Lamarckism: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
→‎Criticism: Deleted paragraph that wasn't criticism. Perhaps it belongs in a different section (if it is factually accurate).
No edit summary
Line 1: Line 1:
'''Lamarckism''' (or '''Lamarckian inheritance''') is the [[idea]] that an [[organism]] can pass on characteristics that it acquired during its lifetime to its [[offspring]] (also known as [[inheritance of acquired characteristics|heritability of acquired characteristics]] or [[soft inheritance]]). It is named after the French biologist [[Jean-Baptiste Lamarck]] (1744–1829), who incorporated the action of soft inheritance into his evolutionary theories as a supplement to his concept of an inherent progressive tendency driving organisms continuously towards greater complexity, in parallel but separate lineages with no extinction. Lamarck did not originate the idea of soft inheritance, which proposes that individual efforts during the lifetime of the organisms were the main mechanism driving species to [[adaptation]], as they supposedly would acquire adaptive changes and pass them on to offspring.
'''Lamarckism''' (or '''Lamarckian inheritance''') is the [[idea]] that an [[organism]] can pass on characteristics that it acquired during its lifetime to its [[offspring]] (also known as [[inheritance of acquired characteristics|heritability of acquired characteristics]] or [[soft inheritance]]). It is named after the French biologist [[Jean-Baptiste Lamarck]] (1744–1829), who incorporated the action of soft inheritance into his evolutionary theories as a supplement to his concept of an inherent progressive tendency driving organisms continuously towards greater complexity, in parallel but separate lineages with no extinction. Lamarck did not originate the idea of soft inheritance, which proposes that individual efforts during the lifetime of the organisms were the main mechanism driving species to [[adaptation]], as they supposedly would acquire adaptive changes and pass them on to offspring.
{{Evolution theories}}
{{Evolution theories}}
When [[Charles Darwin]] published his theory of [[evolution]] by [[natural selection]] in ''[[On the Origin of Species]]'', he continued to give credence to what he called "use and disuse inheritance", but rejected other aspects of Lamarck's theories. Later, [[Mendelian genetics]] supplanted the notion of inheritance of acquired traits, eventually leading to the development of the [[modern evolutionary synthesis]], and the general abandonment of the Lamarckian theory of evolution in biology. Despite this abandonment, interest in Lamarckism has continued (2009) as studies in the field of [[epigenetics]] have highlighted the possible inheritance of behavioral traits acquired by the previous generation.<ref name=".<ref name="Roth et al.,">{{cite journal|last=Roth|first=Tania|coauthors=Lubin, Funk, Sweatt|title=Lasting Epigenetic Influence of early-life adversity on the BDNF Gene|journal=Biological Psychiatry|year=2009|month=February|volume=65|pages=760–769|url=http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/19150054|accessdate=13 May 2013|doi=10.1016/j.biopsych.2008.11.028|pmid=19150054|issue=9|pmc=3056389}}</ref><ref name="Arai et al.">{{cite journal|last=Arai|first=J|coauthors=Li, Hartley, Feig|title=Transgenerational rescue of a genetic deficit in Long-Term Potentiation and memory formation by juvenile enrichment|journal=The Journal of Neuroscience|year=2009|month=February|volume=29|issue=5|pages=1496–1502|url=http://www.jneurosci.org/content/29/5/1496.full.pdf|accessdate=13 May 2013|doi=10.1523/JNEUROSCI.5057-08.2009|pmid=19193896|pmc=3408235}}</ref>
When [[Charles Darwin]] published his theory of [[evolution]] by [[natural selection]] in ''[[On the Origin of Species]]'', he continued to give credence to what he called "use and disuse inheritance", but rejected other aspects of Lamarck's theories. Later, [[Mendelian genetics]] supplanted the notion of inheritance of acquired traits, eventually leading to the development of the [[modern evolutionary synthesis]], and the general abandonment of the Lamarckian theory of evolution in biology. Despite this abandonment, interest in Lamarckism has continued (2009) as studies in the field of [[epigenetics]] have highlighted the possible inheritance of behavioral traits acquired by the previous generation.<ref name=".<ref name="Roth et al.,">{{cite journal |doi=10.1016/j.biopsych.2008.11.028}}</ref><ref name="Arai et al.">{{cite journal |doi=10.1523/JNEUROSCI.5057-08.2009}}</ref>


==History==
==History==
Line 11: Line 11:
The ''[[Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation]]'', authored by [[Robert Chambers (journalist)|Robert Chambers]] in [[St Andrews]] and published anonymously in England in 1844, proposed a theory which combined radical [[phrenology]] with Lamarckism, causing political controversy for its [[Extremism|radicalism]] and unorthodoxy, but exciting popular interest and preparing a huge and prosperous audience for Darwin.
The ''[[Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation]]'', authored by [[Robert Chambers (journalist)|Robert Chambers]] in [[St Andrews]] and published anonymously in England in 1844, proposed a theory which combined radical [[phrenology]] with Lamarckism, causing political controversy for its [[Extremism|radicalism]] and unorthodoxy, but exciting popular interest and preparing a huge and prosperous audience for Darwin.


Darwin's ''[[Origin of Species]]'' proposed [[natural selection]] as the main mechanism for development of species, but did not rule out a variant of Lamarckism as a supplementary mechanism.<ref>[[Adrian Desmond|Desmond A.]] & [[James Moore (biographer)|Moore, J.]] (1991) ''Darwin'' Penguin Books p.617 "Darwin was {{sic|?|loathe|reason=The adjective is "loth"}} to let go of the notion that a well-used and strengthened organ could be inherited"</ref> Darwin called his Lamarckian hypothesis [[Pangenesis]], and explained it in the final chapter of his book ''Variation in Plants and Animals under Domestication'', after describing numerous examples to demonstrate what he considered to be the inheritance of acquired characteristics. Pangenesis, which he emphasised was a hypothesis, was based on the idea that [[somatic cell]]s would, in response to environmental stimulation (use and disuse), throw off '[[gemmules]]' or 'pangenes' which travelled around the body (though not necessarily in the bloodstream). These pangenes were microscopic particles that supposedly contained information about the characteristics of their parent cell, and Darwin believed that they eventually accumulated in the germ cells where they could pass on to the next generation the newly acquired characteristics of the parents. Darwin's half-cousin, [[Francis Galton]] carried out experiments on rabbits, with Darwin's cooperation, in which he transfused the blood of one variety of rabbit into another variety in the expectation that its offspring would show some characteristics of the first. They did not, and Galton declared that he had disproved Darwin's hypothesis of Pangenesis, but Darwin objected, in a letter to ''[[Nature (journal)|Nature]]'', that he had done nothing of the sort, since he had never mentioned blood in his writings. He pointed out that he regarded Pangenesis as occurring in Protozoa and plants, which have no blood.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://darwin-online.org.uk/content/frameset?viewtype=text&itemID=F1751&pageseq=1 |title=Pangenesis |accessdate=2007-11-08 |author= Charles Darwin|authorlink=Charles Darwin |date=27 April 1871 |work= |publisher=''Nature''. A Weekly Illustrated Journal of Science |pages=502–503 }}</ref>
Darwin's ''[[Origin of Species]]'' proposed [[natural selection]] as the main mechanism for development of species, but did not rule out a variant of Lamarckism as a supplementary mechanism.<ref>[[Adrian Desmond|Desmond A.]] & [[James Moore (biographer)|Moore, J.]] (1991) ''Darwin'' Penguin Books p.617 "Darwin was {{sic|?|loathe|reason=The adjective is "loth"}} to let go of the notion that a well-used and strengthened organ could be inherited"</ref> Darwin called his Lamarckian hypothesis [[Pangenesis]], and explained it in the final chapter of his book ''Variation in Plants and Animals under Domestication'', after describing numerous examples to demonstrate what he considered to be the inheritance of acquired characteristics. Pangenesis, which he emphasised was a hypothesis, was based on the idea that [[somatic cell]]s would, in response to environmental stimulation (use and disuse), throw off '[[gemmules]]' or 'pangenes' which travelled around the body (though not necessarily in the bloodstream). These pangenes were microscopic particles that supposedly contained information about the characteristics of their parent cell, and Darwin believed that they eventually accumulated in the germ cells where they could pass on to the next generation the newly acquired characteristics of the parents. Darwin's half-cousin, [[Francis Galton]] carried out experiments on rabbits, with Darwin's cooperation, in which he transfused the blood of one variety of rabbit into another variety in the expectation that its offspring would show some characteristics of the first. They did not, and Galton declared that he had disproved Darwin's hypothesis of Pangenesis, but Darwin objected, in a letter to ''[[Nature (journal)|Nature]]'', that he had done nothing of the sort, since he had never mentioned blood in his writings. He pointed out that he regarded Pangenesis as occurring in Protozoa and plants, which have no blood.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1038/003502a0 |doi_brokendate=December 27, 2013 |bibcode=1871Natur...3..502D}}</ref>


===1880 to 1930===
===1880 to 1930===
Line 22: Line 22:
A form of Lamarckism was revived in the [[Soviet Union]] of the 1930s when [[Trofim Lysenko]] promoted [[Lysenkoism]] which suited the ideological opposition of [[Joseph Stalin]] to [[genetics]]. This ideologically driven research influenced Soviet agricultural policy which in turn was later blamed for crop failures.<ref>Davis Baird, Eric R. Scerri, Lee C. McIntyre. (2005). ''Philosophy of Chemistry: Synthesis of a New Discipline''. Springer. p. 166</ref>
A form of Lamarckism was revived in the [[Soviet Union]] of the 1930s when [[Trofim Lysenko]] promoted [[Lysenkoism]] which suited the ideological opposition of [[Joseph Stalin]] to [[genetics]]. This ideologically driven research influenced Soviet agricultural policy which in turn was later blamed for crop failures.<ref>Davis Baird, Eric R. Scerri, Lee C. McIntyre. (2005). ''Philosophy of Chemistry: Synthesis of a New Discipline''. Springer. p. 166</ref>


