Jump to content

Quantum logic: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Saving current version
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Theory of logic to account for observations from quantum theory}}
{{Short description|Theory of logic to account for observations from quantum theory}}
{{Quantum mechanics|cTopic=[[Interpretation of quantum mechanics|Interpretations]]}}
{{Quantum mechanics|cTopic=[[Interpretation of quantum mechanics|Interpretationsma]]}}
In [[quantum mechanics]], '''quantum logic''' is a set of rules for [[reasoning]] about [[proposition]]s that takes the principles of quantum theory into account. This research area and its name originated in a 1936 paper{{sfn|Birkhoff|von Neumann|1936}} by [[Garrett Birkhoff]] and [[John von Neumann]], who were attempting to reconcile the apparent inconsistency of [[classical logic]] with the facts concerning the measurement of [[complementarity (physics)|complementary variable]]s in quantum mechanics, such as [[Position operator|position]] and [[Momentum operator|momentum]].
In [[quantum mechanics]], '''quantum logic''' is a set of rules for [[reasoning]] about [[proposition]]s that takes the principles of quantum theory into account. This research area and its name originated in a 1936 paper{{sfn|Birkhoff|von Neumann|1936}} by [[Garrett Birkhoff]] and [[John von Neumann]], who were attempting to reconcile the apparent inconsistency of [[classical logic]] with the facts concerning the measurement of [[complementarity (physics)|complementary variable]]s in quantum mechanics, such as [[Position operator|position]] and [[Momentum operator|momentum]].


Line 9: Line 9:
The more common view regarding quantum logic, however, is that it provides a [[Formalism (mathematics)|formalism]] for relating [[observable]]s, system preparation filters and [[quantum state|state]]s.{{citation needed|date=February 2014}} In this view, the quantum logic approach resembles more closely the [[C*-algebra]]ic approach to quantum mechanics. The similarities of the quantum logic formalism to a system of [[deductive]] logic may then be regarded more as a curiosity than as a fact of fundamental philosophical importance.
The more common view regarding quantum logic, however, is that it provides a [[Formalism (mathematics)|formalism]] for relating [[observable]]s, system preparation filters and [[quantum state|state]]s.{{citation needed|date=February 2014}} In this view, the quantum logic approach resembles more closely the [[C*-algebra]]ic approach to quantum mechanics. The similarities of the quantum logic formalism to a system of [[deductive]] logic may then be regarded more as a curiosity than as a fact of fundamental philosophical importance.


The need of quantum logic for describing quantum mechanics has been questioned.<ref name=":0" /> Alternative logical approaches to address the apparent paradoxical nature of quantum mechanics include the use of partial Boolean algebras as introduced in the formalism for the [[Kochen-Specker theorem]]<ref>{{Cite journal|last1=Kochen|first1=Simon|last2=Specker|first2=E.|date=1967|title=The Problem of Hidden Variables in Quantum Mechanics|url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1512/iumj.1968.17.17004|journal=Indiana University Mathematics Journal|volume=17|issue=1|pages=59–87|doi=10.1512/iumj.1968.17.17004|issn=0022-2518}}</ref> and explored further in works on [[quantum contextuality]].<ref>{{cite book|last1=Abramsky|first1=Samson|last2=Barbosa|first2=Rui Soares|date=2020-11-05|title=The Logic of Contextuality|series=Leibniz International Proceedings in Informatics (LIPIcs)|volume=183|pages=5:1–5:18|doi=10.4230/LIPIcs.CSL.2021.5|arxiv=2011.03064|isbn=9783959771757|s2cid=226278224}}</ref>
The need of quantum logic for describing quantum mechanics has been questioned.{{sfn|Maudlin|2005}} Alternative logical approaches to address the apparent paradoxical nature of quantum mechanics include the use of partial Boolean algebras as introduced in the formalism for the [[Kochen-Specker theorem]]<ref>{{Cite journal|last1=Kochen|first1=Simon|last2=Specker|first2=E.|date=1967|title=The Problem of Hidden Variables in Quantum Mechanics|url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1512/iumj.1968.17.17004|journal=Indiana University Mathematics Journal|volume=17|issue=1|pages=59–87|doi=10.1512/iumj.1968.17.17004|issn=0022-2518}}</ref> and explored further in works on [[quantum contextuality]].<ref>{{cite book|last1=Abramsky|first1=Samson|last2=Barbosa|first2=Rui Soares|date=2020-11-05|title=The Logic of Contextuality|series=Leibniz International Proceedings in Informatics (LIPIcs)|volume=183|pages=5:1–5:18|doi=10.4230/LIPIcs.CSL.2021.5|arxiv=2011.03064|isbn=9783959771757|s2cid=226278224}}</ref>


