Jump to content

Wigner's friend: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Gmusser (talk | contribs)
Discussion: addition of new reference
Gmusser (talk | contribs)
m Discussion: fixed typo
Line 193: Line 193:


=== Discussion ===
=== Discussion ===
The meaning and implications of the Extended Wigner's friend thought experiment are still highly debated. A number of assumptions taken in the argument are very foundational in content, and therefore cannot be given up easily. However, the questions remains whether there are "hidden" assumptions that do not explicitly appear in the argument. The authors themselves seem to favour the rejection of their (implicit) assumption that macroscopic agents can be modelled as physical systems by quantum theory. Their rejection then renders their conclusion that "quantum theory cannot be extrapolated to complex systems, at least not in a straightforward manner".<ref name=":2" /> On the other hand, one presentation of the experiment as a quantum circuit models the agents as single qubits and their reasoning as simple conditional operations.<ref>{{cite web |url= https://fqxi.org/community/forum/topic/3354 |title= Watching the Watchmen: Demystifying the Frauchiger-Renner Experiment |last=Musser |first=George |date=December 30, 2019 |website=FQXi.org |access-date=December 28, 2019}}</ref>
The meaning and implications of the Extended Wigner's friend thought experiment are still highly debated. A number of assumptions taken in the argument are very foundational in content, and therefore cannot be given up easily. However, the questions remains whether there are "hidden" assumptions that do not explicitly appear in the argument. The authors themselves seem to favour the rejection of their (implicit) assumption that macroscopic agents can be modelled as physical systems by quantum theory. Their rejection then renders their conclusion that "quantum theory cannot be extrapolated to complex systems, at least not in a straightforward manner".<ref name=":2" /> On the other hand, one presentation of the experiment as a quantum circuit models the agents as single qubits and their reasoning as simple conditional operations.<ref>{{cite web |url= https://fqxi.org/community/forum/topic/3354 |title= Watching the Watchmen: Demystifying the Frauchiger-Renner Experiment |last=Musser |first=George |date=December 24, 2019 |website=FQXi.org |access-date=December 28, 2019}}</ref>


The impact of the Extended Wigner's friend [[thought experiment]] on current discussion about the foundations of quantum theory is highlighted by the fact that none of the different [[interpretations of quantum mechanics]] is able to provide a universally accepted explanation.
The impact of the Extended Wigner's friend [[thought experiment]] on current discussion about the foundations of quantum theory is highlighted by the fact that none of the different [[interpretations of quantum mechanics]] is able to provide a universally accepted explanation.

Revision as of 17:30, 28 December 2019

Wigner's friend is a thought experiment in theoretical quantum physics, proposed by the physicist Eugene Wigner in 1961.[1] The scenario involves an indirect observation of a quantum measurement: An observer W observes another observer F who performs a quantum measurement on a physical system. The two observers then formulate a statement about the physical system's state after the measurement according to the laws of quantum theory. However, in most of the interpretations of quantum theory, the resulting statements of the two observers contradict each other. This reflects a seeming incompatibility of two laws in quantum theory: the deterministic and continuous time evolution of the state of a closed system and the probabilistic, discontinuous collapse of the state of a system upon measurement. Wigner's friend is therefore directly linked to the measurement problem in quantum mechanics with its famous Schrödinger's cat paradox.

The thought experiment

The thought experiment posits a friend of Wigner in a laboratory, and lets the friend perform a quantum measurement on a physical system (this could be a spin system or something analogous to Schrödinger's cat). This system is assumed to be in a superposition of two distinct states, say, state 0 and state 1 (or "dead" and "alive", in the case of Schrödinger's cat). When Wigner's friend measures the system in the 0/1-basis, according to quantum mechanics, they will get one of the two possible outcomes (0 or 1) and the system collapses into the corresponding state.

Now Wigner himself models the scenario from outside the laboratory, knowing that inside, his friend will at some point perform the 0/1-measurement on the physical system. According to the linearity of the quantum mechanical equations, Wigner will assign a superposition state to the whole laboratory (i.e. the joint system of the physical system together with the friend): The superposition state of the lab is then a linear combination of "system is in state 0/ friend has measured 0" and "system is in state 1/ friend has measured 1".

Let Wigner now ask his friend for the result of the measurement: whichever answer the friend gives (0 or 1), Wigner would then assign the state "system is in state 0/ friend has measured 0" or "system is in state 1/ friend has measured 1" to the laboratory. Therefore, it is only at the time when he learns about his friend's result that the superposition state of the laboratory collapses.