The biologist [[Ernest MacBride]] was a supporter of Lamarckian evolution.<ref>[[Peter J. Bowler]]. (1984). ''E. W. MacBride's Lamarckian eugenics and its implications for the social construction of scientific knowledge''. Annals of Science, Vol. 41, Issue 3. pp. 245-260</ref> [[Herbert Graham Cannon]] a British zoologist defended Lamarckism in his book ''Lamarck and Modern Genetics'' in 1959.<ref>[[Herbert Graham Cannon]]. (1975). ''Lamarck and Modern Genetics'' Greenwood Press Reprint. ISBN 0-8371-8173-9</ref>
The biologist [[Ernest MacBride]] was a supporter of Lamarckian evolution.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1080/00033798400200251}}</ref> [[Herbert Graham Cannon]] a British zoologist defended Lamarckism in his book ''Lamarck and Modern Genetics'' in 1959.<ref>[[Herbert Graham Cannon]]. (1975). ''Lamarck and Modern Genetics'' Greenwood Press Reprint. ISBN 0-8371-8173-9</ref>


Since 1988 certain scientists have produced work proposing that Lamarckism could apply to single celled organisms. A version of Lamarckian acquisition in higher order animals is still posited in certain branches of [[psychology]], as, for example, in the Jungian [[racial memory]].
Since 1988 certain scientists have produced work proposing that Lamarckism could apply to single celled organisms. A version of Lamarckian acquisition in higher order animals is still posited in certain branches of [[psychology]], as, for example, in the Jungian [[racial memory]].
Line 43: Line 43:
Lamarck stated the following two laws:
Lamarck stated the following two laws:
# ''Première Loi. Dans tout animal qui n' a point dépassé le terme de ses développemens, l' emploi plus fréquent et soutenu d' un organe quelconque, fortifie peu à peu cet organe, le développe, l' agrandit, et lui donne une puissance proportionnée à la durée de cet emploi ; tandis que le défaut constant d' usage de tel organe, l'affoiblit insensiblement, le détériore, diminue progressivement ses facultés, et finit par le faire disparoître.''
# ''Première Loi. Dans tout animal qui n' a point dépassé le terme de ses développemens, l' emploi plus fréquent et soutenu d' un organe quelconque, fortifie peu à peu cet organe, le développe, l' agrandit, et lui donne une puissance proportionnée à la durée de cet emploi ; tandis que le défaut constant d' usage de tel organe, l'affoiblit insensiblement, le détériore, diminue progressivement ses facultés, et finit par le faire disparoître.''
# ''Deuxième Loi. Tout ce que la nature a fait acquérir ou perdre aux individus par l' influence des circonstances où leur race se trouve depuis long-temps exposée, et, par conséquent, par l' influence de l' emploi prédominant de tel organe, ou par celle d' un défaut constant d' usage de telle partie ; elle le conserve par la génération aux nouveaux individus qui en proviennent, pourvu que les changemens acquis soient communs aux deux sexes, ou à ceux qui ont produit ces nouveaux individus.''<ref>Jean-Baptiste Lamarck ''[http://www.lamarck.cnrs.fr/ice/ice_book_detail.php?lang=fr&type=text&bdd=lamarck&table=ouvrages_lamarck&bookId=29&typeofbookId=1&num=0 Philosophie zoologique]'' ch.7, p.235</ref>
# ''Deuxième Loi. Tout ce que la nature a fait acquérir ou perdre aux individus par l' influence des circonstances où leur race se trouve depuis long-temps exposée, et, par conséquent, par l' influence de l' emploi prédominant de tel organe, ou par celle d' un défaut constant d' usage de telle partie ; elle le conserve par la génération aux nouveaux individus qui en proviennent, pourvu que les changemens acquis soient communs aux deux sexes, ou à ceux qui ont produit ces nouveaux individus.''<ref>Jean-Baptiste Lamarck ''[http://www.lamarck.cnrs.fr/ice/ice_book_detail.php?lang=fr&type=text&bdd=lamarck&table=ouvrages_lamarck&bookId=29&typeofbookId=1&num=0 Philosophie zoologique]'' ch.7, p.235{{dead link}}</ref>
English translation:
English translation:
# ''In every animal which has not passed the limit of its development, a more frequent and continuous use of any organ gradually strengthens, develops and enlarges that organ, and gives it a power proportional to the length of time it has been so used; while the permanent disuse of any organ imperceptibly weakens and deteriorates it, and progressively diminishes its functional capacity, until it finally disappears.''
# ''In every animal which has not passed the limit of its development, a more frequent and continuous use of any organ gradually strengthens, develops and enlarges that organ, and gives it a power proportional to the length of time it has been so used; while the permanent disuse of any organ imperceptibly weakens and deteriorates it, and progressively diminishes its functional capacity, until it finally disappears.''
Line 61: Line 61:
</ref>
</ref>


The French botanist [[Gaston Bonnier]], conducting experiments in the [[French Alps]] in 1884 and the [[Pyrenees]] in 1886, studied structural changes induced by growing plants at various altitudes and [[transplanting]] them to others. Bonnier believed he had proven acquired adaptive characteristics; however, he did not weed, cultivate, fertilize or protect his plant specimens from native vegetation. In the 1920s his experiments were analysed and attributed to [[Genetic pollution|genetic contamination]] rather than Lamarckian inheritance.<ref>Robert E. Kohler. (2002). ''Landscapes and Labscapes: Exploring the Lab-Field Border in Biology''. University Of Chicago Press. p. 167. ISBN 978-0226450100</ref>
The French botanist [[Gaston Bonnier]], conducting experiments in the [[French Alps]] in 1884 and the [[Pyrenees]] in 1886, studied structural changes induced by growing plants at various altitudes and [[transplanting]] them to others. Bonnier believed he had proven acquired adaptive characteristics; however, he did not weed, cultivate, fertilize or protect his plant specimens from native vegetation. In the 1920s his experiments were analysed and attributed to [[Genetic pollution|genetic contamination]] rather than Lamarckian inheritance.<ref>Robert E. Kohler. (2002). ''Landscapes and Labscapes: Exploring the Lab-Field Border in Biology''. University Of Chicago Press. p. 167. ISBN 978-0-226-45010-0</ref>


In a series of experiments (in 1891, 1893 and 1895) on the action of light on the coloration of [[flatfish]], the British marine biologist [[Joseph Thomas Cunningham]] directed light upon the lower sides of flatfishes by means of a glass-bottomed [[Aquarium|tank]] placed over a mirror. He discovered the influence of light in producing [[Biological pigment|pigments]] on the lower sides of flatfishes and gave his results a Lamarckian interpretation.<ref>Cunningham, J. T. (1891). ''An experiment concerning the absence of color from the lower sides of flat-fishes''. Zool. Anzeiger 14: 27-32. Cunningham J. T. (1893). ''Researches on the coloration of the skins of flat-fishes''. Journal of the Marine Biological Association. 3:111-118. Cunningham, J. T. (1895). ''Additional Evidence on the Influence of Light in producing Pigments on the Lower Sides of Flat Fishes''. J. Mar. Bio. Assoc. U.K. 4 (N.S): 53-59.</ref> Other scientists wrote that Cunningham had received some definite results, but that they were open to more than one interpretation.<ref>[[The Spectator]]. (1928). Volume 141. p. 25</ref> The geneticist [[William Bateson]] was not convinced that the cause of the increase in pigmentation was from the illumination. [[George Romanes]] wrote approvingly of Cunningham's interpretation.<ref>Alan G. Cock, Donald R. Forsdyke. (2008). ''Treasure Your Exceptions: The Science and Life of William Bateson''. Springer. pp. 132-133. ISBN 978-0387756875</ref> [[Thomas Hunt Morgan]] (1903) criticized the experiments and did not believe the results were evidence for Lamarckism.<ref>[[Thomas Hunt Morgan]]. (1903). ''Evolution and Adaptation''. The Macmillan company. pp. 257-259</ref>
In a series of experiments (in 1891, 1893 and 1895) on the action of light on the coloration of [[flatfish]], the British marine biologist [[Joseph Thomas Cunningham]] directed light upon the lower sides of flatfishes by means of a glass-bottomed [[Aquarium|tank]] placed over a mirror. He discovered the influence of light in producing [[Biological pigment|pigments]] on the lower sides of flatfishes and gave his results a Lamarckian interpretation.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Cunningham |first=J. T. |year=1891 |title=An experiment concerning the absence of color from the lower sides of flat-fishes |journal=Zool. Anzeiger |volume=14 |pages=27-32}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1017/S0025315400049596}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |doi=/10.1017/S0025315400050761}}</ref> Other scientists wrote that Cunningham had received some definite results, but that they were open to more than one interpretation.<ref>[[The Spectator]]. (1928). Volume 141. p. 25</ref> The geneticist [[William Bateson]] was not convinced that the cause of the increase in pigmentation was from the illumination. [[George Romanes]] wrote approvingly of Cunningham's interpretation.<ref>Alan G. Cock, Donald R. Forsdyke. (2008). ''Treasure Your Exceptions: The Science and Life of William Bateson''. Springer. pp. 132-133. ISBN 978-0387756875</ref> [[Thomas Hunt Morgan]] (1903) criticized the experiments and did not believe the results were evidence for Lamarckism.<ref>[[Thomas Hunt Morgan]]. (1903). ''Evolution and Adaptation''. The Macmillan company. pp. 257-259</ref>