==Introduction==
==Differences with classical logic==
Quantum logic has some properties that clearly distinguish it from [[classical logic]], most notably, the failure of the [[distributive law]] of [[propositional logic]]:<ref>Peter Forrest, "Quantum logic" in ''[[Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]'', vol.&nbsp;7, 1998. p.&nbsp;882ff: "[Quantum logic] differs from the standard sentential calculus....The most notable difference is that the distributive laws fail, being replaced by a weaker law known as orthomodularity."</ref>
The most notable difference between quantum logic and [[classical logic]] is the failure of the [[propositional logic|propositional]] [[distributive law]]:<ref>Peter Forrest, "Quantum logic" in ''[[Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]'', vol.&nbsp;7, 1998. p.&nbsp;882ff: "[Quantum logic] differs from the standard sentential calculus....The most notable difference is that the distributive laws fail, being replaced by a weaker law known as orthomodularity."</ref>
:''p'' and (''q'' or ''r'') = (''p'' and ''q'') or (''p'' and ''r''),
:''p'' and (''q'' or ''r'') = (''p'' and ''q'') or (''p'' and ''r''),
where the symbols ''p'', ''q'' and ''r'' are propositional variables. To illustrate why the distributive law fails, consider a particle moving on a line and (using some system of units where the [[reduced Planck's constant]] is 1) let<ref group="Note">Due to technical reasons, it is not possible to represent these propositions as [[Operator (quantum mechanics)|quantum-mechanical operators]]. They are presented here because they are simple enough to enable intuition, and can be considered as limiting cases of operators that ''are'' feasible. See {{Slink||Quantum logic as the logic of observables}} ''et seq.'' for details.</ref>
where the symbols ''p'', ''q'' and ''r'' are propositional variables.
To illustrate why the distributive law fails, consider a particle moving on a line and (using some system of units where the [[reduced Planck's constant]] is 1) let<ref group="Note">Due to technical reasons, it is not possible to represent these propositions as [[Operator (quantum mechanics)|quantum-mechanical operators]]. They are presented here because they are simple enough to enable intuition, and can be considered as limiting cases of operators that ''are'' feasible. See {{Slink||Quantum logic as the logic of observables}} ''et seq.'' for details.</ref>
: ''p'' = "the particle has momentum in the interval [0, +1/6]"
: ''p'' = "the particle has momentum in the interval [0, +1/6]"
: ''q'' = "the particle is in the interval [−1, 1]"
: ''q'' = "the particle is in the interval [−1, 1]"
Line 25: Line 27:
: (''p'' and ''q'') or (''p'' and ''r'') = ''false''
: (''p'' and ''q'') or (''p'' and ''r'') = ''false''


== History ==
Thus the distributive law fails.

== History and connection with lattice theory ==
In his classic 1932 treatise ''[[Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics]]'', [[John von Neumann]] noted that [[projection (mathematics)|projection]]s on a [[Hilbert space]] can be viewed as propositions about physical observables; that is, as potential ''yes-or-no questions'' an observer might ask about the state of a physical system, questions that could be settled by some measurement.{{sfn|von Neumann|1932}} Principles for manipulating these quantum propositions were then called ''quantum logic'' by von Neumann and Birkhoff in a 1936 paper.{{sfn|Birkhoff|von Neumann|1936}}
In his classic 1932 treatise ''[[Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics]]'', [[John von Neumann]] noted that [[projection (mathematics)|projection]]s on a [[Hilbert space]] can be viewed as propositions about physical observables; that is, as potential ''yes-or-no questions'' an observer might ask about the state of a physical system, questions that could be settled by some measurement.{{sfn|von Neumann|1932}} Principles for manipulating these quantum propositions were then called ''quantum logic'' by von Neumann and Birkhoff in a 1936 paper.{{sfn|Birkhoff|von Neumann|1936}}


[[George Mackey]], in his 1963 book (also called ''Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics''), attempted to axiomatize quantum logic as the structure of an [[orthocomplemented lattice]], and recognized that a physical observable could be ''defined'' in terms of quantum propositions. But Mackey's axiom system did not provide any greater generality than conventional presentations of quantum theory, since it assumes that the underlying [[orthocomplemented lattice]] is the [[Lattice (order)|lattice]] of [[closed set|closed]] [[linear subspace]]s of a [[separable space|separable]] Hilbert space.{{sfn|Mackey|1963}} [[Constantin Piron]], Günther Ludwig and others have attempted to give axiomatizations that do not require such explicit relations to the lattice of subspaces.
[[George Mackey]], in his 1963 book (also called ''Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics''), attempted to axiomatize quantum logic as the structure of an [[orthocomplemented lattice]], and recognized that a physical observable could be ''defined'' in terms of quantum propositions. Although Mackey's presentation still assumed that the [[orthocomplemented lattice]] is the [[Lattice (order)|lattice]] of [[closed set|closed]] [[linear subspace]]s of a [[separable space|separable]] Hilbert space,{{sfn|Mackey|1963}} [[Constantin Piron]], Günther Ludwig and others later developed axiomatizations that do not assume an underlying Hilbert space.

Inspired by [[Hans Reichenbach]]'s recent defence of [[general relativity]], the philosopher [[Hilary Putnam]] popularized Mackey's work in two papers in 1968 and 1975.{{sfn|Maudlin|2005}} Putnam hoped to develop a possible alternative to [[hidden variables]] or [[wavefunction collapse]] in the problem of [[quantum measurement]], but [[Gleason's theorem]] presents severe difficulties for this goal.{{sfn|Maudlin|2005}}{{sfn|Wilce}} Putnam later retracted his views, albeit with much less fanfare.{{sfn|Maudlin|2005}}

Quantum logic remains in limited use among logicians as an extremely pathological counterexample (della Chiara and Giuntini: "Why quantum logics? Simply because 'quantum logics are there!'"). Although the central insight to quantum logic remains [[mathematical folklore]] as an intuition pump, discussions rarely mention quantum logic.<ref>[[Terry Tao]], "[https://terrytao.wordpress.com/2021/11/07/venn-and-euler-type-diagrams-for-vector-spaces-and-abelian-groups/ Venn and Euler type diagrams for vector spaces and abelian groups]" on ''What's New'' (blog), 2021.</ref>


== Algebraic structure ==
== Algebraic structure ==
Line 86: Line 90:
* ''p''∨''q'' = ¬(¬''p''∧¬''q'') refers to states that [[quantum superposition|superpose]] ''p'' and ''q''.
* ''p''∨''q'' = ¬(¬''p''∧¬''q'') refers to states that [[quantum superposition|superpose]] ''p'' and ''q''.


