Jump to content

The Philosophy of Freedom

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This is an old revision of this page, as edited by Qexigator (talk | contribs) at 06:58, 25 March 2014 (isbn Oberski). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

The Philosophy of Freedom is the fundamental philosophical work of the philosopher and esotericist Rudolf Steiner (1861–1925). It addresses the questions whether and in what sense man can be said to be free. Originally published in 1894 in German as Die Philosophie der Freiheit, the work has appeared under a number of English titles, including The Philosophy of Freedom (1916), The Philosophy of Spiritual Activity (1921), and more recently Intuitive Thinking as a Spiritual Path (1995).

Part One of The Philosophy of Freedom examines the basis for freedom in human thinking, and includes accounts of knowledge and perception; Part Two examines the conditions for freedom in relation to action. The book's subtitle, "Some results of introspective observation following the methods of Natural Science",[1] describes the philosophical method Steiner intends to follow.

In the first part of the book Steiner discusses freedom in thinking, and the question of thinking's reliability as a means to knowledge, that is. the epistemology of freedom. In the second part, which depends on the first, he examines the conditions necessary for freedom of action.[2]

Historical context

Steiner had wanted to write a philosophy of freedom since at least 1880.[3] The appearance of the book was preceded by his publications on Goethe, focusing on epistemology and the philosophy of science, particularly Goethe the Scientist (1883)[4] and The Theory of Knowledge Implicit in Goethe's World Conception (1886).[5] In 1891, Steiner presented his doctoral dissertation, an epistemological study that includes discussion of Kant's and Fichte's theories of knowledge. A revised version of the thesis was published a year later in book form as Truth and Knowledge: Introduction to a Philosophy of Freedom.[6] The Philosophy of Freedom appeared in 1894.[7]

Steiner was influenced by Franz Brentano, an important precursor of the phenomenological movement in philosophy, whose lectures he attended as a student in Vienna (see School of Brentano). Like the later phenomenologists, Steiner was seeking a way to solve the subject-object problem. Steiner's approach to freedom was also in part a response to those contained in Schiller's On the Aesthetic Education of Man and the works of Goethe, both of whom Steiner believed had not focused sufficiently on the role of thinking in developing inner freedom.[8]

Steiner's division of his subject into the knowledge of freedom and the reality of freedom in some respects parallels Fichte's distinction between formal freedom, the capacity and disposition to form intentions based on larger goals, including a person's awareness of this capacity, and material freedom, the realization of this capacity by formulating new actions.[9] Steiner is also critical of Fichte's philosophy, however, criticizing what he called a "fundamental mistake" in Fichte's "Science of Knowledge.[10]

Steiner was also deeply affected as a young man by Kant's argument in the Critique of Pure Reason that we cannot know things as they are in themselves, and he devotes a long chapter of The Philosophy of Freedom to a refutation of this view, arguing that there are in principle no limits to knowledge. This claim is important to freedom, because for Steiner freedom involves knowing the real basis of our actions. If this basis cannot be known, then freedom is not possible. Steiner's argument in favour of freedom also responds to determinists such as Spinoza, for whom human action is just as much determined as anything else in the necessity that governs nature as a whole. Steiner argues against both hard determinism[11] and compatibilism.[12]

Other philosophers mentioned or discussed in The Philosophy of Freedom include Hegel, Schelling, von Hartmann, Robert Hamerling, Schopenhauer, Herbert Spencer, George Berkeley, Pierre Jean George Cabanis, Descartes, David Hume, Otto Liebmann, Ernst Haeckel, Kreyenbuehl,[13] Friedrich Paulsen, Paul Rée, Johannes Rehmke, and David Strauss.[14]

Arrangement and outline of the book

Twofold structure

The twofold structure of The Philosophy of Freedom partly parallels Hegel's description of freedom: "Ethical life is the Idea of freedom as the living good which has its knowledge and volition in self-consciousness, and its actuality through self-conscious action." [15] However, Steiner differs from Hegel in an essential way: Steiner finds the activity of thinking to be something much greater and more real than the concepts which crystallize out of thinking.[16]

Steiner seeks to demonstrate that inner freedom is achieved when we bridge the gap between our perception, which reflects the outer appearance of the world, and our cognition, which gives us access to the inner structure of the world. He suggests that outer freedom arises when we bridge the gap between our ideals and the constraints of external reality, letting our deeds be inspired by the moral imagination.[2]

Understanding freedom

Steiner begins exploring the nature of human freedom by considering what happens when a person becomes conscious of his or her motives for acting. He takes it "that an action, of which the agent does not know why he performs it, cannot be free," and asks, 'But what about an action for which the reasons are known?'[17] The philosophical method Steiner intends to follow in addressing this question is introspective observation.

