Problem of Hell
The problem of Hell is a variant of the problem of evil, applying specifically to religions which hold both that:
- An omnipotent (all-powerful), omniscient (all-knowing), and omnibenevolent (all-loving) God exists.
- Some people will be consigned to Hell forever, and will be eternally punished.
The debate
While Hell has traditionally been regarded as a punishment for wrong-doing or sin in life, the problem arises primarily from the severity of the punishment, if Hell is indeed seen as eternal torture. However, the view of hell as "punishment" is not universal. For example, the Eastern Orthodox see it as a condition brought about by, and the natural consequence of, free rejection of God's love as cited in What do Orthodox Christians teach about death and what happens when we die? The Roman Catholic Church teaches that hell is a place of punishment[1] brought about by a person's self exclusion from communion with God.[2]
The debate mostly focuses on whether God would want to allow a situation where some people are consigned to Hell forever. There is also the question of why an omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent God would allow the creation of souls foreknowing those souls would end up in Hell.
Judaism holds that Hell has a time limit of 12 months, and thus does not have this problem. Additionally Judaism holds that hell is not intended as a punishment, but rather as a cleansing of sorts, with more "dirt" requiring longer "washing". After the time in Hell is complete the soul moves to Heaven, or is reincarnated.[citation needed]
Hell as condition
For many ancient Christians, Hell was the same "place" as Heaven: living in the presence of God and directly experiencing God's love. Scripture clearly describes God's love as a raging "fire"; in the Psalms, David declares that God's glory shines even in Hell. Whether this was experienced as pleasure or torment depended on one's disposition towards God.
I also maintain that those who are punished in Gehenna, are scourged by the scourge of love. Nay, what is so bitter and vehement as the torment of love?...It would be improper for a man to think that sinners in Gehenna are deprived of the love of God...it torments sinners...Thus I say that this is the torment of Gehenna: bitter regret. —St. Isaac of Syria, Ascetical Homilies 28, Page 141
This ancient view is still the doctrine of the Eastern Orthodox Church. [1] [2]
Issues of justice
You must add a |reason=
parameter to this Cleanup template – replace it with {{Cleanup|section|reason=<Fill reason here>}}
, or remove the Cleanup template.
Opponents of the doctrine of Hell claim that the punishment is disproportionate to any crimes that could be committed, an overkill. Humans can commit only a finite amount of sin, yet Hell is an infinite punishment, and some believe that few (if any) people deserve such punishment. Others have noted that Heaven is also not deserved, for nothing we do in a finite mortal life could merit eternal bliss.
Against the alleged injustice of Hell, some theists have maintained that God is so infinitely great that any transgression against him warrants an infinite punishment. On this view, the correct punishment for a crime is proportional to the status of the wronged individual. Opponents of this view reply that the correct punishment is also proportional to the intentions and understanding of the wrongdoer.
Jorge Luis Borges suggests in his essay La duración del Infierno that no transgression can warrant an infinite punishment on the grounds that there is no such thing as an "infinite transgression".
Some are of the belief that all human beings sometimes do things which are wrong. Arguably, punishing humans for a situation which humans cannot avoid is unjust. Christianity agrees with the former view - For all have sinned, and come short of the glory of God; (Epistle to the Romans, 3:23) - but not the latter. For Christians argue that all people continue to choose to reject God and his rule.
Those assigned to Hell are destined to suffer there forever. For this to be justified, it must be inevitable that they will continue sinning eternally and continue to deserve further punishment. Hell becomes a futile punishment which cannot serve to prevent sin. Furthermore, if the sinners in Hell cannot avoid further sin they cannot easily be seen as responsible for their actions once they enter Hell.[citation needed]
However it can be argued that the previous point is a red herring, that Hell is not a disincentive to sin, but instead a punishment for it, and so arguing that the punishment is futile as a disincentive could be interpreted as a misunderstanding of the reason Hell exists.[citation needed]
It may also be argued that Hell is designed, in a sense, as a deterrent to non-believers; in short, if one does not believe in God, they will go to hell. But there is a flaw in this method: if one does not believe in God, then one probably does not believe in Hell either. It may be argued that the doctrine of hell acts as a deterrent to those who waver in their belief in God, i.e. the threat of eternal pain intimidates the person such that they would rather risk being wrong in their "belief" in God rather than suffer eternal torment for their disbelief. This still fails to explain the apparent injustice of total non believers being punished in hell. This injustice is furthered when one considers that God, who demands that everyone must believe in him, could have, as an omnipotent being, made it a lot more obvious that he exists than is apparent. If God truly wanted everyone to believe in him, it is alleged, then why does he still choose not to show himself?