This semantics has the nice property that the pre-Hilbert space is complete (i.e., Hilbert) if and only if the propositions satisfy the orthomodular law, a result known as the [[Sol&egrave;r theorem]].<ref name=Handbk />{{sfn|de Ronde|Domenech|Freytes}} Although much of the development of quantum logic has been motivated by the standard semantics, it is not the characterized by the latter; there are additional properties satisfied by that lattice that need not hold in quantum logic.<ref name=Handbk />
This semantics has the nice property that the pre-Hilbert space is complete (i.e., Hilbert) if and only if the propositions satisfy the orthomodular law, a result known as the [[Sol&egrave;r theorem]].<ref>{{harvnb|Della Chiara|Giuntini|2002}} and {{harvnb|de Ronde|Domenech|Freytes}}. Despite claims otherwise, this property is not peculiar to (pre-)Hilbert spaces; an analogous claim holds in most [[Category (math)|categories]]; see John Harding, "[https://www.ams.org/journals/tran/1996-348-05/S0002-9947-96-01548-6/S0002-9947-96-01548-6.pdf Decompositions in Quantum Logic]," ''Transactions of the AMS'', vol.&nbsp;348, no.&nbsp;5, 1996. pp.&nbsp;1839-1862.</ref> But note that this property is not peculiar Although much of the development of quantum logic has been motivated by the standard semantics, it is not the characterized by the latter; there are additional properties satisfied by that lattice that need not hold in quantum logic.<ref name=Handbk />


==Differences with classical logic==
==Differences with classical logic==
Line 132: Line 136:
The operator ''S'' is necessarily non-negative (that is all eigenvalues are non-negative) and of trace 1. Such an operator is often called a ''density operator'' or [[density matrix]], after its [[Coordinate-free|coordinatization]].
The operator ''S'' is necessarily non-negative (that is all eigenvalues are non-negative) and of trace 1. Such an operator is often called a ''density operator'' or [[density matrix]], after its [[Coordinate-free|coordinatization]].


== Alternative semantics ==
== Relationship to other logics ==
Quantum logic embeds into [[linear logic]]<ref name=linear>Vaughan Pratt, "[http://boole.stanford.edu/pub/ql.pdf Linear logic for generalized quantum mechanics]," in ''Proc. of Workshop on Physics and Computation (PhysComp '92)''. See also the discussion at [[#nlab|''n''lab]], [http://ncatlab.org/nlab/revision/quantum%20logic/42 Revision 42], which cites G.D. Crown, "On some orthomodular posets of vector bundles," ''Journ. of Natural Sci. and Math.'', vol.&nbsp;15 issue 1-2: pp.&nbsp;11–25, 1975.</ref> and the [[modal logic]] ''B''.<ref name=Handbk>M.&nbsp;Dalla Chiara and R.&nbsp;Giuntini, "Quantum Logics", in ''Handbook of Philosophical Logic'', vol.&nbsp;6, D.&nbsp;Gabbay and F.&nbsp;Guenthner, (eds.), Kluwer, 2002. arXiv&nbsp;[https://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0101028 quant-ph/0101028].</ref>
Quantum logic embeds into [[linear logic]]<ref name=linear>Vaughan Pratt, "[http://boole.stanford.edu/pub/ql.pdf Linear logic for generalized quantum mechanics]," in ''Proc. of Workshop on Physics and Computation (PhysComp '92)''. See also the discussion at [[#nlab|''n''lab]], [http://ncatlab.org/nlab/revision/quantum%20logic/42 Revision 42], which cites G.D. Crown, "On some orthomodular posets of vector bundles," ''Journ. of Natural Sci. and Math.'', vol.&nbsp;15 issue 1-2: pp.&nbsp;11–25, 1975.</ref> and the [[modal logic]] ''B''.<ref name=Handbk>{{wikicite|M.&nbsp;Della Chiara and R.&nbsp;Giuntini, "Quantum Logics", in ''Handbook of Philosophical Logic'', vol.&nbsp;6, D.&nbsp;Gabbay and F.&nbsp;Guenthner, (eds.), Kluwer, 2002. arXiv&nbsp;[https://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0101028 quant-ph/0101028].|ref={{harvid|Della Chiara|Giuntini|2002}}}}</ref>

The orthocomplemented lattice of any set of quantum propositions can be embedded into a Boolean algebra, which is then amenable to classical logic.<ref>Jeffery Bub & William Demopoulos, "The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics," in ''Logical and Epistemological Studies in Contemporary Physics,'' Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science Vol.&nbsp;13, ed.&nbsp;Robert&nbsp;S. Cohen and Marx&nbsp;W. Wartofsky; D.&nbsp;Riedel, 1974. pp.&nbsp;92-122. DOI:&nbsp;[http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2656-7 10.1007/978-94-010-2656-7]. {{ISBN|978-94-010-2656-7}}.</ref>


