Jump to content

Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
m Need a 'the' in there
Expanding - background and synopsis to replace 'chapters', and a few other small changes
Line 5: Line 5:
| translator =
| translator =
| image = [[image:Darwin's Dangerous Idea.jpg|200px]]
| image = [[image:Darwin's Dangerous Idea.jpg|200px]]
| image_caption = <!-- Which edition cover is this? -->
| image_caption = Jacket painting by [[Henri Rousseau]] ([[:Image:Henri Rousseau 011.jpg|image]])<!-- Which edition cover is this? -->
| author = [[Daniel C. Dennett]]
| author = [[Daniel C. Dennett]]
| cover_artist =
| cover_artist =
Line 22: Line 22:
}}
}}


'''''Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life''''' ([[1995]]) is a [[List of controversial non-fiction books|controversial book]] by [[Daniel Dennett]] which argues that [[Darwinian process]]es are the central organising force in the [[Universe]]. Dennett asserts that [[natural selection]] is a blind and [[algorithm]]ic process which is sufficiently powerful to account for the generation and [[evolution]] of [[life]] including the ins and outs of [[human]] [[mind]]s and [[societies]]. These assertions have generated a great deal of debate and discussion within the [[scientific community]].
'''''Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life''''' ([[1995 in literature|1995]]) is a [[List of controversial non-fiction books|controversial book]] by [[Daniel Dennett]] which argues that [[Darwinian process]]es are the central organising force in the [[Universe]]. Dennett asserts that [[natural selection]] is a blind and [[algorithm]]ic process which is sufficiently powerful to account for the generation and [[evolution]] of [[life]] including the ins and outs of [[human]] [[mind]]s and [[societies]]. These assertions have generated a great deal of debate and discussion within the [[scientific community]].


==Chapters==
==Background==


Dennett's previous book was ''[[Consciousness Explained]]'' (1991). Dennett noted discomfort with [[Darwinism]] among not only lay people but even academics, and decided it was time to write a book dealing with the subject.<ref>''Darwin's Dangerous Idea'', preface.</ref> ''Darwin's Dangerous Idea'' is not meant to be a work of [[science]], but an [[interdisciplinary]] book; Dennett admits that he doesn't understand all of the scientific details himself. He goes into a moderate level of detail, but leaves it for the reader to go into greater depth if desired, providing plenty of references for this end.


In writing the book, Dennett wanted to "get thinkers in other disciplines to take evolutionary theory seriously, to show them how they have been underestimating it, and to show them why they have been listening to the wrong sirens." To do this he tells a story; one that is mainly original but which includes some material from his previous work.
*Part I: Starting in the Middle

**1. Tell Me Why
Dennett taught an undergraduate seminar at [[Tufts University]] on Darwin and philsophy, which included most of the ideas in the book. He also had the help of fellow staff and other academics, some of which read drafts of the book.<ref>These include [[Richard Dawkins]], [[David Haig (biologist)|David Haig]], [[Doug Hofstadter]], [[Nick Humphrey]], [[Ray Jackendoff]], [[Philip Kitcher]], [[Justin Leiber]], [[Ernst Mayr]], [[Steve Pinker]] and [[Kim Sterelny]].</ref> It is dedicated to [[Willard Van Orman Quine|Van Quine]], "teacher and friend".<ref>''Darwin's Dangerous Idea'', p. 5</ref>
**2. An Idea Is Born

**3. Universal Acid
==Synopsis==
**4. The Tree of Life
**5. The Possible and the Actual
===Part I: Starting in the Middle===
"Starting in the Middle", Part I of ''Darwin's Dangerous Idea'', gets its name from a quote by [[Willard Van Orman Quine]]: "Analyze theory-building how we will, we all must start in the middle. Our conceptual firsts are middle-sized, middle-distance objects, and our introduction to them and to everything comes midway in the cultural evoluiton of the race."
**6. Threads of Actuality in Design Space

*Part II: Darwinian Thinking in Biology
The first chapter "Tell Me Why" is named after a song.
**7. Priming Darwin's Pump