In the late 19th century [[Frederick Merrifield]] exposed [[caterpillar]]s and [[Pupa|chrysalid]]s to significantly high and low temperatures, and discovered permanent changes in some offspring's wing patterns. Swiss biologist [[Max Standfuss]] led 30 years of intensive breeding experiments with European butterflies and after several generations, found similar preserved variations even generations after the cessation of exposing them to low temperatures.<ref>[[Auguste Forel]]. (1929). ''The Sexual Question: A Scientific, Psychological, Hygienic and Sociological Study for the Cultured Classes''. Physicians and Surgeons Book Company. p. 36</ref> Standfuss was a Lamarckian and attributed the results of his experiments as direct changes to the environment.<ref>John Michels. (1896). Science: Volume 4. Moses King. p. 53</ref> In 1940 [[Richard Goldschmidt]] interpreted these results without invoking Lamarckian inheritance, and in 1998 [[Ernst Mayr]] wrote that results reported by Standfuss and others on the effects of abnormal temperatures on [[Lepidoptera]] are difficult to interpret.<ref>[[Richard Goldschmidt]] (1940). ''The Material Basis of Evolution''. Yale University. pp. 266-267. [[Ernst Mayr]]. (1998). ''The Evolutionary Synthesis: Perspectives on the Unification of Biology''. Harvard University Press. p. 348</ref>
In the late 19th century [[Frederick Merrifield]] exposed [[caterpillar]]s and [[Pupa|chrysalid]]s to significantly high and low temperatures, and discovered permanent changes in some offspring's wing patterns. Swiss biologist [[Max Standfuss]] led 30 years of intensive breeding experiments with European butterflies and after several generations, found similar preserved variations even generations after the cessation of exposing them to low temperatures.<ref>[[Auguste Forel]]. (1929). ''The Sexual Question: A Scientific, Psychological, Hygienic and Sociological Study for the Cultured Classes''. Physicians and Surgeons Book Company. p. 36</ref> Standfuss was a Lamarckian and attributed the results of his experiments as direct changes to the environment.<ref>John Michels. (1896). Science: Volume 4. Moses King. p. 53</ref> In 1940 [[Richard Goldschmidt]] interpreted these results without invoking Lamarckian inheritance, and in 1998 [[Ernst Mayr]] wrote that results reported by Standfuss and others on the effects of abnormal temperatures on [[Lepidoptera]] are difficult to interpret.<ref>[[Richard Goldschmidt]] (1940). ''The Material Basis of Evolution''. Yale University. pp. 266-267. [[Ernst Mayr]]. (1998). ''The Evolutionary Synthesis: Perspectives on the Unification of Biology''. Harvard University Press. p. 348</ref>
Line 71: Line 71:
In a series of experiments [[Francis Bertody Sumner]] (1874-1945) reared several generations of white mice under different conditions of temperature and relative humidity.<ref>Robert Thompson Young. (1922). ''Biology in America''. R.G. Badger. p. 249</ref> Sumner discovered that the white mice at 20°C to 30°C developed longer bodies, tails and hind feet which were also transmitted to their offspring over a number of generations, however, later results were not entirely consistent and the experiments ended in uncertainty.<ref>Charles Manning Child. (1947). ''Biographical Memoir of Francis Bertody Sumner, 1874-1945''. In National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America Biographical Memoirs, Vol. 25. 146-73.</ref>
In a series of experiments [[Francis Bertody Sumner]] (1874-1945) reared several generations of white mice under different conditions of temperature and relative humidity.<ref>Robert Thompson Young. (1922). ''Biology in America''. R.G. Badger. p. 249</ref> Sumner discovered that the white mice at 20°C to 30°C developed longer bodies, tails and hind feet which were also transmitted to their offspring over a number of generations, however, later results were not entirely consistent and the experiments ended in uncertainty.<ref>Charles Manning Child. (1947). ''Biographical Memoir of Francis Bertody Sumner, 1874-1945''. In National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America Biographical Memoirs, Vol. 25. 146-73.</ref>


In the 1920s, Harvard University researcher [[William McDougall (psychologist)|William McDougall]] studied the abilities of rats to correctly solve mazes. He found that offspring of rats that had learned the maze were able to run it faster. The first rats would get it wrong 165 times before being able to run it perfectly each time, but after a few generations it was down to 20. McDougall attributed this to some sort of Lamarckian evolutionary process.<ref>William McDougall. (1938). ''Fourth Report on a Lamarckian Experiment''. British Journal of Psychology 28: 321-345.</ref> [[Oscar Werner Tiegs]] and [[Wilfred Eade Agar]] later showed McDougall's results to be incorrect, caused by poor experimental controls.<ref>{{cite journal |author=Pantin, C F A |publisher=[[The Royal Society]] |journal=Biographical Memiors of Fellows of the [[Royal Society]] |volume=3 |date=November 1957 |page=247 |title=Oscar Werner Tiegs |doi=10.1098/rsbm.1957.0017}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |title=First report on a test of McDougall's Lamarckian experiment on the training of rats |year=1935 |journal=Journal of Experimental Biology |volume=12 |page=191 |author=W E Agar, F H Drummond}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |title=Second report on a test of McDougall's Lamarckian experiment on the training of rats |year=1942 |journal=Journal of Experimental Biology |volume=19 |page=158 |author=W E Agar, F H Drummond}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |title=Third report on a test of McDougall's Lamarckian experiment on the training of rats |year=1948 |journal=Journal of Experimental Biology |volume=25 |page=103 |author=W E Agar, F H Drummond}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |title=Fourth (final) report on a test of McDougall's Lamarckian experiment on the training of rats |year=1954 |journal=Journal of Experimental Biology |volume=31 |page=308 |author=W E Agar, F H Drummond, M M Gunson}}</ref>
In the 1920s, Harvard University researcher [[William McDougall (psychologist)|William McDougall]] studied the abilities of rats to correctly solve mazes. He found that offspring of rats that had learned the maze were able to run it faster. The first rats would get it wrong 165 times before being able to run it perfectly each time, but after a few generations it was down to 20. McDougall attributed this to some sort of Lamarckian evolutionary process.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1111/j.2044-8295.1938.tb00882.x}}</ref> [[Oscar Werner Tiegs]] and [[Wilfred Eade Agar]] later showed McDougall's results to be incorrect, caused by poor experimental controls.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1098/rsbm.1957.0017}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |title=First report on a test of McDougall's Lamarckian experiment on the training of rats |year=1935 |journal=Journal of Experimental Biology |volume=12 |page=191 |author=W E Agar, F H Drummond}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |title=Second report on a test of McDougall's Lamarckian experiment on the training of rats |year=1942 |journal=Journal of Experimental Biology |volume=19 |page=158 |author=W E Agar, F H Drummond |url=http://jeb.biologists.org/content/19/2/158.short}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |title=Third report on a test of McDougall's Lamarckian experiment on the training of rats |year=1948 |journal=Journal of Experimental Biology |volume=25 |page=103 |author=W E Agar, F H Drummond |url=http://jeb.biologists.org/content/25/2/103.short}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |title=Fourth (final) report on a test of McDougall's Lamarckian experiment on the training of rats |year=1954 |journal=Journal of Experimental Biology |volume=31 |page=308 |author=W E Agar, F H Drummond, M M Gunson |url=http://jeb.biologists.org/content/31/3/307.short}}</ref>


The Russian physiologist [[Ivan Pavlov]] claimed to have observed a similar phenomenon in white mice being subject to a [[conditioned reflex]] experiment involving food and the sound of a bell. He wrote that with each generation, the mice became easier to condition. In 1926 Pavlov announced that there had been a fatal flaw in his experiment and retracted his claim to have demonstrated Lamarckian inheritance.<ref>[[William McDougall (psychologist)|William McDougall]]. (1934). ''Religion and the Sciences of Life: With Other Essays on Allied Topics''. Methuen & Co., Ltd. p. 180</ref> In other experiments [[Coleman Griffith]] (1920, 1922) and John Detlefson (1923, 1925) reared rats in cages on a rotating table for three months. The rats adapted to the rotating condition to such an extent that when the rotation was stopped they showed signs of [[Balance disorder|disequilibration]] and other [[physiology|physiological]] conditions which were inherited for several generations.<ref>Griffith, C. R. (1920). ''The Effect upon the White Rat of Continued Bodily Rotation''. The American Naturalist. Vol 54, No. 635. pp. 524-534. Griffith, C. R. (1922). ''Are permanent disturbances of equilibration inherited?''" ''Science'' 56: 676-8. Detlefsen, J. A. (1923). Are the effects of long-continued rotation in rats inherited? Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 62, 292-300. Detlefsen, J. A. (1925). ''The inheritance of acquired characters''. Physiological Reviews, 5. pp. 224-278.</ref> In 1933 Roy Dorcus replicated their experiments but obtained different results as the rotated rats did not manifest any abnormalities of posture described by Griffith and Detlefson.<ref>Dorcus. R. M. (1933). ''The effect of intermittent rotation on orientation and the habituation of nystagmusin the rat and some observations on the effects of prenatal rotation on post-natal development''. Jour. Comp. Psychol. 15: 469-475.</ref> Other studies revealed that the same abnormalities could occur in rats without rotation if they were suffering from an ear infection thus the results were interpreted as a case of infection, not Lamarckian inheritance.<ref>Studies from the Otho S. A. Sprague Memorial Institute. (1940). Volume 25. p. 162</ref>
The Russian physiologist [[Ivan Pavlov]] claimed to have observed a similar phenomenon in white mice being subject to a [[conditioned reflex]] experiment involving food and the sound of a bell. He wrote that with each generation, the mice became easier to condition. In 1926 Pavlov announced that there had been a fatal flaw in his experiment and retracted his claim to have demonstrated Lamarckian inheritance.<ref>[[William McDougall (psychologist)|William McDougall]]. (1934). ''Religion and the Sciences of Life: With Other Essays on Allied Topics''. Methuen & Co., Ltd. p. 180</ref> In other experiments [[Coleman Griffith]] (1920, 1922) and John Detlefson (1923, 1925) reared rats in cages on a rotating table for three months. The rats adapted to the rotating condition to such an extent that when the rotation was stopped they showed signs of [[Balance disorder|disequilibration]] and other [[physiology|physiological]] conditions which were inherited for several generations.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Griffith |first1=Coleman R. |year=1920 |title=The Effect upon the White Rat of Continued Bodily Rotation |journal=The American Naturalist |volume=54 |issue=635 |pages=524-34 |jstor=2456346}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1126/science.56.1459.676}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last=Detlefsen |first=J. A. |year=1923 |title=Are the Effects of Long-Continued Rotation in Rats Inherited? |journal=Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society |volume=62 |issue=5 |pages=292-300 |jstor=984462}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last=Detlefsen |first=J. A. |year=1925 |title=The inheritance of acquired characters |journal=Physiological Reviews |volume=5 |issue=2 |pages=224-78 |url=http://physrev.physiology.org/content/5/2/244.extract}}</ref> In 1933 Roy Dorcus replicated their experiments but obtained different results as the rotated rats did not manifest any abnormalities of posture described by Griffith and Detlefson.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1037/h0074715}}</ref> Other studies revealed that the same abnormalities could occur in rats without rotation if they were suffering from an ear infection thus the results were interpreted as a case of infection, not Lamarckian inheritance.<ref>Studies from the Otho S. A. Sprague Memorial Institute. (1940). Volume 25. p. 162</ref>


