Jump to content

Charles Renouvier

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This is an old revision of this page, as edited by InternetArchiveBot (talk | contribs) at 21:19, 19 November 2016 (Rescuing 1 sources and tagging 0 as dead. #IABot (v1.2.7.1)). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

Charles Renouvier
Born(1815-01-01)January 1, 1815
DiedSeptember 1, 1903(1903-09-01) (aged 88)
Alma materÉcole Polytechnique
Era19th-century philosophy
RegionWestern Philosophy
SchoolCritical philosophy[1]
Main interests
Metaphysics
Notable ideas
Néo-criticisme

Charles Bernard Renouvier (French: [ʁənuvje]; January 1, 1815 – September 1, 1903) was a French philosopher.

Biography

Charles B. Renouvier was born in Montpellier and educated in Paris at the École Polytechnique. He took an early interest in politics. Renouvier never held public office, spending his time writing, away from public scrutiny.

Thought

Renouvier was the first Frenchman after Nicolas Malebranche to formulate a complete idealistic system, and had a vast influence on the development of French thought. His system is based on Immanuel Kant's, as his chosen term "néo-criticisme" indicates; but it is a transformation rather than a continuation of Kantianism.

The two leading ideas are the dislike of the "unknowable" in all its forms, and a reliance on the validity of personal experience. The former accounts for Renouvier's acceptance of Kant's phenomenalism, combined with rejection of the thing-in-itself. It accounts, too, for his polemic on the one hand against a Substantial Soul, a Buddhistic Absolute, an Infinite Spiritual Substance; on the other hand against the no less mysterious material or dynamic substratum by which naturalistic Monism explains the world. He holds that nothing exists except presentations, which are not merely sensational, and have an objective aspect no less than a subjective. To explain the formal organization of our experience he adopts a modified version of the Kantian categories.

The insistence on the validity of personal experience leads Renouvier to a yet more important divergence from Kant in his treatment of volition. Liberty, he says, in a much wider sense than Kant, is man's fundamental characteristic. Human freedom acts in the phenomenal, not in an imaginary noumenal sphere. Belief is not intellectual merely, but is determined by an act of will affirming what we hold to be morally good.

In his religious views Renouvier makes a considerable approximation to Gottfried Leibniz. He holds that we are rationally justified in affirming human immortality and the existence of a finite God who is to be a constitutional ruler, but not a despot, over the souls of men. He nevertheless regards atheism as preferable to a belief in an infinite Deity.

Renouvier's dislike of the unknowable also led him to take up arms against the notion of an actual infinite. He believed that an infinite sum must be a name for something incomplete. If one begins to count, "one, two, three ..." there never comes a time when one is entitled to shout "infinity"! Infinity is a project, never a fact, in the neocritical view.

Renouvier became an important influence upon the thought of American psychologist and philosopher William James. James wrote that "but for the decisive impression made on me in the 1870s by his masterly advocacy of pluralism, I might never have got free from the monistic superstition under which I had grown up."

Works

  • Essais de critique générale (1854–64)
  • Science de la morale[3] (1869)
  • Uchronie (1876)
  • Comment je suis arrivé à cette conclusion (1885)
  • Esquisse d'une classification systématique des doctrines philosophiques (1885–86)
  • Philosophie analytique de l'histoire (1896–97)
  • Histoire et solution des problèmes métaphysiques (1901)
  • Victor Hugo: Le Poète (1893)
  • Victor Hugo: Le Philosophe (1900)
  • Les Dilemmes de la métaphysique pure[3] (1901)
  • Le Personnalisme (1903)
  • Critique de la doctrine de Kant[3] (1906)

Notes

  1. ^ John I. Brooks, The Eclectic Legacy: Academic Philosophy and the Human Sciences in Nineteenth-century France, University of Delaware Press, 1998, p. 150.
  2. ^ "Herbert Spencer et Charles Renouvier"
  3. ^ a b c Textes philosophiques complets Archived 2004-12-04 at the Wayback Machine at www.ac-nancy-metz.fr

Further reading

  • Emmanuel Carrère: Le Détroit de Behring. P.O.L., Paris 1986.
  • Paul K. Alkon: Origins of Futuristic Fiction. University of Georgia Press, 1987.
  • Bernard J. Looks: How I Arrived At This Conclusion: A Philosophical Memoir. Translation to English of Renouvier's Comment je suis arrivé à cette conclusion. YBK Publishers, 2011.