**8. Biology Is Engineering
{{bquote|
**9. Searching for Quality
Tell me why the stars do shine,<br>
**10. Bully for Brontosaurus
Tell me why the ivy twines, <br>
**11. Controversies Contained
Tell me why the sky's so blue.<br>
*Part III: Mind, Meaning, Mathematics, and Morality
Then I will tell you just why I love you.<br><br>
**12. The Cranes of Culture

**13. Losing Our Minds to Darwin
Because God made the stars to shine,<br>
**14. The Evolution of Meanings
Because God made the ivy twine,<br>
**15. The Emperor's New Mind, and Other Fables
Because God made the sky so blue.<br>
**16. On the Origin of Morality
Because God made you, that's why I love you.}}
**17. Redesigning Morality

**18. The Future of an Idea
Before [[Charles Darwin]], [[God]] was seen as the [[ultimate cause]] of all design, or the ultimate answer to '[[wikt:why|why]]<!-- this should have an article too... -->?' questions. [[John Locke]] argued for the primacy of [[mind]] before [[matter]],<ref>{{cite book |title=[[An Essay Concerning Human Understanding]] |last=Locke |first=John |authorlink=John Locke |year=1690 |publisher= |location=London |isbn= |pages= |url= }}</ref> and [[David Hume]], while exposing problems with Locke's view,<ref>{{cite book |title=[[Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion]] |last=Hume |first=David |authorlink=David Hume |year=1779 |publisher= |location=London |isbn= |pages= |url= }}</ref> could not see any alternative.

Darwin provided just such an alternative: [[evolution]].<ref>{{cite book |title=[[On the Origin of Species]] |last=Darwin |first=Charles |authorlink=Charles Darwin |year=1859 |publisher=John Murray |location=London |isbn= |pages= |url= }}</ref> Besides providing [[evidence of common descent]], he introduced a [[mechanism (philosophy)|mechanism]] to explain it: [[natural selection]]. According to Dennett, natural selection is a mindless, mechanical and [[algorithm|algorithmic]] process&mdash;Darwin's dangerous idea. The third chapter introduces the concept of "skyhooks" and "cranes" (see below). He suggests that resistance to Darwinism is based on a desire for skyhooks, which do not really exist. According to Dennett, good [[reductionism|reductionists]] explain apparent [[design]] without skyhooks; [[greedy reductionism|greedy reductionists]] try to explain it without cranes.

Chapter 4 looks at the [[Tree of life (science)|tree of life]], such as how it can be visualized and some crucial events in [[evolutionary history of life|life's history]]. The next chapter concerns the possible<!-- we should have an article on this, no? --> and the actual, using the 'Library of [[Gregor Mendel|Mendel]]' (the space of all [[logical possibility|logically possible]] [[genome]]s) as a conceptual aid.

In the last chapter of part I, Dennett treats human [[artifact]]s and [[culture]] as a branch of a unified Design Space. [[Commons descent|Descent]] or [[homology]] can be detected by shared design features that would be Vastly<!-- sic --> unlikely to appear independently. However, there are also "forced moves" or "good tricks" that will be discovered repeatedly, either by natural selection (see [[convergent evolution]]) or human investigation.

===Part II: Darwinian Thinking in Biology===
The first chapter of part II, "Darwinian Thinking in Biology", asserts that [[origin of life|life originated]] without any skyhooks, and the orderly world we know is the result of a blind and undirected shuffle through [[chaos]].

The eighth chapter's message is conveyed by its title, "Biology is Engineering"; [[biology]] is the study of design, [[function (biology)|function]], construction and operation. However, there are some important differences between biology and [[engineering]]. Related to the engineering concept of optimization, the next chapter deals with [[adaptationism]], which Dennett endorses, calling [[Stephen Jay Gould|Gould]] and [[Richard Lewontin|Lewontin]]'s "refution" of it<ref>{{cite journal |last=Gould |first=Stephen Jay |authorlink=Stephen Jay Gould |coauthors=[[Richard Lewontin]] |year=1979 |month= |title=The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme |journal=[[Proceedings of the Royal Society|Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B]] |volume=205 |issue= |pages=581-598 |id= |url=http://www.aaas.org/spp/dser/03_Areas/evolution/perspectives/Gould_Lewontin_1979.shtml |accessdate= |quote= }}</ref> an illusion. Dennett thinks adaptationism is, in fact, the best way of uncovering constraints<!-- pretty sure we should have an article on constraints too -->.