However, unless Wigner is considered in a "privileged position as ultimate observer",[1] the friend's point of view must be regarded as equally valid, and this is where an apparent paradox comes into play: From the point of view of the friend, the measurement result was determined long before Wigner had asked about it, and the state of the physical system has already collapsed. When now exactly did the collapse occur? Was it when the friend had finished their measurement, or when the information of its result entered Wigner's consciousness?

Mathematical description

Assume for simplicity that the physical system is a two-state spin system with states and , corresponding to measurement results 0 and 1.

Initially, is in a superposition state

and gets measured by Wigner's friend () in the - basis. Then, with probability , will measure 0 and with probability , will measure 1.

From the friend's point of view, the spin has collapsed into one of its basis states upon his measurement, and hence, they will assign to the spin the state corresponding to their measurement result: If they got 0, they will assign the state to the spin, if they got 1, they will assign the state to the spin.

Wigner () now models the combined system of the spin together with his friend (the joint system is given by the tensor product ). He thereby takes a viewpoint outside of 's laboratory, which is considered isolated from the environment. Hence, by the laws of quantum mechanics for isolated systems, the state of the whole laboratory evolves unitarily in time. Therefore, the correct description of the state of the joint system as seen from outside is the superposition state

,

where denotes the state of the friend when they have measured 0, and denotes the state of the friend when they have measured 1.

For an initial state of , the state for would be after ' s measurement, and for an initial state , the state of would be . Now, by the linearity of Schrödinger's quantum mechanical equations of motion, an initial state for results in the superposition for .

Discussion

Consciousness and Wigner's friend

Eugene Wigner designed the thought experiment to illustrate his belief that consciousness is necessary to the quantum mechanical measurement process (and therefore, that consciousness in general must be an "ultimate reality"[1] according to Descartes's "Cogito ergo sum" philosophy): "All that quantum mechanics purports to provide are probability connections between subsequent impressions (also called 'apperceptions') of the consciousness".[1]

Here, "impressions of the consciousness" are understood as specific knowledge about a (measured) system, i.e., the result of an observation. This way, the content of one's consciousness is precisely all knowledge of one’s external world and measurements are defined as the interactions which create the impressions in our consciousness. Since the knowledge about any quantum mechanical wave function is based on such impressions, the wave function of a physical system is modified once the information about the system enters our consciousness. This idea has become known as the "consciousness causes collapse" interpretation.

In the Wigner's friend thought experiment, this (Wigner's) view comes in as follows:

The friend's consciousness gets "impressed" by their measurement of the spin, and therefore they may assign a wave function to it according to the nature of their impression. Wigner, having no access to that information, can only assign the wave function to the joint system of spin and friend after the interaction. When he then asks his friend about the measurement outcome, Wigner's consciousness gets "impressed" by the friend's answer: As a result, Wigner will be able to assign a wave function to the spin system, i.e., he will assign to it the wave function corresponding to the friend's answer.

So far, there is no inconsistency in the theory of measurement. However, Wigner then learns (by asking his friend again) that the feelings/ thoughts of his friend about the measurement outcome had been in the friend's mind long before Wigner had asked about them in the first place. Therefore, the correct wave function for the joint system of spin and friend just after the interaction must have been either or , and not their linear combination. Hence, there is a contradiction, specifically in the "consciousness causes collapse" interpretation.

Wigner then follows that "the being with a consciousness must have a different role in quantum mechanics than the inanimate measuring device":[1] If the friend were replaced by some measuring device without a consciousness, the superposition state would describe the joint system of spin and device correctly. In addition, Wigner considers a superposition state for a human being to be absurd, as the friend could not have been in a state of "suspended animation"[1] before they answered the question. This view would need the quantum mechanical equations to be non-linear. It is Wigner's belief that the laws of physics must be modified when allowing conscious beings to be included.

The above and other of Wigner's original remarks about his friend appeared in his article "Remarks on the Mind-Body Question", published in the book The Scientist Speculates (1961), edited by I. J. Good. The article is reprinted in Wigner's own book Symmetries and Reflections (1967).