A chapter follows in which Steiner discusses the distinction between mind, or subject, and world, or object, and the way in which the material for distinctions of this sort arises within "the depths of our own being"[18] or consciousness. After criticizing solutions to this problem provided by dualism in the philosophy of mind and several forms of monism as one-sided, Steiner writes that he wishes to pursue an "introspective observation following the methods of natural science" of consciousness and its contents, without aiming at the "sharp distinctions" usually made by science.

In Ch. 3, "Thinking in the service of Knowledge," Steiner observes that when confronted with percepts, we feel obliged to think about and add concepts to these: to observation we add "thinking".[19] Steiner seeks to demonstrate that what he considers the primary antithesis between observation and thinking underlies all other antitheses and philosophic distinctions, such as subject vs. object, appearance vs. reality, and so on.

Steiner then considers whether we can observe our own thinking processes, which he suggests differs from all other objects of observation in the following way. Normally, we can either observe an object of consciousness or observe our thoughts about this object. We cannot observe both the percept and our thinking about this percept simultaneously. Thinking is unique in that we can simultaneously observe it and our thoughts about it, for here the percept (thinking) and our thinking about the percept consist of the same element (thought): Thinking about thinking takes place in thinking; observing the latter, we are simultaneously observing the former.

Normally, however, we do not pay attention to the process of thinking, only its results, the thoughts themselves:

The first observation which we make about thinking is therefore this: that it is the unobserved element in our ordinary mental and spiritual life.[20]

Steiner connects this "first observation" to the fact that thinking is entirely due to our own activity. It does not appear before us unless we ourselves produce it. Nevertheless, when I apprehend the content of thinking, which is the concept, the concept is its own reason, in the sense that it can be asked why I feel this or that way about something, a triangle, for example, but not why it produces in me this or that concept. 'Why do I connect a triangle with the concept of a triangle?" is a question that is "simply meaningless", unlike the question, 'Why do I dislike triangles?'[21](The answer to this last question might be, 'Because my geometry teacher was an angry man.') Accordingly I can know from their contents why the relations of concepts to one another are as they are.

A further observation can be made. When I observe my thinking, it always a past instance of thinking that I observe, not a present one. I cannot divide myself into the thinker and the observer of the thinker. They are one and the same. The reason for this is just that thinking is my own activity. This latter fact also explains why I can know thinking "more intimately and immediately than any other process in the world"[22] This is what Steiner calls "the transparent clearness concerning our thinking process".[23] To appreciate this point, we must be able to adopt to our own thinking the "exceptional" procedure mentioned above: we must apply it to itself. If we are unable to do this, and we think of thinking as a brain-process, it is because we do not see thinking, because we are unable to take up the exceptional position needed to do so.

Steiner takes Descartes' dictum, "I think, therefore I am," to signify the truth that "I am certain . . . that [thinking] exists in the sense that I myself bring it forth,"[24] However, Steiner advances the objection (common to many others, beginning in Descartes' own time,[25]) that the further claim that I am is more problematic.[26]

In Chapter 4, "Thinking in the Service of Knowledge", Steiner writes,

...thinking must never be regarded as merely a subjective activity. Thinking lies beyond subject and object. It produces these two concepts just as it produces all others. When, therefore, I, as thinking subject, refer a concept to an object, we must not regard this reference as something purely subjective. It is not the subject that makes the reference, but thinking. The subject does not think because it is a subject; rather it appears to itself as a subject because it can think. The activity exercised by man as a thinking being is thus not merely subjective. Rather is it something neither subjective nor objective, that transcends both these concepts. I ought never to say that my individual subject thinks, but much more that my individual subject lives by the grace of thinking.