The tenth chapter, entitled "[[Bully for Brontosaurus]]", is an extended [[critique]] of [[Stephen Jay Gould]], who Dennett feels has created a distored view of evolution with his [[popular science|popular]] writings; his "self-styled revolutions" against adaptationism, [[gradualism]] and other orthodox Darwinism all being false alarms. The final chapter of part II dismisses [[directed mutation]], the [[inheritance of acquired traits]] and [[Pierre Teilhard de Chardin|Teilhard]]'s "[[Omega-point]]", and insists that other controversies and hypotheses (like the [[unit of selection]] and [[Panspermia]]) have no dire consequences for orthodox Darwinism.

===Part III: Mind, Meaning, Mathematics and Morality===
"Mind, Meaning, Mathematics and Morality" is the name of Part III, which begins with a quote from Nietzsche.<ref>{{cite book |title=[[Daybreak: Thoughts of the Prejudices of Morality]] |last=Nietzsche |first=Friedrich |authorlink=Friedrich Nietzsche |year=1881 |publisher= |location= |isbn= |pages= |url= }} Translated by R. J. Hollingdale. [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982].</ref> Chapter 12, "The Cranes of Culture", discusses [[cultural evolution]]. It asserts that the [[meme]] has a role to play in our understanding of culture, and that it allows [[human]]s, alone among [[animal]]s, to "transcend" our [[gene-centered view of evolution|selfish genes]].<ref>{{cite book |title=[[The Selfish Gene]] |last=Dawkins |first=Richard |authorlink=Richard Dawkins |year=1976 |publisher=Oxford University Press |location=Oxford |isbn= |pages= |url= }}</ref> "Losing Our Minds to Darwin" follows, a chapter about the evolution of brains, minds and [[language]]. Dennett criticizes [[Noam Chomsky]]'s perceived resistance to the [[evolution of language]], its modeling by [[artificial intelligence]], and [[reverse engineering]].

The evolution of meaning<!-- to what can I link? --> is then discussed, and Dennett uses a series of [[thought experiment]]s to persuade the reader that meaning is the product of meangingless, algorithmic process.

Chapter 15 asserts that [[Gödel's incompleteness theorems|Gödel's Theorum]] does not make certain sorts of [[artificial intelligence]] impossible. Dennett extends his criticism to [[Roger Penrose]].<ref>{{cite book |title=[[The Emperor's New Mind]] |last=Penrose |first=Roger |authorlink=Roger Penrose |year=1989 |publisher=Oxford University Press |location=Oxford |isbn= |pages= |url= }}</ref> The subject then moves on to the [[evolution of morality|origin and evolution of morality]], beginning with [[Thomas Hobbes]]<ref>{{cite book |title=[[Leviathan (book)|Leviathan]] |last=Hobbes |first=Thomas |authorlink=Thomas Hobbes |year=1651 |publisher=Crooke |location=London |isbn= |pages= |url= }}</ref> (who Dennett calls "the first [[sociobiology|sociobiologist]]") and [[Friedrich Nietzsche]].<ref>{{cite book |title=[[On the Genealogy of Morals]] |last=Nietzsche |first=Friedrich |authorlink=Friedrich Nietzsche |year=1887 |publisher= |location= |isbn= |pages= |url= }} Translated by [[Walter Kaufmann (philosopher)|Walter Kaufmann]] [New York: Vintage, 1967].</ref> He concludes that only an evolutionary analysis of [[ethics]] makes sense, though he cautions against some varieties of 'greedy ethical reductionism'. Before moving to the next chapter, he discusses some [[sociobiology]] controversies.