Between 1918 and 1924 two American scientists Michael F. Guyer and Elizabeth A. Smith performed experiments in which fowl serum antibodies for [[rabbit]] lens-protein were injected into pregnant rabbits which resulted in defects in the eyes of some of their offspring that were inherited through eight generations.<ref>M. F. Guyer and E. A. Smith. (1920). ''Transmission of Eye-Defects Induced in Rabbits by means of Lens-Sensitized Fowl-Serum''. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. No. 3. pp. 134-136.</ref> Their experiments were criticized and were not repeated by other scientists.<ref>[[Peter Medawar]]. (1985). ''Aristotle to Zoos: A Philosophical Dictionary of Biology''. Harvard University Press. p. 169</ref> In the 1930s the German geneticist [[Victor Jollos]] (1887-1941) in a series of experiments claimed evidence for inherited changes induced by heat treatment in ''[[Drosophila melanogaster]]''.<ref>Jollos, V. (1934). ''Inherited changes produced by heat-treatment in Drosophila melanogaster''" ''Genetica'' 16:476-494.</ref> His experiments were described as Lamarckian however Jollos was not an advocate of Lamarckian evolution and attributed the results from his experiments as evidence for [[directed mutagenesis]]. American scientists were unable to replicate his results.<ref>Jonathan Harwood. (1993). ''Styles of Scientific Thought: The German Genetics Community, 1900-1933''. The University of Chicago Press. pp. 121-131.</ref>
Between 1918 and 1924 two American scientists Michael F. Guyer and Elizabeth A. Smith performed experiments in which fowl serum antibodies for [[rabbit]] lens-protein were injected into pregnant rabbits which resulted in defects in the eyes of some of their offspring that were inherited through eight generations.<ref>{{cite journal |pmid=16576477}}</ref> Their experiments were criticized and were not repeated by other scientists.<ref>[[Peter Medawar]]. (1985). ''Aristotle to Zoos: A Philosophical Dictionary of Biology''. Harvard University Press. p. 169</ref> In the 1930s the German geneticist [[Victor Jollos]] (1887-1941) in a series of experiments claimed evidence for inherited changes induced by heat treatment in ''[[Drosophila melanogaster]]''.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1007/BF01984742}}</ref> His experiments were described as Lamarckian however Jollos was not an advocate of Lamarckian evolution and attributed the results from his experiments as evidence for [[directed mutagenesis]]. American scientists were unable to replicate his results.<ref>Jonathan Harwood. (1993). ''Styles of Scientific Thought: The German Genetics Community, 1900-1933''. The University of Chicago Press. pp. 121-131.</ref>
The American paleontologist [[Edward Drinker Cope]] was a neo-Lamarckian as he believed that an organism could respond to any challenge by choosing to adapt to a new way of life.<ref>[[Peter J. Bowler]]. (2009). ''Evolution: The History of an Idea''. University of California Press. p. 227. ISBN 978-0520261280</ref> The British anthropologist [[Frederic Wood Jones]] and the South African paleontologist [[Robert Broom]] supported a neo-Lamarckian view of human evolution as opposed to the Darwinian view. The German anthropologist [[Hermann Klaatsch]] relied on a neo-Lamarckian model of evolution to try and explain the origin of [[bipedalism]]. Neo-Lamarckism remained influential in [[biology]] until the 1940s when the role of [[natural selection]] was reasserted in evolution as part of the [[modern evolutionary synthesis]].<ref>Bernard Wood. (2013). ''Wiley-Blackwell Encyclopedia of Human Evolution''. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1118650998</ref>
The American paleontologist [[Edward Drinker Cope]] was a neo-Lamarckian as he believed that an organism could respond to any challenge by choosing to adapt to a new way of life.<ref>[[Peter J. Bowler]]. (2009). ''Evolution: The History of an Idea''. University of California Press. p. 227. ISBN 978-0-520-26128-0</ref> The British anthropologist [[Frederic Wood Jones]] and the South African paleontologist [[Robert Broom]] supported a neo-Lamarckian view of human evolution as opposed to the Darwinian view. The German anthropologist [[Hermann Klaatsch]] relied on a neo-Lamarckian model of evolution to try and explain the origin of [[bipedalism]]. Neo-Lamarckism remained influential in [[biology]] until the 1940s when the role of [[natural selection]] was reasserted in evolution as part of the [[modern evolutionary synthesis]].<ref>Bernard Wood. (2013). ''Wiley-Blackwell Encyclopedia of Human Evolution''. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-118-65099-8</ref>


In the 1970s the immunologist [[Edward J. Steele|Ted Steele]], formerly of the [[University of Wollongong]], and colleagues, proposed a neo-Lamarckian mechanism to try to explain why homologous DNA sequences from the VDJ gene regions of parent mice were found in their germ cells and seemed to persist in the offspring for a few generations. The mechanism involved the somatic selection and clonal amplification of newly acquired [[antibody]] gene sequences that were generated via somatic hyper-mutation in [[B-cells]]. The mRNA products of these somatically novel genes were captured by retroviruses endogenous to the B-cells and were then transported through the blood stream where they could breach the [[Weismann barrier|soma-germ barrier]] and retrofect ([[reverse transcription|reverse transcribe]]) the newly acquired genes into the cells of the germ line. Although Steele was advocating this theory for the better part of two decades, little more than indirect evidence was ever acquired to support it. An interesting attribute of this idea is that it strongly resembles Darwin's own theory of pangenesis, except in the soma to germ line feedback theory, pangenes are replaced with realistic retroviruses.<ref name=Steele>Edward J. Steele, Robyn A. Lindley, Robert V. Blanden. (1998). ''Lamarck's Signature : How Retrogenes Are Changing Darwin's Natural Selection Paradigm''. Perseus Books.</ref> Regarding Steele's research [[Peter J. Bowler]] wrote "his work was bitterly criticized at the time by biologists who doubted his experimental results and rejected his hypothetical mechanism as implausible."<ref>[[Peter J. Bowler]]. (1989). The Mendelian Revolution: The Emergence of Hereditarian Concepts in Modern Science and Society. The Johns Hopkins University Press. p. 179</ref>
In the 1970s the immunologist [[Edward J. Steele|Ted Steele]], formerly of the [[University of Wollongong]], and colleagues, proposed a neo-Lamarckian mechanism to try to explain why homologous DNA sequences from the VDJ gene regions of parent mice were found in their germ cells and seemed to persist in the offspring for a few generations. The mechanism involved the somatic selection and clonal amplification of newly acquired [[antibody]] gene sequences that were generated via somatic hyper-mutation in [[B-cells]]. The mRNA products of these somatically novel genes were captured by retroviruses endogenous to the B-cells and were then transported through the blood stream where they could breach the [[Weismann barrier|soma-germ barrier]] and retrofect ([[reverse transcription|reverse transcribe]]) the newly acquired genes into the cells of the germ line. Although Steele was advocating this theory for the better part of two decades, little more than indirect evidence was ever acquired to support it. An interesting attribute of this idea is that it strongly resembles Darwin's own theory of pangenesis, except in the soma to germ line feedback theory, pangenes are replaced with realistic retroviruses.<ref name=Steele>Edward J. Steele, Robyn A. Lindley, Robert V. Blanden. (1998). ''Lamarck's Signature : How Retrogenes Are Changing Darwin's Natural Selection Paradigm''. Perseus Books{{pn}}ref> Regarding Steele's research [[Peter J. Bowler]] wrote "his work was bitterly criticized at the time by biologists who doubted his experimental results and rejected his hypothetical mechanism as implausible."<ref>[[Peter J. Bowler]]. (1989). The Mendelian Revolution: The Emergence of Hereditarian Concepts in Modern Science and Society. The Johns Hopkins University Press. p. 179</ref>


Neo-Lamarckism was dominant in French [[biology]] for more than a century. French scientists who supported neo-Lamarckism included [[Edmond Perrier]] (1844-1921), [[Alfred Mathieu Giard|Alfred Giard]] (1846-1908), [[Gaston Bonnier]] (1853-1922) and [[Pierre-Paul Grassé]] (1895-1985).<ref>Loison, L. (2011). [http://loison.laurent.free.fr/pdf/French-Roots-of-French-Neo-Lamarckisms-JHB.pdf ''French roots of French Neo-Lamarckisms, 1879-1985]''. ''Journal of the History of Biology'' 44, 713-744.</ref>
Neo-Lamarckism was dominant in French [[biology]] for more than a century. French scientists who supported neo-Lamarckism included [[Edmond Perrier]] (1844-1921), [[Alfred Mathieu Giard|Alfred Giard]] (1846-1908), [[Gaston Bonnier]] (1853-1922) and [[Pierre-Paul Grassé]] (1895-1985).<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1007/s10739-010-9240-x}}</ref>


===Ideological neo-Lamarckism===
===Ideological neo-Lamarckism===
Neo-Lamarckian versions of evolution were widespread in the late 19th century. The idea that living things could to some degree ''choose'' the characteristics that would be inherited allowed them things to be in charge of their own destiny as opposed to the Darwinian view, which made them puppets at the mercy of the environment. Such ideas were more popular than [[natural selection]] in the late 19th century as it made it possible for biological evolution to fit into a framework of a divine or naturally willed plan, thus the neo-Lamarckian view of evolution was often advocated by proponents of [[orthogenesis]].<ref>[[Peter J. Bowler]]. (1992). ''The Eclipse of Darwinism: Anti-Darwinian Evolution Theories in the Decades around 1900''. The Johns Hopkins University Press. ISBN 978-0801843914</ref> According to historian of biology [[Peter J. Bowler]]:
Neo-Lamarckian versions of evolution were widespread in the late 19th century. The idea that living things could to some degree ''choose'' the characteristics that would be inherited allowed them things to be in charge of their own destiny as opposed to the Darwinian view, which made them puppets at the mercy of the environment. Such ideas were more popular than [[natural selection]] in the late 19th century as it made it possible for biological evolution to fit into a framework of a divine or naturally willed plan, thus the neo-Lamarckian view of evolution was often advocated by proponents of [[orthogenesis]].<ref>[[Peter J. Bowler]]. (1992). ''The Eclipse of Darwinism: Anti-Darwinian Evolution Theories in the Decades around 1900''. The Johns Hopkins University Press. ISBN 978-0-8018-4391-4</ref> According to historian of biology [[Peter J. Bowler]]:


{{blockquote|One of the most emotionally compelling arguments used by the neo-Lamarckians of the late nineteenth century was the claim that Darwinism was a mechanistic theory which reduced living things to puppets driven by heredity. The selection theory made life into a game of Russian roulette, where life or death was predetermined by the genes one inherited. The individual could do nothing to mitigate bad heredity. Lamarckism, in contrast, allowed the individual to choose a new habit when faced with an environmental challenge and shape the whole future course of evolution.<ref>[[Peter J. Bowler]]. (2003). ''Evolution: The History of an Idea''. University of California Press p. 367. ISBN 978-0520261280</ref>}}
{{blockquote|One of the most emotionally compelling arguments used by the neo-Lamarckians of the late nineteenth century was the claim that Darwinism was a mechanistic theory which reduced living things to puppets driven by heredity. The selection theory made life into a game of Russian roulette, where life or death was predetermined by the genes one inherited. The individual could do nothing to mitigate bad heredity. Lamarckism, in contrast, allowed the individual to choose a new habit when faced with an environmental challenge and shape the whole future course of evolution.<ref>[[Peter J. Bowler]]. (2003). ''Evolution: The History of an Idea''. University of California Press p. 367. ISBN 978-0-520-26128-0</ref>}}


Supporters of neo-Lamarckism such as [[George Bernard Shaw]] and [[Arthur Koestler]] claimed that Lamarckism is more humane, and optimistic than Darwinism.<ref>James Richard Moore. (2002). ''History, Humanity and Evolution: Essays for John C. Greene''. Cambridge University Press. p. 330. ISBN 978-0521524780</ref>
Supporters of neo-Lamarckism such as [[George Bernard Shaw]] and [[Arthur Koestler]] claimed that Lamarckism is more humane, and optimistic than Darwinism.<ref>James Richard Moore. (2002). ''History, Humanity and Evolution: Essays for John C. Greene''. Cambridge University Press. p. 330. ISBN 978-0-521-52478-0</ref>


== Current views ==
== Current views ==
===Epigenetic inheritance===
===Epigenetic inheritance===
[[File:DNA methylation.jpg|thumb|300px|Illustration of a [[DNA]] molecule that is methylated at the two center cytosines. DNA methylation plays an important role for [[Epigenetics|epigenetic]] gene regulation in development and disease.]]
[[File:DNA methylation.jpg|thumb|300px|Illustration of a [[DNA]] molecule that is methylated at the two center cytosines. DNA methylation plays an important role for [[Epigenetics|epigenetic]] gene regulation in development and disease.]]
Forms of 'soft' or [[Epigenetics|epigenetic inheritance]] within organisms have been suggested as neo-Lamarckian in nature by such scientists as [[Eva Jablonka]] and [[Marion J. Lamb]]. In addition to 'hard' or genetic inheritance, involving the duplication of genetic material and its segregation during [[meiosis]], there are other hereditary elements that pass into the germ cells also. These include things like [[DNA methylation|methylation]] patterns in DNA and [[chromatin]] marks, both of which regulate the activity of genes. These are considered "Lamarckian" in the sense that they are responsive to environmental stimuli and can differentially affect gene expression adaptively, with phenotypic results that can persist for many generations in certain organisms.<ref name=Jablonka>[[Eva Jablonka]], [[Marion J. Lamb]]. (1995). ''Epigenetic Inheritance and Evolution: The Lamarckian Dimension''. Oxford University Press.</ref> In 2008, Jablonka and Lamb published a paper which claimed there is evidence for Lamarckian epigenetic control systems causing evolutionary changes and the mechanisms underlying epigenetic inheritance can also lead to [[Saltation (biology)|saltational]] changes that reorganize the epigenome.<ref>[[Eva Jablonka]], [[Marion J. Lamb]]. (2008). ''Soft Inheritance: Challenging the Modern Synthesis''. Genetics and Molecular Biology. 31: 393.</ref>
Forms of 'soft' or [[Epigenetics|epigenetic inheritance]] within organisms have been suggested as neo-Lamarckian in nature by such scientists as [[Eva Jablonka]] and [[Marion J. Lamb]]. In addition to 'hard' or genetic inheritance, involving the duplication of genetic material and its segregation during [[meiosis]], there are other hereditary elements that pass into the germ cells also. These include things like [[DNA methylation|methylation]] patterns in DNA and [[chromatin]] marks, both of which regulate the activity of genes. These are considered "Lamarckian" in the sense that they are responsive to environmental stimuli and can differentially affect gene expression adaptively, with phenotypic results that can persist for many generations in certain organisms.<ref name=Jablonka>[[Eva Jablonka]], [[Marion J. Lamb]]. (1995). ''Epigenetic Inheritance and Evolution: The Lamarckian Dimension''. Oxford University Press.{{pn}}</ref> In 2008, Jablonka and Lamb published a paper which claimed there is evidence for Lamarckian epigenetic control systems causing evolutionary changes and the mechanisms underlying epigenetic inheritance can also lead to [[Saltation (biology)|saltational]] changes that reorganize the epigenome.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1590/S1415-47572008000300001}}</ref>


Interest in Lamarckism has increased, as studies in the field of [[epigenetics]] have highlighted the possible inheritance of behavioral traits acquired by the previous generation. A 2009 study examined foraging behavior in chickens as a function of stress,<ref name="plosone.org">{{cite web|url=http://www.plosone.org/article/info:doi/10.1371/journal.pone.0006405 |title=Inheritance of Acquired Behaviour Adaptations and Brain Gene Expression in Chickens |publisher=Plos One |date= |accessdate=2011-04-12}}</ref> concluding:<blockquote>Our findings suggest that unpredictable food access caused seemingly adaptive responses in feeding behavior, which may have been transmitted to the offspring by means of epigenetic mechanisms, including regulation of immune genes. This may have prepared the offspring for coping with an unpredictable environment.... Transmissions of information across generations which does not involve traditional inheritance of DNA-sequence alleles is often referred to as soft inheritance <ref>Richards EJ (2006) Inherited epigenetic variation–revisiting soft inheritance" ''Nat Rev Genet'' 7(5) 395–401.</ref> or 'Lamarckian inheritance'.<ref name="plosone.org"/></blockquote>
Interest in Lamarckism has increased, as studies in the field of [[epigenetics]] have highlighted the possible inheritance of behavioral traits acquired by the previous generation. A 2009 study examined foraging behavior in chickens as a function of stress,<ref name="plosone.org">{{cite journal |doi=10.1371/journal.pone.0006405}}</ref> concluding:<blockquote>Our findings suggest that unpredictable food access caused seemingly adaptive responses in feeding behavior, which may have been transmitted to the offspring by means of epigenetic mechanisms, including regulation of immune genes. This may have prepared the offspring for coping with an unpredictable environment.... Transmissions of information across generations which does not involve traditional inheritance of DNA-sequence alleles is often referred to as soft inheritance <ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1038/nrg1834}}</ref> or 'Lamarckian inheritance'.<ref name="plosone.org"/></blockquote>


The evolution of acquired characteristics has also been shown in human populations who have experienced starvation, resulting in altered gene function in both the starved population and their offspring.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://cat.inist.fr/?aModele=afficheN&cpsidt=3596539 |title=Timing of prenatal starvation in women and birth weight in their first and second born offspring : the Dutch famine birth cohort study |publisher=Cat.inist.fr |date= |accessdate=2011-04-12}}</ref> The process of [[DNA methylation]] is thought to be behind such changes.
The evolution of acquired characteristics has also been shown in human populations who have experienced starvation, resulting in altered gene function in both the starved population and their offspring.<ref>{{cite journal |id={{INIST|3596539}} |doi=10.1016/0028-2243(95)02149-M}}</ref> The process of [[DNA methylation]] is thought to be behind such changes.


In October 2010, further evidence linking food intake to traits inherited by the offspring were shown in a study of rats conducted by several Australian universities.<ref>{{cite web|author=Ng SF, Lin R, Laybutt DR, Barres R, Owens JA, Morris MJ |url=http://www.nature.com/nature/journal/v467/n7318/full/nature09491.html |title=Chronic high-fat diet in fathers programs [bgr&#93;-cell dysfunction in female rat offspring : Nature : Nature Publishing Group |publisher=Nature |date= |accessdate=2011-04-12}}</ref> The study strongly suggested that fathers can transfer a propensity for obesity to their daughters as a result of the fathers' food intake, and not their genetics (or specific genes), prior to the conception of the daughter. A "paternal high-fat diet" was shown to cause cell dysfunction in the daughter, which in turn led to obesity for the daughter. Felicia Nowak, et al. reported at The Endocrine Society meeting in June 2013 that obese male rats passed on the tendency to obesity to their male offspring.<ref>[http://www.ohio.edu/research/communications/obese_paternal.cfm Obese male mice father offspring with higher levels of body fat]</ref>
In October 2010, further evidence linking food intake to traits inherited by the offspring were shown in a study of rats conducted by several Australian universities.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1038/nature09491}}</ref> The study strongly suggested that fathers can transfer a propensity for obesity to their daughters as a result of the fathers' food intake, and not their genetics (or specific genes), prior to the conception of the daughter. A "paternal high-fat diet" was shown to cause cell dysfunction in the daughter, which in turn led to obesity for the daughter. Felicia Nowak, et al. reported at The Endocrine Society meeting in June 2013 that obese male rats passed on the tendency to obesity to their male offspring.<ref>[http://www.ohio.edu/research/communications/obese_paternal.cfm Obese male mice father offspring with higher levels of body fat]</ref>