An important part of the book analyzes and rejects the view that subject and object (mind and world) are divided from each other in reality, and that a person cannot experience the world itself but only subjective images somewhere inside the brain (or in the soul inside the brain). Steiner points out the inconsistency of treating all our perceptions as mere subjective mental images inside the brain. If that were true, the brain itself, our knowledge of which is after all derived from perception, would have to be a mere subjective mental image inside . . . the brain. The absurdity of that becomes clearer in Steiner's more detailed discussions, during the course of which a profoundly different understanding of perception is proposed.

With regard to freedom of the will, Steiner observes that a key question is how the will to action arises in the first place. Steiner describes to begin with two sources for human action: on the one hand, the driving forces springing from our natural being, from our instincts, feelings, and thoughts insofar as these are determined by our character - and on the other hand, various kinds of external motives we may adopt, including the dictates of abstract ethical or moral codes. In this way, both nature and culture bring forces to bear on our will and soul life. Overcoming these two elements, neither of which is individualized, we can achieve genuinely individualized intuitions that speak to the particular situation at hand. By overcoming a slavish or automatic response to the dictates of both our 'lower' drives and conventional morality, and by orchestrating a meeting place of objective and subjective elements of experience, we find the freedom to choose how to think and act.[27]: Chap. 9 

Freedom for Steiner does not consist in acting out everything subjective within us, but in acting out of love, thoughtfully and creatively. In this way we can love our own actions, which are unique and individual to us, rather than stemming from obedience to external moral codes or compulsive physical drives. Both of the latter constitute limitations on freedom:

Whether his unfreedom is forced on him by physical means or by moral laws, whether man is unfree because he follows his unlimited sexual desire or because he is bound by the fetters of conventional morality, is quite immaterial from a certain point of view...let us not assert that such a man can rightly call his actions his own, seeing that he is driven to them by a force other than himself.[28]

Freedom arises most clearly at the moment when a human being becomes active in pure, individualized thinking; this is, for Steiner, spiritual activity.[2] Achieving freedom is then accomplished by learning to let an ever larger portion of one's actions be determined by such individualized thought, rather than by habit, addiction, reflex, or involuntary or unconscious motives. Steiner differentiates pure thinking into "moral intuition" (formulation of individual purposes), "moral imagination" (creative strategies for realizing these larger purposes in the concrete situation), and "moral technique" (the practical capacity to accomplish what was intended). He suggests that we only achieve free deeds when we find an ethically impelled but particularized response to the immediacy of a given situation. Such a response will always be radically individual; it cannot be predicted or prescribed.[2]

Steiner's philosophy neither evaluates the moral value of an action only according to its consequences (utilitarianism), nor does it allow any categorical imperative, whether Kantian or otherwise, to be the moral arbiter of human actions. For Steiner, the highest morality exists when a person's inner life actively connects with the external world through deeds of love realized by means of individually developed and contextually-sensitive moral imaginations,[2] a view that perhaps has affinities with the "dilige et quod vis fac" ("Love, and do what you will") of St. Augustine.[29]

Steiner began by saying, in Ch. I, that we must look for freedom in conscious action, but not that we will necessarily find it. He explores the various compulsions of motives at different levels, and points out that freedom does not exist if we are still within the grip of the various forces acting within us. At the beginning of Ch. 2 he quoted Goethe:

Two souls dwell, alas, in my breast
Each would from the other split;
One clutches, in its dullish lust
Tight to the world with its organs' grip;
The other raises itself forcibly from dust:
High ancestral fields are its quest.
Faust I, lines 1112-7

The polarity in consciousness is between perception through the senses, which gives us access to the outer nature of things, and perception through thinking, which gives us access to the inner nature of things. Steiner treats thinking as an organ of perception as valid as the senses themselves, albeit at a higher level; both are subject to illusion and distortion, but both can reveal true and ever new aspects of the world to us. Steiner tells us however that what he means by “pure thinking” is not the dry, gray, or abstract experience people often mean by “thinking”. In what might seem a paradox, he says pure thinking is one with feeling and will in the depths of their reality; it is the power of love in its spiritual form. If we were to see deeply enough into pure thinking, we'd realize that gray abstractions are just the left over remains, the corpses of what once was alive but has since fallen away from pure thinking. Pure thinking, in its depths, is a living, warm, luminous, entry into the creative depths of the world. Elsewhere in the book, Steiner says that thinking, in its purest form, is "the conscious experience, in pure spirit, of a purely spiritual content." Steiner there intends the word "spiritual" to mean "non-material," "non-physical," "immaterial."