The penultimate chapter, entitled "Redesigning Morality", begins by asking if ethics can be 'naturalized'. Dennett does not believe there is much hope of discovering an algorithm for doing the right thing, but expresses optimism in our ability to design and redesign our approach to moral problems. In "The Future of an Idea", the book's last chapter, Dennett praises [[biodiversity]], including [[cultural diversity]], but does not extend this praise to [[religious fundamentalism]]. In closing, he uses ''[[Beauty and the Beast]]'' as an analogy; although Darwin's idea may seem dangerous, it is actually quite beautiful.


== Central concepts ==
== Central concepts ==
Line 89: Line 113:
==See also==
==See also==
*[[Jerry Fodor]]
*[[Jerry Fodor]]
*[[Richard Lewontin]]
*[[Roger Penrose]]
*[[John Searle]]
*[[John Searle]]



Revision as of 07:22, 7 September 2008

Darwin's Dangerous Idea
File:Darwin's Dangerous Idea.jpg
Jacket painting by Henri Rousseau (image)
AuthorDaniel C. Dennett
SubjectEvolution, ethics
PublisherSimon & Schuster
Publication date
1995
Pages586
ISBNISBN 0-670-03186-0 Parameter error in {{ISBNT}}: invalid character
Preceded byConsciousness Explained 
Followed byKinds of Minds: Toward an Understanding of Consciousness 

Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life (1995) is a controversial book by Daniel Dennett which argues that Darwinian processes are the central organising force in the Universe. Dennett asserts that natural selection is a blind and algorithmic process which is sufficiently powerful to account for the generation and evolution of life including the ins and outs of human minds and societies. These assertions have generated a great deal of debate and discussion within the scientific community.

Background

Dennett's previous book was Consciousness Explained (1991). Dennett noted discomfort with Darwinism among not only lay people but even academics, and decided it was time to write a book dealing with the subject.[1] Darwin's Dangerous Idea is not meant to be a work of science, but an interdisciplinary book; Dennett admits that he doesn't understand all of the scientific details himself. He goes into a moderate level of detail, but leaves it for the reader to go into greater depth if desired, providing plenty of references for this end.

In writing the book, Dennett wanted to "get thinkers in other disciplines to take evolutionary theory seriously, to show them how they have been underestimating it, and to show them why they have been listening to the wrong sirens." To do this he tells a story; one that is mainly original but which includes some material from his previous work.

Dennett taught an undergraduate seminar at Tufts University on Darwin and philsophy, which included most of the ideas in the book. He also had the help of fellow staff and other academics, some of which read drafts of the book.[2] It is dedicated to Van Quine, "teacher and friend".[3]

Synopsis

Part I: Starting in the Middle

"Starting in the Middle", Part I of Darwin's Dangerous Idea, gets its name from a quote by Willard Van Orman Quine: "Analyze theory-building how we will, we all must start in the middle. Our conceptual firsts are middle-sized, middle-distance objects, and our introduction to them and to everything comes midway in the cultural evoluiton of the race."

The first chapter "Tell Me Why" is named after a song.

Tell me why the stars do shine,
Tell me why the ivy twines,
Tell me why the sky's so blue.
Then I will tell you just why I love you.

Because God made the stars to shine,
Because God made the ivy twine,
Because God made the sky so blue.

Because God made you, that's why I love you.

Before Charles Darwin, God was seen as the ultimate cause of all design, or the ultimate answer to 'why?' questions. John Locke argued for the primacy of mind before matter,[4] and David Hume, while exposing problems with Locke's view,[5] could not see any alternative.

Darwin provided just such an alternative: evolution.[6] Besides providing evidence of common descent, he introduced a mechanism to explain it: natural selection. According to Dennett, natural selection is a mindless, mechanical and algorithmic process—Darwin's dangerous idea. The third chapter introduces the concept of "skyhooks" and "cranes" (see below). He suggests that resistance to Darwinism is based on a desire for skyhooks, which do not really exist. According to Dennett, good reductionists explain apparent design without skyhooks; greedy reductionists try to explain it without cranes.

Chapter 4 looks at the tree of life, such as how it can be visualized and some crucial events in life's history. The next chapter concerns the possible and the actual, using the 'Library of Mendel' (the space of all logically possible genomes) as a conceptual aid.