A counterargument

A counterargument is that the superimposition of two conscious states is not paradoxical – just as there is no interaction between the multiple quantum states of a particle, so the superimposed consciousnesses need not be aware of each other.[2]

The state of the observer's perception is considered to be entangled with the state of the cat. The perception state "I perceive a live cat" accompanies the "live-cat" state and the perception state "I perceive a dead cat" accompanies the "dead-cat" state. ... It is then assumed that a perceiving being always finds his/her perception state to be in one of these two; accordingly, the cat is, in the perceived world, either alive or dead. ... I wish to make clear that, as it stands, this is far from a resolution of the cat paradox. For there is nothing in the formalism of quantum mechanics that demands that a state of consciousness cannot involve the simultaneous perception of a live and a dead cat.

Wigner's friend in the many-worlds interpretation

The various versions of the many worlds interpretation avoid the need to postulate that consciousness causes collapse – indeed, that collapse occurs at all.

Hugh Everett III's doctoral thesis "'Relative state' formulation of quantum mechanics"[3] serves as the foundation for today's many versions of many-worlds interpretations. In the introductory part of his work, Everett discusses the "amusing, but extremely hypothetical drama" of the Wigner's friend paradox. Note that there is evidence of a drawing of the scenario in an early draft of Everett's thesis.[4] It was therefore Everett who provided the first written discussion of the problem four or five years before it was discussed in "Remarks on the mind-body question"[1] by Wigner, of whom it received the name and fame thereafter. However, Everett being a student of Wigner's, it is clear that they must have discussed it together at some point.[4]

In contrast to his teacher Wigner, who held the consciousness of an observer to be responsible for a collapse, Everett understands the Wigner's friend scenario in a different way: Insisting that quantum states assignments should be objective and nonperspectival, Everett derives a straightforward logical contradiction when letting and reason about the laboratory's state of together with . Then, the Wigner's Friend scenario shows to Everett an incompatibility of the collapse postulate for describing measurements with the deterministic evolution of closed systems.[5] In the context of his new theory, Everett claims to solve the Wigner's Friend paradox by only allowing a continuous unitary time evolution of the wave function of the universe. Measurements are modelled as interactions between subsystems of the universe and manifest themselves as a branching of the universal state. The different branches account for the different possible measurement outcomes and are seen to exist as subjective experiences of the corresponding observers.

Objective collapse theories

According to objective collapse theories, wave function collapse occurs when a superposed system reaches a certain objective threshold of size or complexity. Objective collapse proponents would expect a system as macroscopic as a cat to have collapsed before the box was opened, so the question of observation-of-observers does not arise for them.[6] If the measured system were much simpler (such as a single spin state) then once the observation was made the system would be expected to collapse since the larger system of the scientist, equipment, and room would be considered far too complex to become entangled in the superposition.

QBism

In the interpretation known as QBism, advocated by N. David Mermin among others, the Wigner's-friend situation does not lead to a paradox, because there is never a uniquely correct wavefunction for any system. Instead, a wavefunction is a statement of personalist Bayesian probabilities, and moreover, the probabilities that wavefunctions encode are probabilities for experiences that are also personal to the agent who experiences them.[7] As von Baeyer puts it, "Wavefunctions are not tethered to electrons and carried along like haloes hovering over the heads of saints—they are assigned by an agent and depend on the total information available to the agent."[8] Consequently, there is nothing wrong in principle with Wigner and his friend assigning different wavefunctions to the same system. A similar position is taken by Brukner, who uses an elaboration of the Wigner's-friend scenario to argue for it.[6]

QBism and relational quantum mechanics have been argued to avoid the contradiction suggested by the extended Wigner's-friend scenario of Frauchiger and Renner.[9]

An extension of the Wigner's friend experiment

In 2016, Frauchiger and Renner used an elaboration of the Wigner's-friend scenario to argue that quantum theory cannot be used to model physical systems that are themselves agents who use quantum theory.[10] They provide an information-theoretic analysis of two specifically connected pairs of "Wigner's friend" experiments, where the human observers are modelled within quantum theory. By then letting the four different agents reason about each other’s measurement results (using the laws of quantum mechanics), contradictory statements are derived.

The resulting theorem highlights an incompatibility of a number of assumptions that are usually taken for granted when modelling measurements in quantum mechanics.