In The Philosophy of Freedom Steiner explains that thinking is unique in our access in it to the true inner reality of the world at least in one corner. We can become conscious of our thought processes in a way that we cannot be of our feelings, will or sense perceptions. Once we learn, by dint of great efforts, to peel out all externals and sense-perceptible elements from our thought experiences, and arrive at what Steiner calls pure thinking, we can know that what we are experiencing as pure thinking is exactly what it seems. Appearance and reality become one. We observe a corner of reality where we see into the innermost core of the world. By contrast, our feelings appear as percepts whose meaning is not so directly apparent. We only perceive the meaning of the percept after some form of thinking has been brought to bear, even if only so briefly and quickly that the thinker barely notices. We understand our perceptions (for example, we give the right spatial meaning to the visually converging lines of railroad tracks) through our conceptual framework. Thinking is thus necessary if we are to properly interpret our perception.

Only when we bring thinking to bear upon perceptions (including the perceptions to be had from experiments) can we obtain scientific clarity about them. On the other hand, mathematics is a kind of thinking in which thought itself forms the perceptions; no sense-perceptions are needed to form a basis for mathematical principles. Mathematics could be said to be a science of the inner side of things, or rather of that portion of the inner side of things that resembles numerical relations. To do mathematics we need not know anything about outer appearances.

Though our experience at first leads us to the illusion of dualism, in reality we are experiencing two sides of a single phenomenon when we perceive it and think about it: two sides of a single, unified world. Steiner tells us that we only experience the full reality of something when we have united its percept with thinking—the percept by itself is incomplete, only a half reality.

Steiner explains that our consciousness is "dualistic" in that the unity of the world (and of every object or element of the world), is at first only available to us split in two, because of our two basic modes of perception. Thus the world comes to us as "inner" and "outer," or "thought" and "percept," or "concept" and "given". It is the work of the human mind or spirit to uncover the fundamental unity of these two aspects, to recognize that they are two poles of a single reality, not two absolutely separate things. Though they are different, yet at the same time each contains in its innermost core something of the other. In his book The Theory of Knowledge Implicit in Goethe's World-Conception (1886), one chapter is titled "Thinking as a Higher Experience within Experience."[30] That chapter title exemplifies the way in which Steiner finds thinking and perception to be simultaneously one and yet distinct, an inwardly differentiated unity, not two elements.

Steiner says that we have the capacity to overcome the dualism of experience by discovering the inner unity, at first hidden, of perception with thinking.[31] For example, when observing a thinking process with sufficient energy, perceiving and thinking can begin to become one for us.

Steiner tells us that we think in perceiving, and perceive in thinking. Consider the first part of that sentence: thinking is more pervasive in our ordinary perceiving than we often recognize. If for example we had not as infants learned, unconsciously, to think with our eyes and limbs, then our eyes, even if functioning perfectly in a physical sense, would see only something like what the philosopher William James referred to as a "blooming buzzing confusion,” or what Steiner referred to in his Ph.D thesis as a highly chaotic stage of the “given.” We would not perceive spatial or temporal structure or recognize distinct qualities. If that conclusion seems surprising, that's because the thinking-in-perceiving that we learned to do as children has usually become habitual and automatic long before we reached adulthood and full consciousness; so we rarely become conscious of the key role thinking plays in even the simplest perceptions.

There are limits beyond which our understanding does not presently go, but both our perception and our thinking can be extended beyond their present abilities. The telescope and microscope offer us radical extensions of the range of our perceptions; we can look to extend our powers of thought until they become organs of perception for higher worlds. Steiner thus challenges the philosophy of his (and our) time: it is not enough simply to define the limits of possible knowledge; it is necessary to work to extend these as well.[31]

Exercising freedom

Toward the end of the second part of the book, Steiner writes that "The unique character of the idea, by means of which I distinguish myself as 'I', makes me an individual." And then, "An act the grounds for which lie in the ideal part of my nature is free." Steiner there is using the term ideal to refer to pure ideation or pure thinking in Steiner's sense. "The action is therefore neither stereotyped, carried out according to set rules, nor is it performed automatically in response to an external impetus; the action is determined solely through its ideal content."[32] What is individual in us is to be distinguished from what is generic by its ideal character. If an act proceeds out of genuine thinking, or practical reason, then it is free.