== Limitations ==
== Limitations ==
Line 169: Line 175:


== Criticism ==
== Criticism ==
Most philosophers find quantum logic an unappealing competitor to [[classical logic]]. It is far from evident that quantum logic is a ''logic'', in the sense of describing a process of reasoning, as opposed to a particularly convenient language to summarize the measurements performed by quantum apparatuses.{{sfn|Maudlin|2005|p=159-161}}
The approach of quantum logic has been generally seen as unsuccessful. It is far from evident that quantum logic is applicable to truth values (as opposed to switch positions), and if such an application is to be made, it must be done inside the supporting structure of customary two-valued logic. The eminent [[philosopher of science]] [[Tim Maudlin]] writes, “the horse of quantum logic has been so thrashed, whipped and pummeled, and is so thoroughly deceased that...the question is not whether the horse will rise again, it is: how in the world did this horse get here in the first place? The tale of quantum logic is not the tale of a promising idea gone bad, it is rather the tale of the unrelenting pursuit of a bad idea. The entire mathematical complex structure of quantum mechanics is perfectly well-described and clear and understood using [[classical logic]]. While there are interpretive obstacles with [[quantum mechanics]] that have to be dealt with, none of those obstacles can be dealt with, or even ameliorated, by dismissing classical logic."<ref name=":0">{{cite book |last= Maudlin|first= Tim|date= 2005|title= "The Tale of Quantum Logic," in Hilary Putna|chapter= The Tale of Quantum Logic|series= Contemporary Philosophy in Focus|url= https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/hilary-putnam/tale-of-quantum-logic/0879F95D2F957BEAAC7CDC0DF9847262|location= Cambridge|publisher= Cambridge University Press|pages= 184–5|doi= 10.1017/CBO9780511614187.006|isbn= 9780521012546}}</ref>

The [[philosopher of science]] [[Tim Maudlin]] notes that quantum logic "'solves' the [[measurement problem|[measurement] problem]] by making the problem impossible to state" and writes <blockquote>the horse of quantum logic has been so thrashed, whipped and pummeled, and is so thoroughly deceased that...the question is not whether the horse will rise again, it is: how in the world did this horse get here in the first place? The tale of quantum logic is not the tale of a promising idea gone bad, it is rather the tale of the unrelenting pursuit of a bad idea. And this pursuit is by no means Putnam’s alone: many, many philosophers and physicists have become convinced that a change of logic (and most dramatically, the rejection of classical logic) will somehow help in understanding quantum theory, or is somehow suggested or forced on us by quantum theory. But quantum logic, even through its many incarnations and variations, both in technical form and in interpretation, has never yielded the goods.{{sfn|Maudlin|2005}}</blockquote>


== See also ==
== See also ==
Line 205: Line 213:
* G. Ludwig, ''Foundations of Quantum Mechanics'', Springer-Verlag, 1983.
* G. Ludwig, ''Foundations of Quantum Mechanics'', Springer-Verlag, 1983.
* {{wikicite|[[George Mackey|G. Mackey]], ''Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics'', W. A. Benjamin, 1963 (HathiTrust&nbsp;[https://hdl.handle.net/2027/mdp.39015001329567 2027/mdp.39015001329567]; Dover paperback reprint&nbsp;2004).|ref={{harvid|Mackey|1963}}}}
* {{wikicite|[[George Mackey|G. Mackey]], ''Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics'', W. A. Benjamin, 1963 (HathiTrust&nbsp;[https://hdl.handle.net/2027/mdp.39015001329567 2027/mdp.39015001329567]; Dover paperback reprint&nbsp;2004).|ref={{harvid|Mackey|1963}}}}
* {{wikicite|[[Tim Maudlin]], "[https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/hilary-putnam/tale-of-quantum-logic/0879F95D2F957BEAAC7CDC0DF9847262 The Tale of Quantum Logic]" in ''Hilary Putnam''; [[Cambridge University Press]] "Contemporary Philosophy in Focus" series, 2005. pp.&nbsp;184-5. DOI:&nbsp;[http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511614187.006 10.1017/CBO9780511614187.006] {{ISBN|9780521012546}}.|ref={{harvid|Maudlin|2005}}}}
* {{wikicite|J. von Neumann, ''Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics'', Princeton University Press, 1955 (paperback reprint; original 1932).|ref={{harvid|von Neumann|1932}}}}
* {{wikicite|J. von Neumann, ''Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics'', Princeton University Press, 1955 (paperback reprint; original 1932).|ref={{harvid|von Neumann|1932}}}}
* R. Omnès, ''[https://archive.org/details/understandingqua00omne <!-- quote="quantum logic". --> Understanding Quantum Mechanics]'', Princeton University Press, 1999. An extraordinarily lucid discussion of some logical and philosophical issues of quantum mechanics, with careful attention to the history of the subject. Also discusses consistent histories.
* R. Omnès, ''[https://archive.org/details/understandingqua00omne <!-- quote="quantum logic". --> Understanding Quantum Mechanics]'', Princeton University Press, 1999. An extraordinarily lucid discussion of some logical and philosophical issues of quantum mechanics, with careful attention to the history of the subject. Also discusses consistent histories.
Line 210: Line 219:
* {{wikicite|[[Constantin Piron|C. Piron]], ''Foundations of Quantum Physics'', W. A. Benjamin, 1976.|ref={{harvid|Piron|1976}}}}
* {{wikicite|[[Constantin Piron|C. Piron]], ''Foundations of Quantum Physics'', W. A. Benjamin, 1976.|ref={{harvid|Piron|1976}}}}
* [[Hilary Putnam|H. Putnam]], ''Is Logic Empirical?'', Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science Vol. V, 1969
* [[Hilary Putnam|H. Putnam]], ''Is Logic Empirical?'', Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science Vol. V, 1969
* {{IEP|qu-logic|Quantum Logic in Historical and Philosophical Perspective|author-first1=C.|author-last1=de&nbsp;Ronde|author-first2=G.|author-last2=Domenech|author-first3=H.|author-last3=Freytes|name-list-style=vanc<!--not quite the style here, but close enough-->}}
* {{IEP|qu-logic|Quantum Logic in Historical and Philosophical Perspective|author-first1=C.|author-last1=de&nbsp;Ronde|author-first2=G.|author-last2=Domenech|author-first3=H.|author-last3=Freytes}}
* [[H. Weyl]], ''The Theory of Groups and Quantum Mechanics'', Dover Publications, 1950.
* [[H. Weyl]], ''The Theory of Groups and Quantum Mechanics'', Dover Publications, 1950.
* {{cite SEP |url-id=qt-quantlog |title=Quantum Logic and Probability Theory |last=Wilce |first=Alexander}}
* {{cite SEP |url-id=qt-quantlog |title=Quantum Logic and Probability Theory |last=Wilce |first=Alexander}}