In the last chapter of part I, Dennett treats human artifacts and culture as a branch of a unified Design Space. Descent or homology can be detected by shared design features that would be Vastly unlikely to appear independently. However, there are also "forced moves" or "good tricks" that will be discovered repeatedly, either by natural selection (see convergent evolution) or human investigation.

Part II: Darwinian Thinking in Biology

The first chapter of part II, "Darwinian Thinking in Biology", asserts that life originated without any skyhooks, and the orderly world we know is the result of a blind and undirected shuffle through chaos.

The eighth chapter's message is conveyed by its title, "Biology is Engineering"; biology is the study of design, function, construction and operation. However, there are some important differences between biology and engineering. Related to the engineering concept of optimization, the next chapter deals with adaptationism, which Dennett endorses, calling Gould and Lewontin's "refution" of it[7] an illusion. Dennett thinks adaptationism is, in fact, the best way of uncovering constraints.

The tenth chapter, entitled "Bully for Brontosaurus", is an extended critique of Stephen Jay Gould, who Dennett feels has created a distored view of evolution with his popular writings; his "self-styled revolutions" against adaptationism, gradualism and other orthodox Darwinism all being false alarms. The final chapter of part II dismisses directed mutation, the inheritance of acquired traits and Teilhard's "Omega-point", and insists that other controversies and hypotheses (like the unit of selection and Panspermia) have no dire consequences for orthodox Darwinism.

Part III: Mind, Meaning, Mathematics and Morality

"Mind, Meaning, Mathematics and Morality" is the name of Part III, which begins with a quote from Nietzsche.[8] Chapter 12, "The Cranes of Culture", discusses cultural evolution. It asserts that the meme has a role to play in our understanding of culture, and that it allows humans, alone among animals, to "transcend" our selfish genes.[9] "Losing Our Minds to Darwin" follows, a chapter about the evolution of brains, minds and language. Dennett criticizes Noam Chomsky's perceived resistance to the evolution of language, its modeling by artificial intelligence, and reverse engineering.

The evolution of meaning is then discussed, and Dennett uses a series of thought experiments to persuade the reader that meaning is the product of meangingless, algorithmic process.

Chapter 15 asserts that Gödel's Theorum does not make certain sorts of artificial intelligence impossible. Dennett extends his criticism to Roger Penrose.[10] The subject then moves on to the origin and evolution of morality, beginning with Thomas Hobbes[11] (who Dennett calls "the first sociobiologist") and Friedrich Nietzsche.[12] He concludes that only an evolutionary analysis of ethics makes sense, though he cautions against some varieties of 'greedy ethical reductionism'. Before moving to the next chapter, he discusses some sociobiology controversies.

The penultimate chapter, entitled "Redesigning Morality", begins by asking if ethics can be 'naturalized'. Dennett does not believe there is much hope of discovering an algorithm for doing the right thing, but expresses optimism in our ability to design and redesign our approach to moral problems. In "The Future of an Idea", the book's last chapter, Dennett praises biodiversity, including cultural diversity, but does not extend this praise to religious fundamentalism. In closing, he uses Beauty and the Beast as an analogy; although Darwin's idea may seem dangerous, it is actually quite beautiful.

Central concepts

Natural selection as an algorithm

Dennett describes natural selection as a substrate-neutral, mindless algorithm for moving through "Design Space".

Universal acid

Dennett writes about the fantasy of a “universal acid” as a liquid that is so corrosive that it would eat through anything that it came into contact with, even a potential container. Such a powerful substance would transform everything it was applied to; leaving something very different in its wake. This is where Dennett draws parallels from the “universal acid” to Darwin’s idea:

“it eats through just about every traditional concept, and leaves in its wake a revolutionized world-view, with most of the old landmarks still recognizable, but transformed in fundamental ways.”

While there are people who would like to see Darwin’s idea contained within the field of biology, Dennett asserts that this dangerous idea inevitably “leaks” out to transform other fields as well.