Finally, it could be argued that humans are incapable of defining "justice" and that God alone can define "justice" and judge things as being just or unjust. If such a definition of justice is to be taken, Hell is justified solely by the fact that God defines it as just. This argument is mostly, but by no means entirely, associated with the Reformed branch of Christianity and with its founder Martin Luther. Skeptics however see this as a method of excusing any evil and indirectly denying the goodness of God.
Hell as a choice
Mirroring similar discussions in the problem of evil, another argument goes that human beings are presumed to have free will, and although a benevolent God would prefer to see everyone saved, he would also allow humans to control their own destinies. This view opens the possibility of seeing Hell not as retributive punishment, but rather as an option that God allows, so that people who do not wish to be with God are not forced to be. C. S. Lewis most famously proposed this view in his book The Great Divorce, saying: "There are only two kinds of people in the end: those who say to God, 'Thy will be done,' and those to whom God says, in the end, 'Thy will be done.'" Some believe that the choice for God must be made by an individual before he dies, but others do not see death as the end of one's chances to accept salvation. On the latter view, which seems suggested by Lewis, those in hell can get to heaven if they choose to accept God. On this view, in Lewis's memorable phrase, to the extent that the doors out of hell are locked for a person, they are "locked from the inside" — by the continuing, willful choice of the person.
Opponents of this view (such as Marilyn McCord Adams) claim that, even if Hell is seen as a choice rather than as punishment, it would be unreasonable for God to give such flawed and ignorant creatures as ourselves the awesome responsibility of our eternal destinies.
Jonathan Kvanvig, in his book, The Problem of Hell, agrees that God would not allow one to be eternally damned by a decision made under the wrong circumstances. One should not always honor the choices of human beings, even when they are full adults, if, for instance, the choice is made while depressed or careless. On Kvanvig's view, God will abandon no person until they have made a settled, final decision, under favorable circumstances, to reject God. But God will respect a choice made under the right circumstances. Once a person finally and competently chooses to reject God, out of respect for the person's autonomy, God allows them to be annihilated.
A question some have asked of those who defend Hell by appealing to human choice is whether humans truly "choose" Hell - if an atheist believed there was no God, would this count as a choice, or merely an honest mistake? At any rate, it is hard to see how someone who does not believe that hell exists can be truthfully described as having specifically chosen to go to Hell. Since Hell is everlasting and torturous, it seems implausible that any informed, rational person would deliberately choose to endure it. Rather than claiming that the damned choose Hell, those who defend hell by appeal to choice might do better to say merely that the damned make choices that result in their being in Hell, even though they never specifically chose to go to Hell.
Naturally, the idea of Hell as a just result of choice depends on a strong account of the degree to which one controls one's beliefs. If a person's actions and choices are the products of genes and environment, neither of which the person can control, Hell seems profoundly unfair. This problem is magnified for religions which claim to be the only path to salvation, since it is clear that which religion a person subscribes to is largely a result of the culture they are born in. Suppose, for example, that one has to be Christian to avoid Hell. Given that very few people born in Iran to Muslim parents become Christians, Hell would seem to punish such people unfairly. However, some Christians[specify] believe that God is above all religions, races and tribes and that the manmade religion is just a multitude of differing ways to reach eternal salvation. It has also been written[specify] that God greatly respects other faiths, such as the Muslim or Jewish religion, and that if that person concerned lived a good life they would go to Heaven. Judaism, on the contrary, does not discriminate between Jews and non-Jews. Those not of the Jewish faith are not condemned to "Hell" by virtue of their religious status. Gentiles have the potential to reach the same "heights" after death as Jews.