Steiner begins the second part of the book by emphasizing the role of self-awareness in objective thinking. Here he modifies the usual description of inner and outer experience by pointing out that our feelings, for example, are given to us as naively as outer perceptions. Both of these, feelings and perceptions, tell about objects we are interested in: the one about ourselves, the other about the world. Both require the help of thinking to penetrate the reasons why they arise, to comprehend their inner message. The same is true of our will. Whereas our feelings tell how the world affects us, our will tells how we would affect the world. Neither attains to true objectivity, for both mix the world's existence and our inner life in an unclear way. Steiner emphasizes that we experience our feelings and will - and our perceptions as well - as being more essentially part of us than our thinking; the former are more basic, more natural. He celebrates this gift of natural, direct experience, but points out that this experience is still dualistic in the sense that it only encompasses one side of the world.

This all is by way of introduction and recapitulation. Steiner then introduces the principle that we can act out of the compulsions of our natural being (reflexes, drives, desires) or out of the compulsion of ethical principles, and that neither of these leaves us free. Between them, however, is an individual insight, a partly situational ethic, that arises neither from abstract principles nor from our bodily impulses.[33] A deed that arises in this way can be said to be truly free; it is also both unpredictable and wholly individual. Here Steiner articulates his fundamental maxim of social life:

Live through deeds of love, and let others live with understanding for each person's unique intentions.

Here he describes a polarity of influences on human nature, stating that morality transcends both the determining factors of bodily influences and those of convention:

A moral misunderstanding, a clash, is out of the question between people who are morally free. Only one who is morally unfree, who obeys bodily instincts or conventional demands of duty, turns away from a fellow human being if the latter does not obey the same instincts and demands as himself.

For Steiner, true morality, the highest good, is the universal mediated by the profoundly individual and situational; it depends upon our achieving freedom from both our inner drives and outer pressures. To achieve such free deeds, we must cultivate our moral imagination, our ability to imaginatively create ethically sound and practical solutions to new situations, in fact, to forge our own ethical principles and to transform these flexibly as needed - not in the service of our own egotistical purposes, but in the face of new demands and unique situations. This is only possible through moral intuitions, immediate experiences of spiritual realities that underlie moral judgments.[2][31] Moral imagination and intuition allow us to realize our subjective impulses in objective reality, thus creating bridges between the spiritual influence of our subjectivity and the natural influence of the objective world in deeds whereby "that which is natural is spiritual, that which is spiritual is natural".[34]

Steiner concludes by pointing out that to achieve this level of freedom, we must lift ourselves out of our group-existence: out of the prejudices we receive from our family, nation, ethnic group and religion, and all that we inherit from the past that limits our creative and imaginative capacity to meet the world directly. Only when we realize our potential to be a unique individual are we free. Thus, it lies in our freedom to achieve freedom; only when we actively strive towards freedom do we have some chance of attaining it.

Relation to earlier and later work

In works written after 1900, Steiner began to explain how thinking can evolve to become an organ of perception of higher worlds of living, creative, spiritual beings. Before 1900, he was still laying the epistemological basis upon which higher modes of perception could be grounded as clearly as possible in science and philosophy. Steiner frequently referred to The Philosophy of Freedom in lectures and in written works, at least once in every year from 1905 to his death in 1925.[35] In his work The Riddles of Philosophy Presented in an Outline of Its History (1914) Steiner mentioned that The Philosophy of Freedom was intended to give the philosophical foundations for what had been outlined in his earlier work Truth and Science (1892).[36]

Near the end of his life, when Steiner was asked which of his writings, in his opinion, would last the longest, he replied, that The Philosophy of Freedom would outlive all his other works.[37] He let it be known that he considered that this work contained, in a philosophical form, the entire content of what he had (after the first publication in 1894) developed explicitly as anthroposophy,[38] while also regarding an earlier work of his, The Theory of Knowledge Implicit in Goethe's World-Conception, to be the foundation and justification, epistemologically, for all he had said and written after that work was published in 1886.[39]

Steiner's principal works on philosophy, and what he said or wrote about the relationship between them and his other works, in summary:

  • 1886 The Theory of Knowledge Implicit in Goethe's World-Conception. The foundation and justification, epistemologically, for all Steiner said and wrote after this book's publication.
  • 1892 Truth and Science.
  • 1894 The Philosophy of Freedom. This presented the philosophical foundations for what had been outlined in Truth and Science, and it contained, in a philosophical form, the entire content of what Steiner had (after the first publication in 1894) developed explicitly as anthroposophy.
  • 1914 A Brief Outline of an Approach to Anthroposophy, chapter 8 in the book The Riddles of Philosophy Presented in an Outline of Its History.

