Jump to content

Proper equilibrium

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This is an old revision of this page, as edited by Erel Segal (talk | contribs) at 10:34, 6 October 2016 (removed Category:Game theory; added Category:Game theory equilibrium concepts using HotCat). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

Proper equilibrium
Solution concept in game theory
Relationship
Subset ofTrembling hand perfect equilibrium
Significance
Proposed byRoger B. Myerson

Proper equilibrium is a refinement of Nash Equilibrium due to Roger B. Myerson. Proper equilibrium further refines Reinhard Selten's notion of a trembling hand perfect equilibrium by assuming that more costly trembles are made with significantly smaller probability than less costly ones.

Definition

Given a normal form game and a parameter , a totally mixed strategy profile is defined to be -proper if, whenever a player has two pure strategies s and s' such that the expected payoff of playing s is smaller than the expected payoff of playing s' (that is ), then the probability assigned to s is at most times the probability assigned to s'.

A strategy profile of the game is then said to be a proper equilibrium if it is a limit point, as approaches 0, of a sequence of -proper strategy profiles.

Example

The game to the right is a variant of Matching Pennies.

Matching Pennies with a twist
Guess heads up Guess tails up Grab penny
Hide heads up -1, 1 0, 0 -1, 1
Hide tails up 0, 0 -1, 1 -1, 1

Player 1 (row player) hides a penny and if Player 2 (column player) guesses correctly whether it is heads up or tails up, he gets the penny. In this variant, Player 2 has a third option: Grabbing the penny without guessing. The Nash equilibria of the game are the strategy profiles where Player 2 grabs the penny with probability 1. Any mixed strategy of Player 1 is in (Nash) equilibrium with this pure strategy of Player 2. Any such pair is even trembling hand perfect. Intuitively, since Player 1 expects Player 2 to grab the penny, he is not concerned about leaving Player 2 uncertain about whether it is heads up or tails up. However, it can be seen that the unique proper equilibrium of this game is the one where Player 1 hides the penny heads up with probability 1/2 and tails up with probability 1/2 (and Player 2 grabs the penny). This unique proper equilibrium can be motivated intuitively as follows: Player 1 fully expects Player 2 to grab the penny. However, Player 1 still prepares for the unlikely event that Player 2 does not grab the penny and instead for some reason decides to make a guess. Player 1 prepares for this event by making sure that Player 2 has no information about whether the penny is heads up or tails up, exactly as in the original Matching Pennies game.

Proper equilibria of extensive games

One may apply the properness notion to extensive form games in two different ways, completely analogous to the two different ways trembling hand perfection is applied to extensive games. This leads to the notions of normal form proper equilibrium and extensive form proper equilibrium of an extensive form game. It was shown by van Damme that a normal form proper equilibrium of an extensive form game is behaviorally equivalent to a quasi-perfect equilibrium of that game.

References

Further reading

  • Roger B. Myerson. Refinements of the Nash equilibrium concept. International Journal of Game Theory, 15:133-154, 1978.
  • Eric van Damme. "A relationship between perfect equilibria in extensive form games and proper equilibria in normal form games." International Journal of Game Theory 13:1--13, 1984.