Skyhooks and cranes

Dennett used the term "skyhook" to describe a source of design complexity that did not build on lower, simpler layers - in simple terms, a miracle.

In philosophical arguments concerning the reducibility (or otherwise) of the human mind, Dennett's concept pokes fun at the idea of intelligent design emanating from on high, either originating from God, or providing its own grounds in an absurd, Münchhausen-like bootstrapping manner.

Dennett also accuses various competing neo-Darwinian ideas of making use of such supposedly unscientific skyhooks in explaining evolution, coming down particularly hard on the ideas of Stephen Jay Gould.

Dennett contrasts theories of complexity which require such miracles with those based on "cranes", structures which permit the construction of entities of greater complexity but which are themselves founded solidly "on the ground" of physical science.

Reception

In the New York Review of Books, John Maynard Smith gave praise for Darwin's Dangerous Idea:

"It is therefore a pleasure to meet a philosopher who understands what Darwinism is about, and approves of it. Dennett goes well beyond biology. He sees Darwinism as a corrosive acid, capable of dissolving our earlier belief and forcing a reconsideration of much of sociology and philosophy. Although modestly written, this is not a modest book. Dennett argues that, if we understand Darwin's dangerous idea, we are forced to reject or modify much of our current intellectual baggage…" [13]

In the New York Review of Books, Stephen Jay Gould criticised Darwin's Dangerous Idea for being an "influential but misguided ultra-Darwinian manifesto".

"Daniel Dennett devotes the longest chapter in Darwin's Dangerous Idea to an excoriating caricature of my ideas, all in order to bolster his defense of Darwinian fundamentalism. If an argued case can be discerned at all amid the slurs and sneers, it would have to be described as an effort to claim that I have, thanks to some literary skill, tried to raise a few piddling, insignificant, and basically conventional ideas to "revolutionary" status, challenging what he takes to be the true Darwinian scripture. Since Dennett shows so little understanding of evolutionary theory beyond natural selection, his critique of my work amounts to little more than sniping at false targets of his own construction. He never deals with my ideas as such, but proceeds by hint, innuendo, false attribution, and error." [14]

Gould was also a harsh criticizer of Dennett's idea of the "universal acid" of natural selection and of his subscription to the idea of memetics.

Dennett's response and an exchange between Dennett, Gould, and Robert Wright can be found here.[15]

Biologist H. Allen Orr wrote a scathing review emphasizing similar points in the Boston Review,[16] to which Dennett later responded.[17]

See also

References

  1. ^ Darwin's Dangerous Idea, preface.
  2. ^ These include Richard Dawkins, David Haig, Doug Hofstadter, Nick Humphrey, Ray Jackendoff, Philip Kitcher, Justin Leiber, Ernst Mayr, Steve Pinker and Kim Sterelny.
  3. ^ Darwin's Dangerous Idea, p. 5
  4. ^ Locke, John (1690). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. London.
  5. ^ Hume, David (1779). Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. London.
  6. ^ Darwin, Charles (1859). On the Origin of Species. London: John Murray.
  7. ^ Gould, Stephen Jay (1979). "The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme". Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B. 205: 581–598. {{cite journal}}: Cite has empty unknown parameter: |month= (help); Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help)
  8. ^ Nietzsche, Friedrich (1881). Daybreak: Thoughts of the Prejudices of Morality. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale. [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982].
  9. ^ Dawkins, Richard (1976). The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  10. ^ Penrose, Roger (1989). The Emperor's New Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  11. ^ Hobbes, Thomas (1651). Leviathan. London: Crooke.
  12. ^ Nietzsche, Friedrich (1887). On the Genealogy of Morals. Translated by Walter Kaufmann [New York: Vintage, 1967].
  13. ^ New York Review of Books: John Maynard Smith "Genes, Memes, & Minds," 1995
  14. ^ Evolution: The Pleasures of Pluralism
  15. ^ Daniel Dennett "'Darwinian Fundamentalism': An Exchange," 1997
  16. ^ Boston Review:Orr Reviews "Darwin's Dangerous Idea" by Daniel Dennett
  17. ^ Reply to Orr

Template:Harvard reference.

External links