Quotations

To live in love towards our actions, and to let live in the understanding of the other person's will, is the fundamental maxim of free men.[27] : Chapter 9 
Only to the extent that a man has emancipated himselff...from all that is generic, does he count as a free spirit within a human community. No man is all genus, none is all individuality. [27]: Chapter 14 

Translations and editions

The first edition of Die Philosophie der Freiheit was published in 1894. A second revised edition appeared in 1918. Further German editions reprinted the 1918 text until 1973, when a revised edition was produced based on Steiner's corrections of the galley proofs of the 1918 edition. Minor changes, including corrections to some of Steiner's citations, were made in the 1987 German edition.[40]

English translations

English translations include:

There is a comparison tool to compare most of the above translations.

Secondary works

  • Rudolf Steiner on His Book the Philosophy of Freedom, Compiled by Otto Palmer (1964), SteinerBooks [1975], Reprinted.
  • Sergei O. Prokofieff, The Guardian of the Threshold and the Philosophy of Freedom: On the Relationship of The Philosophy of Freedom to the Fifth Gospel, Temple Lodge Publishing, Forest Row 2011
  • Sergei O. Prokofieff, Anthroposophy and The Philosophy of Freedom. Anthroposophy and its Method of Cognition. The Christological and Cosmic-Human Dimension of The Philosophy of Freedom, Temple Lodge Publishing, London 2009, from the German edition, 2006. [ISBN 978-1-906999-02-5]
  • Iddo Oberski, Key to Life: An Introductory Sketch to Rudolf Steiner's Philosophy of Freedom, Eloquent Books 2010. [ISBN10 1609118650]
  • G.A.Bondarev, Rudolf Steiner's "Philosophie der Freiheit" as the Foundation of the Logic of Beholding. Religion of the Thinking Will. Organon of the New Cultural Epoch. An introduction to Anthroposophical Methodology, translated from the German from the German edition, 2004. [ISBN 978-1-105-05765-6]