Revision as of 06:00, 21 August 2022

In quantum mechanics, quantum logic is a set of rules for reasoning about propositions that takes the principles of quantum theory into account. This research area and its name originated in a 1936 paper[1] by Garrett Birkhoff and John von Neumann, who were attempting to reconcile the apparent inconsistency of classical logic with the facts concerning the measurement of complementary variables in quantum mechanics, such as position and momentum.

Quantum logic can be formulated either as a modified version of propositional logic or as a noncommutative and non-associative many-valued logic.[2][3][4][5][6]

Quantum logic has been proposed as the correct logic for propositional inference generally, most notably by the philosopher Hilary Putnam, at least at one point in his career. This thesis was an important ingredient in Putnam's 1968 paper "Is Logic Empirical?" in which he analysed the epistemological status of the rules of propositional logic. Putnam attributes the idea that anomalies associated to quantum measurements originate with anomalies in the logic of physics itself to the physicist David Finkelstein. However, this idea had been around for some time and had been revived several years earlier by George Mackey's work on group representations and symmetry.

The more common view regarding quantum logic, however, is that it provides a formalism for relating observables, system preparation filters and states.[citation needed] In this view, the quantum logic approach resembles more closely the C*-algebraic approach to quantum mechanics. The similarities of the quantum logic formalism to a system of deductive logic may then be regarded more as a curiosity than as a fact of fundamental philosophical importance.

The need of quantum logic for describing quantum mechanics has been questioned.[7] Alternative logical approaches to address the apparent paradoxical nature of quantum mechanics include the use of partial Boolean algebras as introduced in the formalism for the Kochen-Specker theorem[8] and explored further in works on quantum contextuality.[9]

Introduction

The most notable difference between quantum logic and classical logic is the failure of the propositional distributive law:[10]

p and (q or r) = (p and q) or (p and r),

where the symbols p, q and r are propositional variables.

To illustrate why the distributive law fails, consider a particle moving on a line and (using some system of units where the reduced Planck's constant is 1) let[Note 1]

p = "the particle has momentum in the interval [0, +1/6]"
q = "the particle is in the interval [−1, 1]"
r = "the particle is in the interval [1, 3]"

We might observe that:

p and (q or r) = true

in other words, that the state of the particle is a weighted superposition of momenta between 0 and +1/6 and positions between −1 and +3.

On the other hand, the propositions "p and q" and "p and r" each assert tighter restrictions on simultaneous values of position and momentum than are allowed by the uncertainty principle (they each have uncertainty 1/3, which is less than the allowed minimum of 1/2). So there are no states that can support either proposition, and

(p and q) or (p and r) = false

History

In his classic 1932 treatise Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, John von Neumann noted that projections on a Hilbert space can be viewed as propositions about physical observables; that is, as potential yes-or-no questions an observer might ask about the state of a physical system, questions that could be settled by some measurement.[11] Principles for manipulating these quantum propositions were then called quantum logic by von Neumann and Birkhoff in a 1936 paper.[1]

George Mackey, in his 1963 book (also called Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics), attempted to axiomatize quantum logic as the structure of an orthocomplemented lattice, and recognized that a physical observable could be defined in terms of quantum propositions. Although Mackey's presentation still assumed that the orthocomplemented lattice is the lattice of closed linear subspaces of a separable Hilbert space,[12] Constantin Piron, Günther Ludwig and others later developed axiomatizations that do not assume an underlying Hilbert space.