Several studies, one conducted by researchers at MIT and another by researchers at the Tufts University School of Medicine, have rekindled the debate once again. As [http://www.technologyreview.com/biomedicine/22061 reported] in MIT's Technology Review in February 2009, "The effects of an animal's environment during adolescence can be passed down to future offspring ... The findings provide support for a 200-year-old theory of evolution that has been largely dismissed: Lamarckian evolution, which states that acquired characteristics can be passed on to offspring." A report investigating the inheritance of resistance to viral infection in the [[nematode]] ''[[Caenorhabditis elegans]]'' suggests that small RNA molecules may be inherited in a non Mendelian fashion and provide resistance to infection.<ref name=Rechavi2011>Rechavi O, Minevich G, Hobert O. (2011). [http://www.aipro.info/drive/File/11_CELL_Transgenerational_Inheritance.._Acquired_Small_RNA%5B1%5D.pdf ''Transgenerational inheritance of an acquired small RNA-Based antiviral response in ''C. elegans'']. ''Cell'' 147(6) 1248-1256.</ref>
Several studies, one conducted by researchers at MIT and another by researchers at the Tufts University School of Medicine, have rekindled the debate once again. As reported in MIT's Technology Review in February 2009, "The effects of an animal's environment during adolescence can be passed down to future offspring ... The findings provide support for a 200-year-old theory of evolution that has been largely dismissed: Lamarckian evolution, which states that acquired characteristics can be passed on to offspring."<ref>http://www.technologyreview.com/biomedicine/22061{{full}}</ref> A report investigating the inheritance of resistance to viral infection in the [[nematode]] ''[[Caenorhabditis elegans]]'' suggests that small RNA molecules may be inherited in a non Mendelian fashion and provide resistance to infection.<ref name=Rechavi2011>{{cite journal |doi=10.1016/j.cell.2011.10.042}}</ref>


A scientific study (Akimoto ''et al''. 2007) on epigenetic inheritance in [[Rice|rice plant]]s came to the conclusion that "gene expression is flexibly tuned by [[methylation]], allowing plants to gain or lose particular traits which are heritable as far as methylation patterns of corresponding genes are maintained. This is in support of the concept of Lamarckian inheritance, suggesting that acquired traits are heritable."<ref>K. Akimoto, H. Katakami, H.-J. Kim, E. Ogawa, C.M. Sano, Y. Wada, H. Sano. (2007). ''Epigenetic inheritance in rice plants''. Ann. Bot. 100, 205–217.</ref> Another study (Sano, 2010) wrote that observations suggest that acquired traits are heritable in plants as far as the acquired methylation pattern is stably transmitted which is consistent with Lamarckian evolution.<ref>Sano, H. (2010). [http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2958583/ ''Inheritance of acquired traits in plants: reinstatement of Lamarck'']. Plant Signal Behav 5: 346–348.</ref> Handel and Ramagopalan, 2010 have written that there is evidence that epigenetic alterations such as [[DNA methylation]] and [[Histone|histone modifications]], are transmitted transgenerationally as a mechanism for environmental influences to be passed from parents to offspring. According to Handel and Romagopalan "epigenetics allows the peaceful co-existence of Darwinian and Lamarckian evolution."<ref>Handel, A.E., Ramagopalan, S.V. (2010). ''[http://www.biomedcentral.com/1471-2350/11/73 Is Lamarckian evolution relevant to medicine?]''. BMC Med. Genet., 11, 73.</ref>
A scientific study (Akimoto ''et al''. 2007) on epigenetic inheritance in [[Rice|rice plant]]s came to the conclusion that "gene expression is flexibly tuned by [[methylation]], allowing plants to gain or lose particular traits which are heritable as far as methylation patterns of corresponding genes are maintained. This is in support of the concept of Lamarckian inheritance, suggesting that acquired traits are heritable."<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1093/aob/mcm110}}</ref> Another study (Sano, 2010) wrote that observations suggest that acquired traits are heritable in plants as far as the acquired methylation pattern is stably transmitted which is consistent with Lamarckian evolution.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.4161/psb.5.4.10803}}</ref> Handel and Ramagopalan, 2010 have written that there is evidence that epigenetic alterations such as [[DNA methylation]] and [[Histone|histone modifications]], are transmitted transgenerationally as a mechanism for environmental influences to be passed from parents to offspring. According to Handel and Romagopalan "epigenetics allows the peaceful co-existence of Darwinian and Lamarckian evolution."<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1186/1471-2350-11-73}}</ref>


In their book ''An Introduction to Zoology'' (2012) Joseph Springer and Dennis Holley wrote:
In their book ''An Introduction to Zoology'' (2012) Joseph Springer and Dennis Holley wrote:
Line 109: Line 109:
<blockquote>Lamarck and his ideas were ridiculed and discredited. In a strange twist of fate, Lamarck may have the last laugh. Epigenetics, an emerging field of genetics, has shown that Lamarck may have been at least partially correct all along. It seems that reversible and heritable changes can occur without a change in DNA sequence (genotype) and that such changes may be induced spontaneously or in response to environmental factors - Lamarck's "acquired traits". Determining which observed phenotypes are genetically inherited and which are environmentally induced remains an important and on going part of the study of genetics, developmental biology, and medicine.<ref>Joseph Springer, Dennis Holley. (2012). ''An Introduction to Zoology''. Jones & Bartlett Learning. p. 94</ref></blockquote>
<blockquote>Lamarck and his ideas were ridiculed and discredited. In a strange twist of fate, Lamarck may have the last laugh. Epigenetics, an emerging field of genetics, has shown that Lamarck may have been at least partially correct all along. It seems that reversible and heritable changes can occur without a change in DNA sequence (genotype) and that such changes may be induced spontaneously or in response to environmental factors - Lamarck's "acquired traits". Determining which observed phenotypes are genetically inherited and which are environmentally induced remains an important and on going part of the study of genetics, developmental biology, and medicine.<ref>Joseph Springer, Dennis Holley. (2012). ''An Introduction to Zoology''. Jones & Bartlett Learning. p. 94</ref></blockquote>


[[Eugene Koonin]] has written that the prokaryotic [[CRISPR]] system and [[Piwi-interacting RNA]] could be classified as Lamarckian and came to the conclusion "Both Darwinian and Lamarckian modalities of evolution appear to be important, and reflect different aspects of the interaction between populations and the environment."<ref> Koonin, E. V., and Y. I. Wolf. (2009). [http://www.biologydirect.com/content/4/1/42 ''Is Evolution Darwinian or/and Lamarckian?'']. Biology Direct 4: 42.</ref>
[[Eugene Koonin]] has written that the prokaryotic [[CRISPR]] system and [[Piwi-interacting RNA]] could be classified as Lamarckian and came to the conclusion "Both Darwinian and Lamarckian modalities of evolution appear to be important, and reflect different aspects of the interaction between populations and the environment."<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1186/1745-6150-4-42}}</ref>


A study in 2013 reported that [[mutation]]s caused by a father's lifestyle can be inherited by his children through multiple generations.<ref>J. O. Linschooten, N. Verhofstad, K. Gutzkow, A.-K. Olsen, C. Yauk, Y. Oligschlager, G. Brunborg, F. J. van Schooten, R. W. L. Godschalk. (2013). ''Paternal lifestyle as a potential source of germline mutations transmitted to offspring''. FASEB J. 27 (7): 2873-2879.</ref><ref>[http://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2013/07/130701135550.htm Gene Mutations Caused by a Father's Lifestyle Can Be Inherited by Multiple Generations]</ref> A Swedish study showed that exercise changes the epigenetic pattern of genes that affect fat storage in the body.<ref>{{cite journal|url=http://www.plosgenetics.org/article/info:doi/10.1371/journal.pgen.1003572|title=A Six Months Exercise Intervention Influences the Genome-wide DNA Methylation Pattern in Human Adipose Tissue|author1=Tina Rönn|author2= Petr Volkov|author3= Cajsa Davegårdh|author4= Tasnim Dayeh|author5= Elin Hall|author6= Anders H. Olsson|author7= Emma Nilsson|author8= Åsa Tornberg|author9= Marloes Dekker Nitert|author10=Karl-Fredrik Eriksson|author11= Helena A. Jones|author12= Leif Groop|author13= Charlotte Ling|date= June 27, 2013|doi=10.1371/journal.pgen.1003572}}</ref><ref name=ScienceDaily>{{cite web|url=http://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2013/07/130703101344.htm|title=Epigenetic Changes to Fat Cells Following Exercise|date=July 3, 2013|work=Science News|publisher=[http://www.sciencedaily.com sciencedaily.com]}}</ref>
A study in 2013 reported that [[mutation]]s caused by a father's lifestyle can be inherited by his children through multiple generations.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1096/fj.13-227694 |layurl=http://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2013/07/130701135550.htm |laysource=ScienceDaily |laydate=July 1, 2013}}</ref> A Swedish study showed that exercise changes the epigenetic pattern of genes that affect fat storage in the body.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1371/journal.pgen.1003572 |layurl=http://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2013/07/130703101344.htm |laysource=ScienceDaily |laydate=July 3, 2013}}</ref>


Commenting on this, ''[[Science Daily]]'' explained,
Commenting on this, ''[[Science Daily]]'' explained,
Line 117: Line 117:
{{quote|The cells of the body contain DNA, which contains genes. We inherit our genes and they cannot be changed. The genes, however, have 'methyl groups' attached which affect what is known as 'gene expression' -- whether the genes are activated or deactivated. The methyl groups can be influenced in various ways, through exercise, diet and lifestyle, in a process known as 'DNA methylation'.<ref name=ScienceDaily />}}
{{quote|The cells of the body contain DNA, which contains genes. We inherit our genes and they cannot be changed. The genes, however, have 'methyl groups' attached which affect what is known as 'gene expression' -- whether the genes are activated or deactivated. The methyl groups can be influenced in various ways, through exercise, diet and lifestyle, in a process known as 'DNA methylation'.<ref name=ScienceDaily />}}