See also

References

  1. ^ An alternate translation reads, "Results of Introspective Observations According to the Method of Natural Science" (Rudolf Steiner, The Philosophy of Spiritual Activity, trans. Rita Stebbing, (N.Y.: Rudolf Steiner Publications, 1963), p. 3). The German original is, "Beobachtungs-Resultate nach naturwissenshcaftlicher Methode" (Steiner, 1894, title page.)
  2. ^ a b c d e f Robert McDermott, The Essential Steiner: Basic Writings of Rudolf Steiner, Harper & Row, 1984, ISBN 0-06-065345-0, pp. 41–44
  3. ^ Christoph Lindenberg, Rudolf Steiner: Eine Biographie, (Stuttgart: Verlag Freies Geistesleben 1997), pp. 212–3.
  4. ^ "Goethe the Scientist"
  5. ^ The Theory of Knowledge Implicit in Goethe's World-Conception, with Specific Reference to Schiller, also translated as Goethe's Theory of Knowledge, An Outline of the Epistemology of His Worldview.
  6. ^ Truth and Knowledge, dedicated to Eduard von Hartmann.
  7. ^ Rudolf Steiner, Die Philosophie der Freiheit: Grundzuege einer modernen Weltanschauung, (Berlin: Emil Felder, 1894)
  8. ^ Sergei Prokofieff, Anthroposophy and The Philosophy of Freedom, Temple Lodge Press 2009, p. 206.
  9. ^ Fichte, The System of Ethics IV
  10. ^ Ch. 6
  11. ^ Rudolf Steiner, The Philosophy of Freedom: The Basis for a Modern World Conception, (London: Rudolf Steiner Press, 1964), ed. Michael Wilson, hereafter "Wilson", Ch. 9
  12. ^ Wilson, Ch. 1, (esp. p. 8).
  13. ^ Ethical-Spiritual Activity in Kant, A critical-speculative study of the true spirit in Kantian philosophy, Johannes Kreyenbuehl, article referenced by Steiner pubished in English tranlation 1986, ISBN 0-936132-81-7 [1]
  14. ^ Rudolf Steiner, Philosophie der Freiheit, Rudolf Steiner Verlag 1987, see Index of Names, pp. 283–284.
  15. ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (1991). Alan W. Wood (ed.). Elements of the philosophy of right. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ¶142.
  16. ^ :"My remarks concerning the self-supporting and self-determined nature of thinking cannot...be simply transferred to concepts. I make special mention of this, because it is here that I differ from Hegel, who regards the concept as something primary and original. -- end of first paragraph, Chapter 4, The Philosophy of Freedom
  17. ^ Wilson, p. 9.
  18. ^ Wilson, p. 19.
  19. ^ Wilson, p. 23.
  20. ^ Wilson, p. 26.
  21. ^ Wilson, p. 25.
  22. ^ Wilson, p. 27.
  23. ^ Wilson, p. 28.
  24. ^ Wilson, p 30. Steiner's own wording: "My investigation first touches firm ground only when I find an object which exists in a sense of which I can derive from the object itself. But I am myself such an object in that I think..."
  25. ^ Cottingham, Meditations, Objections and Replies
  26. ^ Descartes, it could be said, began his Meditations on First Philosophy I) with doubt about his own outer experience, Steiner with trust about his own inner experience.
  27. ^ a b c Steiner, Rudolf (1999). Michael Wilson (ed.). The Philosophy of Freedom: The Basis for a Modern World Conception. Steiner Books. ISBN 1-85584-082-0.
  28. ^ Philosophy of Freedom, p. 40
  29. ^ Augustine, Seventh Homily on the First Epistle of John
  30. ^ Steiner, The Theory of Knowledge Implicit in Goethe's World-Conception, with Specific Reference to Schiller. Chapter VIII in English version by O.D.Wanamaker, 1968 A Theory of Knowledge based on Goethe's World Conception, from second German edition 1924. Also translated as Goethe's Theory of Knowledge, An Outline of the Epistemology of His Worldview.
  31. ^ a b c Johannes Hemleben, Rudolf Steiner: A documentary biography, Henry Goulden, 1975, ISBN 0-904822-02-8, pp. 61–64 (German edition: Rudolf Steiner: mit Selbstzeugnissen und Bilddokumenten, Rowohlt, 1990, ISBN 3-499-50079-5)
  32. ^ The Philosophy of Freedom, Ch. X, "the Idea of Freedom", trans:(1) R.F.A. Hoernle; (2) R. Stebbing
  33. ^ "...Steiner is not implying that the circumstances are...shaping the free deed."Robert A. McDermott, American Philosophy and Rudolf Steiner, 2012 [2]
  34. ^ Agnes Nobel, Educating through Art, ISBN 0-86315-187-6, p. 103. (Originally published as Filosofens Knapp, Carlsson Bokförlag, Stockholm, 1991)
  35. ^ Otto Palmer, "A Partial Bibliography of the Works of Rudolf Steiner in Which He refers to The Philosophy of Freedom included in Rudolf Steiner on His Book the Philosophy of Freedom, Compiled by Otto Palmer (1964), ISBN 0910142688 [3]
  36. ^ The Riddles of Philosophy: A Brief Outline of an Approach to Anthroposophy, Chapter VIII A Brief Outline of an Approach to Anthroposophy.[4]
  37. ^ Paul Marshall Allen, in Foreword to Stebbing's 1963 translation
  38. ^ Sergei Prokofieff, May Human Beings Hear It!, Temple Lodge, 2004. p. 460
  39. ^ Preface to the 1924 edition of The Theory of Knowledge Implicit in Goethe's World-Conception (1886)"Theory of Knowledge Implicit in Goethe's World Conception", also translated as Goethe's Theory of Knowledge, An Outline of the Epistemology of His Worldview. Online translation into English by William Lindeman see [5]: As I look at it again today, it also appears to me to be the epistemological foundation and justification for every thing I said and published later. It speaks of the essential being of knowing activity that opens the way from the sense perceptible world into the spiritual one.
  40. ^ Rudolf Steiner Archive publication history
  41. ^ Majorek, Marek B. (2007). Phenomenology of Life from the Animal Soul to the Human Mind II: The Human Soul in the Creative Transformation of the Mind. Springer. pp. 259–278. ISBN 1402051816.