Inspired by Hans Reichenbach's recent defence of general relativity, the philosopher Hilary Putnam popularized Mackey's work in two papers in 1968 and 1975.[7] Putnam hoped to develop a possible alternative to hidden variables or wavefunction collapse in the problem of quantum measurement, but Gleason's theorem presents severe difficulties for this goal.[7][13] Putnam later retracted his views, albeit with much less fanfare.[7]

Quantum logic remains in limited use among logicians as an extremely pathological counterexample (della Chiara and Giuntini: "Why quantum logics? Simply because 'quantum logics are there!'"). Although the central insight to quantum logic remains mathematical folklore as an intuition pump, discussions rarely mention quantum logic.[14]

Algebraic structure

Quantum logic can be axiomatized as the theory of propositions modulo the following identities:[15]

  • a=¬¬a
  • ∨ is commutative and associative.
  • There is a maximal element ⊤, and ⊤=bb for any b.
  • a∨¬(¬ab)=a.

("¬" is the traditional notation for "not", "∨" the notation for "or", and "∧" the notation for "and".)

Some authors restrict to orthomodular lattices, which additionally satisfy the orthomodular law:

  • If ⊤=¬(¬a∨¬b)∨¬(ab) then a=b.

("⊤" is the traditional notation for truth and "⊥" the traditional notation for falsity.)

Alternative formulations include propositions derivable via a natural deduction,[2] sequent calculus[16][17] or tableaux system.[18] Despite the relatively developed proof theory, quantum logic is not known to be decidable.[15]

Quantum logic as the logic of observables

The remainder of this article assumes the reader is familiar with the spectral theory of self-adjoint operators on a Hilbert space. However, the main ideas can be understood in the finite-dimensional case.

The logic of classical mechanics

The Hamiltonian formulations of classical mechanics have three ingredients: states, observables and dynamics. In the simplest case of a single particle moving in R3, the state space is the position-momentum space R6. An observable is some real-valued function f on the state space. Examples of observables are position, momentum or energy of a particle. For classical systems, the value f(x), that is the value of f for some particular system state x, is obtained by a process of measurement of f.

The propositions concerning a classical system are generated from basic statements of the form

"Measurement of f yields a value in the interval [a, b] for some real numbers a, b."

through the conventional arithmetic operations and pointwise limits. It follows easily from this characterization of propositions in classical systems that the corresponding logic is identical to the Boolean algebra of Borel subsets of the state space. They thus obey the laws of classical propositional logic (such as de Morgan's laws) with the set operations of union and intersection corresponding to the Boolean conjunctives and subset inclusion corresponding to material implication.

In fact, a stronger claim is true: they must obey the infinitary logic Lω1.

We summarize these remarks as follows: The proposition system of a classical system is a lattice with a distinguished orthocomplementation operation: The lattice operations of meet and join are respectively set intersection and set union. The orthocomplementation operation is set complement. Moreover, this lattice is sequentially complete, in the sense that any sequence {Ei}i of elements of the lattice has a least upper bound, specifically the set-theoretic union:

The propositional lattice of a quantum mechanical system

In the Hilbert space formulation of quantum mechanics as presented by von Neumann, a physical observable is represented by some (possibly unbounded) densely defined self-adjoint operator A on a Hilbert space H. A has a spectral decomposition, which is a projection-valued measure E defined on the Borel subsets of R. In particular, for any bounded Borel function f on R, the following extension of f to operators can be made:

In case f is the indicator function of an interval [a, b], the operator f(A) is a self-adjoint projection onto the subspace of generalized eigenvectors of A with eigenvalue in [a,b]. That subspace can be interpreted as the quantum analogue of the classical proposition

  • Measurement of A yields a value in the interval [a, b].

This suggests the following quantum mechanical replacement for the orthocomplemented lattice of propositions in classical mechanics, essentially Mackey's Axiom VII:

  • The propositions of a quantum mechanical system correspond to the lattice of closed subspaces of H; the negation of a proposition V is the orthogonal complement V.

The space Q of quantum propositions is also sequentially complete: any pairwise disjoint sequence{Vi}i of elements of Q has a least upper bound. Here disjointness of W1 and W2 means W2 is a subspace of W1. The least upper bound of {Vi}i is the closed internal direct sum.

Standard semantics

The standard semantics of quantum logic is that quantum logic is the logic of projection operators in a separable Hilbert or pre-Hilbert space, where an observable p is associated with the set of quantum states for which p (when measured) has eigenvalue 1. From there,

  • ¬p is the orthogonal complement of p (since for those states, the probability of observing p, P(p) = 0),
  • pq is the intersection of p and q, and
  • pq = ¬(¬p∧¬q) refers to states that superpose p and q.

This semantics has the nice property that the pre-Hilbert space is complete (i.e., Hilbert) if and only if the propositions satisfy the orthomodular law, a result known as the Solèr theorem.[19] But note that this property is not peculiar Although much of the development of quantum logic has been motivated by the standard semantics, it is not the characterized by the latter; there are additional properties satisfied by that lattice that need not hold in quantum logic.[2]

Differences with classical logic

The structure of Q immediately points to a difference with the partial order structure of a classical proposition system. In the classical case, given a proposition p, the equations

⊤=pq and
⊥=pq

have exactly one solution, namely the set-theoretic complement of p. In the case of the lattice of projections there are infinitely many solutions to the above equations (any closed, algebraic complement of p solves it; it need not be the orthocomplement).

