is in contrast to the concept of monism in metaphysics, while dualism is a limited form, a pluralism of exactly two models, structures, elements, or concepts.[4] A distinction is made between the metaphysical identification of realms of reality[5] and the more restricted sub-fields of ontological pluralism (that examines what exists in each of these realms) and epistemological pluralism (that deals with the methodology for establishing knowledge about these realms).

Ancient pluralism

The concept of elements in the Western tradition originates from Babylonian mythology. The Enûma Eliš, a text written between the 18th and 16th centuries BC, describes four cosmic elements: the sea, earth, sky, and wind.[6] In Greece, Empedocles wrote that they were fire, air, water and earth,[7] although he used the word "root" rather than "element" (στοιχεῖον; stoicheion), which appeared later in Plato.[8] From the association (φιλία; philia) and separation (νεῖκος; neikos) of these indestructible and unchangeable root elements, all things came to be in a fullness (πλήρωμα; pleroma) of ratio (λόγος; logos) and proportion (ἀνάλογος; analogos).

Aristotle incorporated these elements, but his substance pluralism was not material in essence. His hylomorphic theory allowed him to maintain a reduced set of basic material elements as per the Milesians, while answering for the ever-changing flux of Heraclitus and the unchanging unity of Parmenides. In his Physics, due to the continuum of Zeno's paradoxes, as well as both logical and empirical considerations for natural science, he presented numerous arguments against the atomism of Leucippus and Democritus, who posited a basic duality of void and atoms. The atoms were an infinite variety of irreducibles, of all shapes and sizes, which randomly collide and mechanically hook together in the void, thus providing a reductive account of changeable figure, order and position as aggregates of the unchangeable atoms.[9]

Ontological pluralism

The topic of ontological pluralism discusses different ways, kinds, or modes of being. Turner suggests that "In contemporary guise, it is the doctrine that a logically perspicuous description of reality will use multiple quantifiers which cannot be thought of as ranging over a single domain."[10] "There are numbers, fictional characters, impossible things, and holes. But, we don’t think these things all exist in the same sense as cars and human beings."[1]

It is common to refer to a film, novel or otherwise fictitious or virtual narrative as not being 'real'. Thus, the characters in the film or novel are not real, where the 'real world' is the everyday world in which we live. However, as authors are wont to say, fiction informs our concept of reality, and so has some kind of reality.[11][12]

Ludwig Wittgenstein's notion of language-games argues that there is no over-arching, single, fundamental ontology, but only a patchwork of overlapping interconnected ontologies ineluctably leading from one to another. For example, Wittgenstein discusses 'number' as technical vocabulary and in more general usage:

"“All right: the concept of 'number' is defined for you as the logical sum of these individual interrelated concepts: cardinal numbers, rational numbers, real numbers etc.;” ... — it need not be so. For I can give the concept 'number' rigid limits in this way, that is, use the word 'number' for a rigidly limited concept, but I can also use it so that the extension of the concept is not closed by a frontier. ...Can you give the boundary? No. You can draw one..."

— Ludwig Wittgenstein, excerpt from §68 in Philosophical Investigations

Wittgenstein suggests that it is not possible to identify a single concept underlying all versions of 'number', but that there are many interconnected meanings that transition one to another; vocabulary need not be restricted to technical meanings to be useful, and indeed technical meanings are 'exact' only within some proscribed context:

Eklund has argued that Wittgenstein's conception includes as a special case the technically constructed, largely autonomous, forms of language or linguistic frameworks of Carnap and Carnapian ontological pluralism. He places Carnap's ontological pluralism in the context of other philosophers, such as Eli Hirsch and Hilary Putnam[13]

Epistemological pluralism

Epistemological pluralism is a term used in philosophy and in other fields of study to refer to different ways of knowing things, different epistemological methodologies for attaining a full description of a particular field.[14] In the philosophy of science epistemological pluralism arose in opposition to reductionism to express the contrary view that at least some natural phenomena cannot be fully explained by a single theory or fully investigated using a single approach.[14][15]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ a b Joshua Spencer (November 12, 2012). "Ways of being". Philosophy Compass. 7 (12): 910–918. doi:10.1111/j.1747-9991.2012.00527.x. {{cite journal}}: Cite has empty unknown parameter: |1= (help)
  2. ^ "Pluralism". Philosophy Pages. Encyclopedia Britannica. Belief that reality ultimately includes many different kinds of things.
  3. ^ Plato, Republic, Book 6 (509D–513E)
  4. ^ D. W. Hamlyn (1984). "Simple substances: Monism and pluralism". Metaphysics. Cambridge University Press. pp. 109 ff. ISBN 0521286905.
  5. ^ Wayne P. Pomerleau (February 11, 2011). "Subsection Realms of reality in article on William James". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  6. ^ Francesca Rochberg (December 2002). "A consideration of Babylonian astronomy within the historiography of science". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. 33 (4): 661–684. doi:10.1016/S0039-3681(02)00022-5.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: postscript (link)
  7. ^ Diels –Kranz,, Simplicius Physics, frag. B-17
  8. ^ Plato, Timaeus, 48 b - c
  9. ^ Aristotle, Metaphysics, I , 4, 985
  10. ^ Jason Turner (April 2012). "Logic and ontological pluralism". Journal of Philosophical Logic. 41 (2): 419–448. doi:10.1007/s10992-010-9167-x.
  11. ^ Deborah A Prentice, Richard J Gerrig (1999). "Chapter 26: Exploring the boundary between fiction and reality". In Shelly Chaiken, Yaacov Trope, eds (ed.). Dual-process theories in social psychology. Guilford Press. pp. 529–546. ISBN 1572304219. {{cite book}}: |editor= has generic name (help)CS1 maint: multiple names: editors list (link)
  12. ^ Hector-Neri Castañeda (April 1979). "Fiction and reality: Their fundamental connections: An essay on the ontology of total experience". Poetics. 8 (1–2): 31–62.
  13. ^ Matti Eklund (2009). "Chapter 4: Carnap and ontological pluralism". In David J Chalmers, David Manley, Ryan Wasserman (ed.). Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Clarendon Press. pp. 130–156. ISBN 0199546002.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: editors list (link) On-line text found at Cornell
  14. ^ a b Stephen H Kellert, Helen E Longino, C Kenneth Waters (2006). "Introduction: The pluralist stance". Scientific pluralism; volume XIX in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science (PDF). The University of Minnesota Press. p. vii. ISBN 978-0-8166-4763-7.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  15. ^ E Brian Davies (2006). "Epistemological pluralism". Available through PhilSci Archive.

Further reading

  • Goodman,Nelson, 1978, Ways of Worldmaking, Hackett, ISBN 0915144522, paperback ISBN 0915144514