A 2013 study in ''[[Nature (journal)|Nature]]'' reported that mice trained to fear the smell of a chemical called [[acetophenone]] passed their fear onto at least two generations.<ref>Brian G. Dias, Kerry J. Ressler. (2013). [http://www.nature.com/neuro/journal/vaop/ncurrent/full/nn.3594.html ''Parental olfactory experience influences behavior and neural structure in subsequent generations'']. Nature.</ref><ref>[http://www.nature.com/news/fearful-memories-haunt-mouse-descendants-1.14272 Fearful memories haunt mouse descendants]. Nature.</ref><ref>[http://www.newscientist.com/article/dn24677-fear-of-a-smell-can-be-passed-down-several-generations.html#.UqS-08-YbIU Fear of a smell can be passed down several generations] New Scientist.</ref> An article on the study in the ''[[New Scientist]]'' titled ''Mouse memory inheritance may revitalise Lamarckism'' wrote "While it needs to be corroborated, this finding seems consistent with Lamarckian inheritance. It is, however, based on epigenetics: changes that tweak the action of genes, not the genes themselves. So it fits with natural selection – and may yet give Lamarck's name a sheen of respectability."<ref>[http://www.newscientist.com/article/mg22029461.700-mouse-memory-inheritance-may-revitalise-lamarckism.html#.UqS5ws-YbIU Mouse memory inheritance may revitalise Lamarckism]. New Scientist.</ref>
A 2013 study in ''[[Nature (journal)|Nature]]'' reported that mice trained to fear the smell of a chemical called [[acetophenone]] passed their fear onto at least two generations.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1038/nn.3594 |layurl=http://www.newscientist.com/article/dn24677-fear-of-a-smell-can-be-passed-down-several-generations.html |laysource=New Scientist |laydate=December 1, 2013}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1038/nature.2013.14272}}</ref> An article on the study in the ''[[New Scientist]]'' titled ''Mouse memory inheritance may revitalise Lamarckism'' wrote "While it needs to be corroborated, this finding seems consistent with Lamarckian inheritance. It is, however, based on epigenetics: changes that tweak the action of genes, not the genes themselves. So it fits with natural selection – and may yet give Lamarck's name a sheen of respectability."<ref>{{cite news |url=http://www.newscientist.com/article/mg22029461.700-mouse-memory-inheritance-may-revitalise-lamarckism.html |title=Mouse memory inheritance may revitalise Lamarckism |work=New Scientist |date=4 December 2013}}</ref>


Guy Barry in a neuroscience paper in 2013 has written Darwin's hypothesis [[pangenesis]] coupled with "Lamarckian somatic cell-derived epigenetic modifications" and de novo RNA and DNA mutations can explain the evolution of the [[human brain]].<ref>Guy Barry. (2013). [http://www.frontiersin.org/Journal/10.3389/fnins.2013.00224/full ''Lamarckian evolution explains human brain evolution and psychiatric disorders'']. Front. Neurosci. 7: 224.</ref>
Guy Barry in a neuroscience paper in 2013 has written Darwin's hypothesis [[pangenesis]] coupled with "Lamarckian somatic cell-derived epigenetic modifications" and de novo RNA and DNA mutations can explain the evolution of the [[human brain]].<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.3389/fnins.2013.00224}}</ref>


Lamarckian elements also appear in the [[hologenome theory of evolution]].
Lamarckian elements also appear in the [[hologenome theory of evolution]].
Line 127: Line 127:
The botanist Conway Zirkle (1946) pointed out that Lamarck did not originate the hypothesis that [[Inheritance of acquired characteristics|acquired characters were heritable]], therefore it is incorrect to refer to it as Lamarckism:
The botanist Conway Zirkle (1946) pointed out that Lamarck did not originate the hypothesis that [[Inheritance of acquired characteristics|acquired characters were heritable]], therefore it is incorrect to refer to it as Lamarckism:


<blockquote>What Lamarck really did was to accept the hypothesis that acquired characters were heritable, a notion which had been held almost universally for well over two thousand years and which his contemporaries accepted as a matter of course, and to assume that the results of such inheritance were cumulative from generation to generation, thus producing, in time, new species. His individual contribution to biological theory consisted in his application to the problem of the origin of species of the view that acquired characters were inherited and in showing that evolution could be inferred logically from the accepted biological hypotheses. He would doubtless have been greatly astonished to learn that a belief in the inheritance of acquired characters is now labeled “Lamarckian,” although he would almost certainly have felt flattered if evolution itself had been so designated.<ref>Conway Zirkle. (1946). ''The Early History of the Idea of the Inheritance of Acquired Characters and of Pangenesis''. Transactions of the American Philosophical Society. New Series, Vol. 35, No. 2. pp. 91-151.</ref></blockquote>
<blockquote>What Lamarck really did was to accept the hypothesis that acquired characters were heritable, a notion which had been held almost universally for well over two thousand years and which his contemporaries accepted as a matter of course, and to assume that the results of such inheritance were cumulative from generation to generation, thus producing, in time, new species. His individual contribution to biological theory consisted in his application to the problem of the origin of species of the view that acquired characters were inherited and in showing that evolution could be inferred logically from the accepted biological hypotheses. He would doubtless have been greatly astonished to learn that a belief in the inheritance of acquired characters is now labeled “Lamarckian,” although he would almost certainly have felt flattered if evolution itself had been so designated.<ref>{{cite journal |first=Conway |last=Zirkle |month=January |year=1946 |title=The Early History of the Idea of the Inheritance of Acquired Characters and of Pangenesis |journal=Transactions of the American Philosophical Society |volume=35 |issue=2 |pages=91-151 |jstor=1005592}}</ref></blockquote>


The evolutionary biologist [[T. Ryan Gregory]] has written [[Epigenetics|epigenetic inheritance]] should not be considered "Lamarckian". According to Gregory; Lamarck did not claim the environment imposed direct effects on organisms, instead Lamarck "argued that the environment created needs to which organisms responded by using some features more and others less, that this resulted in those features being accentuated or attenuated, and that this difference was then inherited by offspring." Gregory has stated that "Lamarckian" evolution in the context of epigenetics is actually closer to the view held by Darwin rather than by Lamarck.<ref>[[T. Ryan Gregory]]. (2008). [http://www.genomicron.evolverzone.com/2009/03/lamarck-didnt-say-it-darwin-did/ ''Lamarck didn’t say it, Darwin did'']. Evolver Zone.</ref>
The evolutionary biologist [[T. Ryan Gregory]] has written [[Epigenetics|epigenetic inheritance]] should not be considered "Lamarckian". According to Gregory; Lamarck did not claim the environment imposed direct effects on organisms, instead Lamarck "argued that the environment created needs to which organisms responded by using some features more and others less, that this resulted in those features being accentuated or attenuated, and that this difference was then inherited by offspring." Gregory has stated that "Lamarckian" evolution in the context of epigenetics is actually closer to the view held by Darwin rather than by Lamarck.<ref>[[T. Ryan Gregory]]. (2008). [http://www.genomicron.evolverzone.com/2009/03/lamarck-didnt-say-it-darwin-did/ ''Lamarck didn’t say it, Darwin did'']. Evolver Zone.{{rs}}</ref>


Although the reality of epigenetic inheritance is not doubted (as many experiments have validated it), its significance to the evolutionary process is uncertain. Most neo-Darwinians consider epigenetic inheritance modifications to not be inherited past one or two generations, so are not a stable basis for evolutionary change.<ref>[[Jerry Coyne]]. (2010). [http://whyevolutionistrue.wordpress.com/2010/10/24/epigenetics-the-light-and-the-way/ ''Epigenetics: the light and the way?'']. Why Evolution is True.</ref><ref>[[Jerry Coyne]]. (2013). [http://whyevolutionistrue.wordpress.com/2013/09/23/epigenetics-smackdown-at-the-guardian/ ''Epigenetics smackdown at the Guardian'']. Why Evolution is True.</ref>
Although the reality of epigenetic inheritance is not doubted (as many experiments have validated it), its significance to the evolutionary process is uncertain. Most neo-Darwinians consider epigenetic inheritance modifications to not be inherited past one or two generations, so are not a stable basis for evolutionary change.<ref>[[Jerry Coyne]]. (2010). [http://whyevolutionistrue.wordpress.com/2010/10/24/epigenetics-the-light-and-the-way/ ''Epigenetics: the light and the way?'']. Why Evolution is True.{{rs}}</ref><ref>[[Jerry Coyne]]. (2013). [http://whyevolutionistrue.wordpress.com/2013/09/23/epigenetics-smackdown-at-the-guardian/ ''Epigenetics smackdown at the Guardian'']. Why Evolution is True.{{rs}}</ref>


In a paper titled ''Weismann Rules! Epigenetics and the Lamarckian Temptation'' (2007), [[David Haig (biologist)|David Haig]] writes that research into epigenetic processes does allow a Lamarckian element in evolutionary theory but the processes do not challenge the main tenets of the [[modern evolutionary synthesis]] like modern Lamarckians have claimed. Haig argued for the primary of DNA and evolution of epigenetic switches by natural selection.<ref>[[David Haig (biologist)|David Haig]]. (2007). [http://www.oeb.harvard.edu/faculty/haig/publications_files/07Weismann.pdf ''Weismann Rules! OK? Epigenetics and the Lamarckian temptation'']. Biol. Philos. 22: 415-428. "Modern neo-Darwinists do not deny that epigenetic mechanisms play an important role during development nor do they deny that these mechanisms enable a variety of adaptive responses to the environment. Recurrent, predictable changes of epigenetic state provide a useful set of switches that allow genetically-identical cells to acquire differentiated functions and allow facultative responses of a genotype to environmental changes (provided that ‘similar’ changes have occurred repeatedly in the past). However, most neo-Darwinists would claim that the ability to adaptively switch epigenetic state is a property of the DNA sequence (in the sense that alternative sequences would show different switching behavior) and that any increase of adaptedness in the system has come about by a process of natural selection."</ref> Haig has also written there is a "visceral attraction" to Lamarckian evolution from the public and some scientists as it posits the world with a meaning, in which organisms can shape their own evolutionary destiny.<ref>[[David Haig (biologist)|David Haig]]. (2011). [http://quod.lib.umich.edu/p/ptb/6959004.0003.004/--lamarck-ascending?rgn=main;view=fulltext ''Lamarck Ascending!'']. Philosophy & Theory in Biology.</ref>
In a paper titled ''Weismann Rules! Epigenetics and the Lamarckian Temptation'' (2007), [[David Haig (biologist)|David Haig]] writes that research into epigenetic processes does allow a Lamarckian element in evolutionary theory but the processes do not challenge the main tenets of the [[modern evolutionary synthesis]] like modern Lamarckians have claimed. Haig argued for the primary of DNA and evolution of epigenetic switches by natural selection.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1007/s10539-006-9033-y |quote=Modern neo-Darwinists do not deny that epigenetic mechanisms play an important role during development nor do they deny that these mechanisms enable a variety of adaptive responses to the environment. Recurrent, predictable changes of epigenetic state provide a useful set of switches that allow genetically-identical cells to acquire differentiated functions and allow facultative responses of a genotype to environmental changes (provided that 'similar' changes have occurred repeatedly in the past). However, most neo-Darwinists would claim that the ability to adaptively switch epigenetic state is a property of the DNA sequence (in the sense that alternative sequences would show different switching behavior) and that any increase of adaptedness in the system has come about by a process of natural selection.}}</ref> Haig has also written there is a "visceral attraction" to Lamarckian evolution from the public and some scientists as it posits the world with a meaning, in which organisms can shape their own evolutionary destiny.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.3998/ptb.6959004.0003.004}}</ref>