Failure of distributivity

Expressions in quantum logic describe observables using a syntax that resembles classical logic. However, unlike classical logic, the distributive law a ∧ (bc) = (ab) ∨ (ac) fails when dealing with noncommuting observables, such as position and momentum. This occurs because measurement affects the system, and measurement of whether a disjunction holds does not measure which of the disjuncts is true.

For example, consider a simple one-dimensional particle with position denoted by x and momentum by p, and define observables:

  • a — |p| ≤ 1 (in some units)
  • b — x < 0
  • c — x ≥ 0

Now, position and momentum are Fourier transforms of each other, and the Fourier transform of a square-integrable nonzero function with a compact support is entire and hence does not have non-isolated zeroes. Therefore, there is no wave function that is both normalizable in momentum space and vanishes on precisely x ≥ 0. Thus, ab and similarly ac are false, so (ab) ∨ (ac) is false. However, a ∧ (bc) equals a, which is certainly not false (there are states for which it is a viable measurement outcome). Moreover: if the relevant Hilbert space for the particle's dynamics only admits momenta no greater than 1, then a is true.

To understand more, let p1 and p2 be the momenta for the restriction of the particle wave function to x < 0 and x ≥ 0 respectively (with the wave function zero outside of the restriction). Let |p|↾>1 be the restriction of |p| to momenta that are (in absolute value) >1.

(ab) ∨ (ac) corresponds to states with |p1|↾>1=0 and |p2|↾>1 (this holds even if we defined p differently so as to make such states possible; also, ab corresponds to |p1|↾>1=0 and p2=0). As an operator, p=p1+p2, and nonzero |p1|↾>1 and |p2|↾>1 might interfere to produce zero |p|↾>1. Such interference is key to the richness of quantum logic and quantum mechanics.

Relationship to quantum measurement

Mackey observables

Given a orthocomplemented lattice Q, a Mackey observable φ is a countably additive homomorphism from the orthocomplemented lattice of Borel subsets of R to Q. In symbols, this means that for any sequence {Si}i of pairwise disjoint Borel subsets of R, {φ(Si)}i are pairwise orthogonal propositions (elements of Q) and

Equivalently, a Mackey observable is a projection-valued measure on R.

Theorem (Spectral theorem). If Q is the lattice of closed subspaces of Hilbert H, then there is a bijective correspondence between Mackey observables and densely defined self-adjoint operators on H.

Quantum probability measures

A quantum probability measure is a function P defined on Q with values in [0,1] such that P(⊥)=0, P(⊤)=1 and if {Ei}i is a sequence of pairwise orthogonal elements of Q then

The following highly non-trivial theorem is due to Andrew Gleason:

Theorem. Suppose Q is the lattice of closed subspaces of a separable Hilbert space of complex dimension at least 3. Then for any quantum probability measure P on Q there exists a unique trace class operator S such that

for any self-adjoint projection E in Q.

The operator S is necessarily non-negative (that is all eigenvalues are non-negative) and of trace 1. Such an operator is often called a density operator or density matrix, after its coordinatization.

Relationship to other logics

Quantum logic embeds into linear logic[20] and the modal logic B.[2]

The orthocomplemented lattice of any set of quantum propositions can be embedded into a Boolean algebra, which is then amenable to classical logic.[21]

Limitations

Although many treatments of quantum logic assume that the underlying lattice must be orthomodular, such logics cannot handle multiple interacting quantum systems. In an example due to Foulis and Randall, there are orthomodular propositions with (finite-dimensional!) Hilbert models, whose pairing admits no orthomodular model.[13]

Quantum logic admits no reasonable material conditional; any connective that is monotone in a certain, technical sense reduces the class of propositions to a Boolean algebra.[22] Consequently quantum logic struggles to represent the passage of time.[20] One possible workaround is the theory of quantum filtrations developed in the late 1970s and 1980s by Belavkin.[23][24] It is known, however, that System BV, a deep inference fragment of linear logic that is very close to quantum logic, can handle arbitrary discrete spacetimes.[25]

Criticism

Most philosophers find quantum logic an unappealing competitor to classical logic. It is far from evident that quantum logic is a logic, in the sense of describing a process of reasoning, as opposed to a particularly convenient language to summarize the measurements performed by quantum apparatuses.[26]

The philosopher of science Tim Maudlin notes that quantum logic "'solves' the [measurement] problem by making the problem impossible to state" and writes

the horse of quantum logic has been so thrashed, whipped and pummeled, and is so thoroughly deceased that...the question is not whether the horse will rise again, it is: how in the world did this horse get here in the first place? The tale of quantum logic is not the tale of a promising idea gone bad, it is rather the tale of the unrelenting pursuit of a bad idea. And this pursuit is by no means Putnam’s alone: many, many philosophers and physicists have become convinced that a change of logic (and most dramatically, the rejection of classical logic) will somehow help in understanding quantum theory, or is somehow suggested or forced on us by quantum theory. But quantum logic, even through its many incarnations and variations, both in technical form and in interpretation, has never yielded the goods.[7]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Due to technical reasons, it is not possible to represent these propositions as quantum-mechanical operators. They are presented here because they are simple enough to enable intuition, and can be considered as limiting cases of operators that are feasible. See § Quantum logic as the logic of observables et seq. for details.