In the title of their published version of September 2018,[10] the author's interpretation of their result is apparent: Quantum theory as given by the textbook and used in the numerous laboratory experiments up to date "cannot consistently describe the use of itself" in any given (hypothetical) scenario. The implications of the result are currently subject to many debates among physicists of both theoretical and experimental quantum mechanics. In particular, the various proponents of the different interpretations of quantum mechanics have challenged the validity of the Frauchiger–Renner argument.[11]

Motivation and origin

Quantum mechanics has been very well confirmed in laboratory experiments on small scales. However, from the early years on, a number of objections (sometimes called paradoxes) to the underlying theoretical foundations of quantum mechanics have developed. Such objections are mostly related to the restrictive nature of quantum mechanics theory to the microscopic world.

A famous example of such a paradox is the so-called Schrödinger’s cat, named after the physicist Erwin Schrödinger who developed the following thought in his 1935 essay ("The current situation in quantum mechanics"): If the quantum mechanical concept of superposition of states were applied to a cat (as a macroscopic object), it would be possible for the cat to (for example) exist in a state where it is simultaneously alive and dead. Schrödinger concludes that such a scenario "prevents us from so naively accepting as valid a 'blurred model' for representing reality", and thereby expresses his doubts about quantum theory as a universally valid theory.

In 1967, Eugene Wigner describes a very similar scenario, the so called "Wigner's Friend", where he lets two observers come to different conclusions about the same physical system. Already in the Wigner's friend thought experiment, the information transfer of different agents' knowledge is a key point in the argument.

Those two problems highlight a supposed incompatibility of two laws in quantum theory: the unitary time evolution of closed, undisturbed systems and the non-unitary collapse mechanism that comes into play when a measurement is performed and decides the indeterminacy of the pre-measurement state to a definite outcome state.  

This in turn means that we would need a rule telling us when some physical process should be called a measurement in order to decide which axiom to use. The discussion around this topic has been called the measurement problem of quantum mechanics.

In the course of answering to the measurement problem, several attempts have developed that reinterpret the axioms of quantum theory. Such new theories are called interpretations of quantum mechanics and include theories such as Bohmian mechanics, Many Worlds theories, consistent histories, collapse theories, and so forth.

However, there remains diverse preferences for the different interpretations within the community, and the question of reinterpretation if not replacement of quantum theory by some higher framework remains.  

The thought experiment

The experiment was designed using a combination of arguments by Wigner[1] (Wigner's friend), Deutsch[12] and Hardy[13] (see Hardy's paradox).

The setup involves a number of macroscopic agents (observers) performing predefined quantum measurements in a given time order. Those agents are assumed to all be aware of the whole experiment and to be able to use quantum theory to make statements about other people’s measurement results. The design of the thought experiment is such that the different agents' observations along with their logical conclusions drawn from a quantum theoretical analysis yields inconsistent statements.

The scenario corresponds roughly to two parallel pairs of "Wigners" and friends: with and with . The friends each measure a specific spin system, and each Wigner measures "his" friend's laboratory (which includes the friend).

The explicit steps of the thought experiment are the following:[10]

  • Step at :

    measures a qubit state prepared in in the - basis and gets ("heads") or ("tails") with probability and , respectively. Depending on this outcome, prepares a spin system in state and sends it to . Here, if the outcome was and if the outcome was .

  • Step at :

    measures the received spin in the - basis.

  • Step at :

    measures in the - basis where and .

  • Step at :

    measures in the - basis where and .

  • Step at :

    The measurement outcomes of and are compared: If both got the experiment is halted. Otherwise, the protocol starts at the initial step again.

Each agent measures their assigned system in a particular basis, as defined above. Upon their measurement result, the agent now starts to reason about the results of other agents by using logical arguments compatible with quantum theory. It is assumed that all agents know about the experimental protocol and they all know quantum theory. This means that, upon having received a particular measurement outcome, each agent may predict some of the measurement results of the other agents. In the end, all the logical statements of the agents are combined and, after repeating the experiment times, a contradiction arises.

Note that the Wigners and look at the laboratories and from the outside, i.e., they are assumed to see the labs as perfectly isolated. Hence, they model it as a pure state superposition up to the time they themselves have measured their lab. However, even though lab stays isolated as a system, the extended Wigner’s friend experiment is constructed such that some information about the state of is accessible to outsiders. This is achieved by letting the state of depend on the outcome of 's measurement.

Information-theoretic analysis

The analysis of the thought experiment is set in an information-theoretic context: The individual agents make logical conclusions that are based on their measurement result, aiming at predictions about other agent's measurements within the protocol. Therefore, using quantum theoretic analysis, they model systems outside of themselves within the theory and draw conclusions.

