Jump to content

Moral progress

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This is the current revision of this page, as edited by OAbot (talk | contribs) at 02:26, 4 January 2024 (Open access bot: hdl updated in citation with #oabot.). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this version.

(diff) ← Previous revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)

Moral progress refers to improvement in concepts such as moral beliefs and practices experienced on a societal scale.[1] Michele Moody-Adams noted that "moral progress in belief involves deepening our grasp of existing moral concepts, while moral progress in practices involves realizing deepened moral understandings in behavior or social institutions".[2]

Definitions

[edit]

Allen Buchanan defined moral progress as "morally progressive changes in social practices and institutions ... movement towards some morally desirable condition or state of affairs".[1] Michele Moody-Adams defined local moral progress as "coming to appreciate more fully the richness and the range of applications of a particular moral concept", or developing a new one, and the spread of "practices embodying deepened understanding of justice and related moral notions"; in other words, a deepening of our grasp of moral concepts.[2][3] Another view is that moral progress is "a greater success in describing moral reality".[3]

Moral progress on a societal scale should not be confused with moral development in individuals, occasionally also referred to as moral progress.[4]

Aspects

[edit]

Moral progress in societies leads to moral progress in individual beliefs throughout said society.[clarification needed][2] Understanding morality is also not required, once governments decide to implement moral progress notions, and do so through various incentives.[2] This can lead to the faster progress in moral progress in practices than in the moral progress in beliefs; in other words, with external pressures, individuals and organizations may behave better not because of their inherent beliefs, but because of considerations of social expediency and enlightened self-interest.[2] Buchanan differentiates between improvements from a moral point of view, which are caused by external factors, some possibly independent of human motivation and agency, and genuine moral progress. However, he notes that the former generally leads to the later anyway.[5]

Moral progress in the last few centuries has been often the result of the actions of morally progressive social movements who attempt to popularize new morals.[6]

Measurement of universal moral progress is difficult, because there is no universal consensus in regards to the final destination, nor objective standards of ethics.[2][1][3] Most complex moral concepts have more than a single established definition. This makes measuring moral progress even more difficult from measuring human progress in general.[2] Measurement of local, more specific moral progress are easier, as it is simpler to reach consensus on local, more specific ethical issues.[2] As Musschenga and Meyned noted, "Most contemporary Dutchmen will agree that the Netherlands since the 16th century made moral progress. It is doubtful whether Dutchmen from the 16th century would also agree."[4] Jeremy Evans, however, made an argument that is should be possible to create a definition of moral progress that "relies on a correlation between increasing population welfare ... and ethical advancement".[7]

Types of moral progress

[edit]

Buchanan provides a typology of moral progress:[8]

  • better compliance with valid moral norms,
  • better moral concepts,
  • better understanding of the virtues,
  • better moral motivation,
  • better moral reasoning,
  • proper demoralization,
  • proper moralization,
  • better understanding of moral standing and moral statuses,
  • improvements in the understanding of the nature of morality, and
  • better understanding of justice.

Moral circle expansion

[edit]

Moral circle expansion is the process of increasing the number and type of entities given moral consideration over time. Social scientist Jacy Reese Anthis, for example, has argued for moral circle expansion as an important metric of moral progress and as an approach to bettering the long-term future for all sentient beings.[9] His organization, the Sentience Institute, researches moral circle expansion via studying historical and current examples of moral progress, such as the British abolitionist movement.[10]

Examples

[edit]

Buchanan called the modern human rights movement "the most robust instance of [moral] progress"[11] Other examples of moral progress may include:

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b c Buchanan, Allen E. (2018). The Evolution of Moral Progress: A Biocultural Theory. Oxford University Press. p. 46. ISBN 978-0-19-086841-3.
  2. ^ a b c d e f g h i j Moody-Adams, Michele M. (1999). "The idea of moral progress". Metaphilosophy. 30 (3): 168–185. doi:10.1111/1467-9973.00120. JSTOR 24439208.
  3. ^ a b c Musschenga, Albert W.; Meynen, Gerben (2017-02-01). "Moral Progress: an Introduction". Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. 20 (1): 3–15. doi:10.1007/s10677-017-9782-5. hdl:1871.1/0e8fef4b-a775-4d00-a70f-e1c4b821ba0a. ISSN 1572-8447.
  4. ^ a b Minnameier, Gerhard (2009-08-01). "Measuring Moral Progress". Journal of Adult Development. 16 (3): 131–143. doi:10.1007/s10804-009-9058-y. ISSN 1573-3440. S2CID 142735170.
  5. ^ Buchanan, Allen E. (2018). The Evolution of Moral Progress: A Biocultural Theory. Oxford University Press. p. 51. ISBN 978-0-19-086841-3.
  6. ^ a b Moody-Adams, Michele M. (2017). "Moral Progress and Human Agency". Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. 20 (1): 153–168. doi:10.1007/s10677-016-9748-z. ISSN 1572-8447. S2CID 151692461.
  7. ^ Evans, Jeremy (2017-02-01). "A Working Definition of Moral Progress". Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. 20 (1): 75–92. doi:10.1007/s10677-016-9753-2. ISSN 1572-8447. S2CID 151726500.
  8. ^ Buchanan, Allen E. (2018). The Evolution of Moral Progress: A Biocultural Theory. Oxford University Press. p. 53. ISBN 978-0-19-086841-3.
  9. ^ Reese, Jacy (6 November 2018). The End of Animal Farming: How Scientists, Entrepreneurs, and Activists are Building an Animal-Free Food System. Boston: Beacon Press. ISBN 9780807039878.
  10. ^ "Introducing Sentience Institute". Sentience Institute. 2 June 2017. Retrieved 2019-08-05.
  11. ^ Buchanan, Allen E. (2018). The Evolution of Moral Progress: A Biocultural Theory. Oxford University Press. p. 379. ISBN 978-0-19-086841-3.
  12. ^ a b c d e f Buchanan, Allen E. (2018). The Evolution of Moral Progress: A Biocultural Theory. Oxford University Press. p. 47. ISBN 978-0-19-086841-3.
  13. ^ Jamieson, Dale (2017-02-01). "Slavery, Carbon, and Moral Progress". Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. 20 (1): 169–183. doi:10.1007/s10677-016-9746-1. ISSN 1572-8447. S2CID 44381011.
  14. ^ Hermann, Julia (2019). "The dynamics of moral progress". Ratio. 32 (4): 300–311. doi:10.1111/rati.12232. ISSN 1467-9329.