References

  1. ^ a b Birkhoff & von Neumann 1936.
  2. ^ a b c d M. Della Chiara and R. Giuntini, "Quantum Logics", in Handbook of Philosophical Logic, vol. 6, D. Gabbay and F. Guenthner, (eds.), Kluwer, 2002. arXiv quant-ph/0101028.
  3. ^ Dalla Chiara, M. L.; Giuntini, R. (1994). "Unsharp quantum logics". Foundations of Physics. 24 (8): 1161–1177. Bibcode:1994FoPh...24.1161D. doi:10.1007/bf02057862. S2CID 122872424.
  4. ^ [1] [permanent dead link] I. C. Baianu. 2009. Quantum LMn Algebraic Logic.
  5. ^ Georgescu, G.; Vraciu, C. (1970). "On the characterization of centered Łukasiewicz algebras". J. Algebra. 16 (4): 486–495. doi:10.1016/0021-8693(70)90002-5.
  6. ^ Georgescu, G (2006). "N-valued Logics and Łukasiewicz-Moisil Algebras". Axiomathes. 16 (1–2): 123. doi:10.1007/s10516-005-4145-6. S2CID 121264473.
  7. ^ a b c d e Maudlin 2005.
  8. ^ Kochen, Simon; Specker, E. (1967). "The Problem of Hidden Variables in Quantum Mechanics". Indiana University Mathematics Journal. 17 (1): 59–87. doi:10.1512/iumj.1968.17.17004. ISSN 0022-2518.
  9. ^ Abramsky, Samson; Barbosa, Rui Soares (2020-11-05). The Logic of Contextuality. Leibniz International Proceedings in Informatics (LIPIcs). Vol. 183. pp. 5:1–5:18. arXiv:2011.03064. doi:10.4230/LIPIcs.CSL.2021.5. ISBN 9783959771757. S2CID 226278224.
  10. ^ Peter Forrest, "Quantum logic" in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 7, 1998. p. 882ff: "[Quantum logic] differs from the standard sentential calculus....The most notable difference is that the distributive laws fail, being replaced by a weaker law known as orthomodularity."
  11. ^ von Neumann 1932.
  12. ^ Mackey 1963.
  13. ^ a b Wilce.
  14. ^ Terry Tao, "Venn and Euler type diagrams for vector spaces and abelian groups" on What's New (blog), 2021.
  15. ^ a b Megill 2019.
  16. ^ N.J. Cutland; P.F. Gibbins (Sep 1982). "A regular sequent calculus for Quantum Logic in which ∨ and ∧ are dual". Logique et Analyse. Nouvelle Série. 25 (99): 221–248. JSTOR 44084050.
  17. ^
  18. ^ Uwe Egly; Hans Tompits (1999). "Gentzen-like Methods in Quantum Logic" (PDF). Proc. 8th Int. Conf. on Automated Reasoning with Analytic Tableaux and Related Methods (TABLEAUX). University at Albany — SUNY. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.88.9045.
  19. ^ Della Chiara & Giuntini 2002 and de Ronde, Domenech & Freytes. Despite claims otherwise, this property is not peculiar to (pre-)Hilbert spaces; an analogous claim holds in most categories; see John Harding, "Decompositions in Quantum Logic," Transactions of the AMS, vol. 348, no. 5, 1996. pp. 1839-1862.
  20. ^ a b Vaughan Pratt, "Linear logic for generalized quantum mechanics," in Proc. of Workshop on Physics and Computation (PhysComp '92). See also the discussion at nlab, Revision 42, which cites G.D. Crown, "On some orthomodular posets of vector bundles," Journ. of Natural Sci. and Math., vol. 15 issue 1-2: pp. 11–25, 1975.
  21. ^ Jeffery Bub & William Demopoulos, "The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics," in Logical and Epistemological Studies in Contemporary Physics, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science Vol. 13, ed. Robert S. Cohen and Marx W. Wartofsky; D. Riedel, 1974. pp. 92-122. DOI: 10.1007/978-94-010-2656-7. ISBN 978-94-010-2656-7.
  22. ^ L. Román and B. Rumbos, "Quantum Logic Revisited," Foundations of Physics; Plenum Publishing, Vol. 21, No. 6, 1991, pp. 727-734. DOI: 10.1007/BF00733278. See § 2.
  23. ^
    • V. P. Belavkin (1978). "Optimal quantum filtration of Makovian signals [In Russian]". Problems of Control and Information Theory. 7 (5): 345–360.
    • V. P. Belavkin (1992). "Quantum stochastic calculus and quantum nonlinear filtering". Journal of Multivariate Analysis. 42 (2): 171–201. arXiv:math/0512362. doi:10.1016/0047-259X(92)90042-E. S2CID 3909067.
  24. ^ Luc Bouten; Ramon van Handel; Matthew R. James (2009). "A discrete invitation to quantum filtering and feedback control". SIAM Review. 51 (2): 239–316. arXiv:math/0606118. Bibcode:2009SIAMR..51..239B. doi:10.1137/060671504. S2CID 10435983.
  25. ^ Richard Blute, Alessio Guglielmi, Ivan T. Ivanov, Prakash Panangaden, Lutz Straßburger, "A Logical Basis for Quantum Evolution and Entanglement" in Categories and Types in Logic, Language, and Physics: Essays Dedicated to Jim Lambek on the Occasion of His 90th Birthday; Springer, 2014. pp. 90-107. DOI: 10.1007/978-3-642-54789-8_6. HAL 01092279.
  26. ^ Maudlin 2005, p. 159-161.

Further reading

External links