The following four statements may be derived (see the mathematical analysis below) corresponding to the agents viewpoints:

  • Statement 1 by : "If I get , I know that will measure "
  • Statement 2 by : "If I get , I know that had measured "
  • Statement 3 by : "If I get , I know that had measured "
  • Statement 4 by : "If I get , I know that there exists one round of the experiment in which also gets "

Note that the first three statements are always true, the fourth one is true only with probability (see below for a derivation).

The contradiction arises when the four statements are combined for the case that the fourth statement is true, the corresponding round we define as to be round . Therefore, in round of the experiment, measures and knows that measures as well. The latter part then implies that knows that had measured , which implies that knows that got which in turn implies that knows that he himself will measure , and hence a contradiction appears.

No-go Theorem

The theorem phrases the inconsistency found in the Extended Wigner's friend experiment as an impossibility that some three given assumptions be simultaneously valid. Roughly speaking, those assumptions are

(Q): Quantum theory is correct.

(C): Agent's predictions are information-theoretically consistent.

(S): A measurement yields only one single outcome.

More precisely, assumption (Q) involves the probability predictions within quantum theory given by the Born rule. This means that an agent is allowed to trust this rule being correct in assigning probabilities to other outcomes conditioned on his own measurement result. It is however sufficient for the Extended Wigner's friend experiment to assume the validity of the Born rule for probability-1 cases, i.e., if the prediction can be made with certainty.

Assumption (S) specifies that once an agent has arrived at a probability-1 assignment of a certain outcome for a given measurement, they could never agree to a different outcome for the same measurement.

Assumption (C) invokes a consistency among different agents' statements in the following manner: The statement "I know (by the theory) that they know (by the same theory) that x" is equivalent to "I know that x".

Assumptions (Q) and (S) are used by the agents when reasoning about measurement outcomes of other agents, and assumption (C) comes in when an agent () combines other agent's statements with his own. The result is contradictory, and therefore, assumptions (Q), (C) and (S) cannot all be valid, hence the no-go theorem.

Derivation of the four statements

In the following it is explained how each of the agents arrives at his statement:

Statement 1 by : "If I get , I know that will measure "

, upon measuring , sends the spin system in the state to . When now measures in the - basis, knows (by using quantum theory (Q)) that both outcomes are possible for 's measurement. This again means that knows (again by (Q)) that the combined system of and will appear to an outside observer like as the superposition . As this is precisely the state of 's measurement basis, knows that will measure .

Statement 2 by  : "If I get , I know that had measured "

If measures , they know that could only have been sending the spin in state to him, as a state would never result in an outcome in a spin measurement of basis .

Statement 3 by : "If I get , I know that had measured "

As models the two labs and within quantum theory, he writes down the state at different times. He knows that the state at time of the protocol of system (i.e., after ' s measurement ) is where denotes agent 's state of "ready to measure". After the next step of the protocol ( 's measurement at time ), this state evolves to which in turn can be written in the - basis as From this, can conclude with certainty that must have measured if obtains the outcome .

Statement 4 by  : "If I get , I know that there exists one round of the experiment in which also gets "

also has knowledge of the state of both labs and together. He reformulates in his own measurement basis and obtains From this he may conclude that if and he himself perform their measurements, with probability , both and get outcome .

The four statements can be easily read off from the total state for the combined , when this state is rewritten with respect to different basis states, each choice of basis states adapted for the statement under consideration. The numbering of the rewritings below, corresponds to the numbering of the statements (1) till (4) :

From the construction as described in the steps at and , that is, after the measurements within the two labs and

(1) rewritten when concentrating on the tail / head dichotomy in Lab  :

(2) rewritten when concentrating on the Up / Down dichotomy in Lab  :

(3) rewritten when concentrating on w1 +/- dichotomy in Lab  :

(4) concentrating on combinations of plus and minus for both Labs :

(To check the correctness of these rewritings, replace in statements (1) till (3) all states by linear combinations of "+" and "-", like for instance replace by , and check after these substitutions, that all three will end up like rewriting number (4).)