Separate from the suggestion that one chooses his or her eternal fate in life, many fathers of the church[specify] believed that upon death a soul will fully understand the good and evil of all its acts during life, and (if sinful) will in fact go to Hell voluntarily because it will deem itself unworthy for Heaven. Still, this fails to answer the question why a loving God creates souls which He foreknows will end up in Hell.
The argument from ignorance
As in the debate over the problem of evil, an option open to theists is to state that man is not perceptive enough to actually understand the "mind" of God, and cannot therefore conclude that the existence of Hell is unjust. The crux of this is that it is very possible that we do not understand the mind of God, and thus may not understand the reasons for the existence of Hell.
With regard to the question "why is there evil in the world?" there are at least candidate reasons why evil might serve some sort of useful purpose - for example, it might be character forming, or give humans something to struggle against. Furthermore, it would stand to reason that there cannot be good without evil to contrast it with. With Hell however, most such purposes fall away. Hell clearly does not serve any interests of its residents. The only possible conclusion is that God has reasons for Hell that humans cannot fathom.
However, denying human understanding of God's will has a logical windfall: all aspects of God's will become arguably incomprehensible to humans. (It is hard to argue that God's punishments are the only case where His will is beyond human understanding.) And if God's will is beyond human understanding, its products (including the definition of Hell) are beyond human understanding. The inability to even define "Hell" renders the "Problem of Hell" outside rational consideration. The problem is circular: humans interpret the religion to state that God's will is beyond human understanding, but the religion is a product of God's will, so -- one must conclude -- the religion is beyond human understanding. But if the religion is beyond human understanding, human understanding of the religion cannot be trusted to define the nature of God's will.
On the contrary, many believe that humans can reach a fairly good understanding of the nature of God. For example, through reading scripture, a Christian may come to believe that God is "just and right" (Deuteronomy 32:4) or while reading Ecclesiastes come to the conclusion that God cannot be understood by man. If someone holds the belief that he or she understands God and believes in the injustice of Hell, then his or her faith in God and/or personal understanding of God may be disturbed.
Opponents of Hell claim that if the reasons for Hell's existence cannot be understood, then it can hardly be just for people to suffer in it. If we cannot comprehend it, then it would serve no purpose as a deterrent. Another counter-argument is that the "Argument From Ignorance" is not an argument, but merely an attempt at concealing the fact that there is no hell; ie that hell's supporters simply avoid having to answer the question by claiming the answer cannot be understood.
Denial of God's goodness/omnipotence
It has been pointed out that an omnipotent deity could have given human beings a nature that always desired that which was in harmony with Gods own desires, i.e. people would naturally choose with their own free-will that which was pleasing to their nature which in turn would be pleasing to God. In contrast the doctrine of original sin teaches that God makes, or allows to be made, people with natures desiring that which is displeasing to him. He then leaves those estranged by sin to sufferer the consequences of their fall.[3]
References
- ^ Catechism of the Catholic Church, 1035, Libreria Editrice Vaticana, ISBN 0-89243-565-8,1994 - the revised version issued 1997 has no changes in this section
- ^ Catechism of the Catholic Church, 1033, Libreria Editrice Vaticana, ISBN 0-89243-565-8,1994
- ^ Bible Teaching and Religious Practice essay: "Europe and Elsewhere", Mark Twain, 1923
See also
Bibliography
- Marilyn McCord Adams: "The Problem of Hell: A Problem of Evil for Christians," in William Rowe (ed.): God and the Problem of Evil, ISBN 0-631-22220-0
- Jonathan L. Kvanvig: The Problem of Hell, ISBN 0-19-508487-X
- Charles Seymour: A Theodicy of Hell, ISBN 0-7923-6364-7
- Jerry Walls: Hell: The Logic of Damnation, ISBN 0-268-01095-1
- C.S. Lewis: The Problem of Pain, ISBN 0-06-065296-9
- Ted Sider. Hell and Vagueness, Faith and Philosophy 19 (2002): 58-68.