Discussion

The meaning and implications of the Extended Wigner's friend thought experiment are still highly debated. A number of assumptions taken in the argument are very foundational in content, and therefore cannot be given up easily. However, the questions remains whether there are "hidden" assumptions that do not explicitly appear in the argument. The authors themselves seem to favour the rejection of their (implicit) assumption that macroscopic agents can be modelled as physical systems by quantum theory. Their rejection then renders their conclusion that "quantum theory cannot be extrapolated to complex systems, at least not in a straightforward manner".[10] On the other hand, one presentation of the experiment as a quantum circuit models the agents as single qubits and their reasoning as simple conditional operations.[14]

The impact of the Extended Wigner's friend thought experiment on current discussion about the foundations of quantum theory is highlighted by the fact that none of the different interpretations of quantum mechanics is able to provide a universally accepted explanation.

Looking at the rewritings used for the proofs of the four statements, it can be seen why the reasoning that combines the first three statements can lead to a conclusion ( gets "-" implies gets "+") that is in contradiction with the constructed overall state, in which the combined probability for ( gets "-" and gets "-"), is not zero, but equals (see rewriting (4)). The reason is that the statements have implicit assumptions that contradict each other. For instance, statement (1) about a later measurement, supposes that laboratory is in a superposition of "up" and "down" states, ie that the observer is in two states, namely thinking "the spin is up" and thinking "the spin is down". If wants to measure with respect to the basis, then has two possibilities: Either (i) she constructs her projection-test-operator such that a "plus" state for will become a superposition of "up" and "down", i.e. she does not leave a univocal to stay univocal, or (ii) she changes the state of to a single state not coupled any more to the "up" or "down" of the spin (the coupling was the result of a measurement as a unitary evolution, as described in the step at , and any measurement that is realized as a unitary transformation, can be undone in principle, if enough information is given to prevent entropy increase during the transformation). In both cases, the starting point of statement (2) is gone. So, the inference about a later measurement, such as made in statement (1) can only be done, when the starting point of statement (2), namely univocally thinks the spin is , will be made unfullfilled.

In fiction

Stephen Baxter's novel Timelike Infinity (1992) discusses a variation of Wigner's friend thought experiment through a refugee group of humans self-named "The Friends of Wigner". They believe that an ultimate observer at the end of time may collapse all possible entangled wave-functions generated since the beginning of the universe, hence choosing a reality without oppression.

See also

References

  1. ^ a b c d e f g h E. P. Wigner (1961), "Remarks on the mind-body question", in: I. J. Good, "The Scientist Speculates", London, Heinemann
  2. ^ R. Penrose, The Road to Reality, section 29.8.
  3. ^ Everett, Hugh III. (1957). "'Relative State' Formulation of Quantum Mechanics". Reviews of Modern Physics. 29 (3): 454–462. Bibcode:1957RvMP...29..454E. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.29.454.
  4. ^ a b Barrett, J. A., and Byrne, P. (eds.). (2012). The Everett interpretation of quantum mechanics: Collected works 1955–1980 with commentary. Princeton University Press.
  5. ^ Barrett, Jeffrey (2016-10-10). "Everett's Relative-State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  6. ^ a b Brukner, Časlav (2017). "On the quantum measurement problem". Quantum [Un]Speakables II: 50 Years of Bell’s Theorem. Springer. arXiv:1507.05255. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-38987-5. ISBN 978-3-319-38985-1. OCLC 1042356376.
  7. ^ Healey, Richard (2016-12-22). "Quantum-Bayesian and Pragmatist Views of Quantum Theory". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  8. ^ von Baeyer, Hans Christian (2016). QBism: The Future of Quantum Physics. Harvard University Press. ISBN 9780674504646. OCLC 946907398.
  9. ^ Pusey, Matthew F. (2018-09-18). "An inconsistent friend". Nature Physics. 14 (10): 977–978. doi:10.1038/s41567-018-0293-7. ISSN 1745-2473.
  10. ^ a b c d Frauchiger, Daniela; Renner, Renato (2018). "Quantum theory cannot consistently describe the use of itself". Nature Communications. 9 (1): 3711. arXiv:1604.07422. Bibcode:2016arXiv160407422F. doi:10.1038/s41467-018-05739-8. PMC 6143649. PMID 30228272.
  11. ^ Responses taking various positions include the following:
  12. ^ Deutsch, D. (1985). Quantum theory as a universal physical theory. International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 24(1), 1-41.
  13. ^ Hardy, L. (1992). Quantum mechanics, local realistic theories, and Lorentz-invariant realistic theories. Physical Review Letters, 68(20), 2981.
  14. ^ Musser, George (December 24, 2019). "Watching the Watchmen: Demystifying the Frauchiger-Renner Experiment". FQXi.org. Retrieved December 28, 2019.