In 2009, [[Douglas J. Futuyma|Douglas Futuyma]] wrote "There is no evidence yet that epigenetic variation contributes to evolutionary change, and considerable difference of opinion on whether or not it is likely to do so."<ref>[[Douglas J. Futuyma|Douglas Futuyma]]. (2009). ''Evolution''. Sinauer Associates.</ref>
In 2009, [[Douglas J. Futuyma|Douglas Futuyma]] wrote "There is no evidence yet that epigenetic variation contributes to evolutionary change, and considerable difference of opinion on whether or not it is likely to do so."<ref>[[Douglas J. Futuyma|Douglas Futuyma]]. (2009). ''Evolution''. Sinauer Associates.{{pn}}</ref>


Thomas Dickens and Qazi Rahman have written epigenetic mechanisms such as [[DNA methylation]] and histone modification are genetically inherited under the control of natural selection and do not challenge the modern synthesis. Dickens and Rahman have taken issue with the claims of [[Eva Jablonka]] and [[Marion J. Lamb|Marion Lamb]] on Lamarckian epigenetic processes.<ref>Thomas Dickens, Qazi Rahman. (2012). [http://rspb.royalsocietypublishing.org/content/early/2012/05/10/rspb.2012.0273.full ''The extended evolutionary synthesis and the role of soft inheritance in evolution'']. Proceedings of the Royal Society: B biological sciences, 279 (1740). pp. 2913-2921.</ref>
Thomas Dickens and Qazi Rahman have written epigenetic mechanisms such as [[DNA methylation]] and histone modification are genetically inherited under the control of natural selection and do not challenge the modern synthesis. Dickens and Rahman have taken issue with the claims of [[Eva Jablonka]] and [[Marion J. Lamb|Marion Lamb]] on Lamarckian epigenetic processes.<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1098/rspb.2012.0273}}</ref>


[[Jerry Coyne]] has written that "lots of studies show us that Lamarckian inheritance doesn’t operate" and epigenetic changes are rarely passed on to future generations, thus do not serve as the basis of evolutionary change.<ref>[[Jerry Coyne]]. (2013). [http://whyevolutionistrue.wordpress.com/2013/01/12/more-puffery-about-epigenetics-and-my-usual-role-as-go-to-curmudgeon/ ''More puffery about epigenetics, and my usual role as go-to curmudgeon'']. Why Evolution is True.</ref>
[[Jerry Coyne]] has written that "lots of studies show us that Lamarckian inheritance doesn’t operate" and epigenetic changes are rarely passed on to future generations, thus do not serve as the basis of evolutionary change.<ref>[[Jerry Coyne]]. (2013). [http://whyevolutionistrue.wordpress.com/2013/01/12/more-puffery-about-epigenetics-and-my-usual-role-as-go-to-curmudgeon/ ''More puffery about epigenetics, and my usual role as go-to curmudgeon'']. Why Evolution is True.{{rs}}</ref>


==See also==
==See also==
Line 165: Line 165:
==Further reading==
==Further reading==
*Burkeman, Oliver. [http://www.guardian.co.uk/science/2010/mar/19/evolution-darwin-natural-selection-genes-wrong ''Why everything you've been told about evolution is wrong'']. ''The Guardian'', March 19, 2010.
*Burkeman, Oliver. [http://www.guardian.co.uk/science/2010/mar/19/evolution-darwin-natural-selection-genes-wrong ''Why everything you've been told about evolution is wrong'']. ''The Guardian'', March 19, 2010.
*Cook, George. (1999). [http://www.jstor.org/stable/2664721 ''Neo–Lamarckian Experimentalism in America: Origins and Consequences'']. Quarterly Review of Biology. 74: 417–437.
*{{cite journal |first=George M. |last=Cook |month=December |year=1999 |title=Neo-Lamarckian Experimentalism in America: Origins and Consequences |journal=The Quarterly Review of Biology |volume=74 |issue=4 |pages=417-37 |jstor=2664721}}
*{{cite journal |doi=10.1017/S0025315400050761}}
*Cunningham, Joseph Thomas. (1895). [http://sabella.mba.ac.uk/146/01/Additional_evidence_on_the_influence_of_light_in_producing_pigments_on_the_lower_sides_of_flat_fishes.pdf ''Additional Evidence on the Influence of Light in producing Pigments on the Lower Sides of Flat Fishes'']. J. Mar. Bio. Assoc. U.K. 4 (N.S): 53-59.
*{{cite book |last=Desmond |first=Adrian |title=The Politics of Evolution: Morphology, Medicine, and Reform in Radical London|year= 1989 |publisher= University of Chicago Press |location=Chicago |isbn=0-226-14374-0}}
*{{cite book |last=Desmond |first=Adrian |title=The Politics of Evolution: Morphology, Medicine, and Reform in Radical London|year= 1989 |publisher= University of Chicago Press |location=Chicago |isbn=0-226-14374-0}}
* {{cite book |last=Gould |first=Stephen J. |title= [[The Structure of Evolutionary Theory]]|year= 2002 |publisher= Belknap Harvard |location=Harvard|isbn= 0-674-00613-5 | pages=170–197 on Lamarck}}
* {{cite book |last=Gould |first=Stephen J. |title= [[The Structure of Evolutionary Theory]]|year= 2002 |publisher= Belknap Harvard |location=Harvard|isbn= 0-674-00613-5 | pages=170–197 on Lamarck}}
* Medawar, Peter (1959). "The threat and the glory". BBC [[Reith Lectures]] No. 6.
* Medawar, Peter (1959). "The threat and the glory". BBC [[Reith Lectures]] No. 6.
* Molino, Jean (2000). ''Toward an Evolutionary Theory of Music and Language''. In Brown, Merker & Wallin (Eds.). ''The Origins of Music''. ISBN 0-262-23206-5.
*{{cite book |last=Molino |first=Jean |year=2001 |chapter=Toward an Evolutionary Theory of Music and Language |chapterurl=http://books.google.com/books?id=vYQEakqM4I0C&pg=PA165 |pages=165–76 |editor1-last=Wallin |editor1-first=Nils L. |editor2-last=Merker |editor2-first=Björn |editor3-last=Brown |editor3-first=Steven |title=The Origins of Music |location=Cambridge |publisher=The MIT Press |isbn=978-0-262-73143-0}}
* Waddington, Conrad. (1961). "The human evolutionary system". In: Michael Banton (Ed.), ''Darwinism and the Study of Society''. London: Tavistock.
* Waddington, Conrad. (1961). "The human evolutionary system". In: Michael Banton (Ed.), ''Darwinism and the Study of Society''. London: Tavistock.
*{{cite journal |doi=10.1002/hep.26240}}
*Yoshiyuki, Seki. (2013). [http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/hep.26240/abstract ''Serum-Mediated Transgenerational Effects on Sperm: Evidence for Lamarckian Inheritance?'']. Hepatology. Volume 57, Issue 4: 1663–1665.
* Honeywill, Ross (2008). ''Lamarck's Evolution: two centuries of genius and jealousy''. Murdoch Books, Sydney [http://lamarcksevolution.com/ See website]
* Honeywill, Ross (2008). ''Lamarck's Evolution: two centuries of genius and jealousy''. Murdoch Books, Sydney [http://lamarcksevolution.com/ See website]
*Fecht, Sarah. (2011). [http://www.scientificamerican.com/article.cfm?id=longevity-inheritance-epigenetics ''Longevity Shown for First Time to Be Inherited via a Non-DNA Mechanism'']. Scientific American.
*Fecht, Sarah. (2011). [http://www.scientificamerican.com/article.cfm?id=longevity-inheritance-epigenetics ''Longevity Shown for First Time to Be Inherited via a Non-DNA Mechanism'']. Scientific American.
Line 178: Line 178:
*Jablonka, Eva. Lamb, Marion. (2008). [http://www.bionet.nsc.ru/vogis/pict_pdf/2008/t12_1_2/vogis_12_1_2_21.pdf ''The Epigenome in Evolution: Beyond The Modern Synthesis'']. VOGis Herald. Volume 12: 242–254.
*Jablonka, Eva. Lamb, Marion. (2008). [http://www.bionet.nsc.ru/vogis/pict_pdf/2008/t12_1_2/vogis_12_1_2_21.pdf ''The Epigenome in Evolution: Beyond The Modern Synthesis'']. VOGis Herald. Volume 12: 242–254.
*Persell, Stuart. (1999). ''Neo-Lamarckism and the evolution controversy in France, 1870-1920''. Edwin Mellen Press.
*Persell, Stuart. (1999). ''Neo-Lamarckism and the evolution controversy in France, 1870-1920''. Edwin Mellen Press.
*{{cite journal |doi=10.1534/genetics.113.151852}}
*Burkhardt, Richard. (2013). [http://www.genetics.org/content/194/4/793.short ''Lamarck, Evolution, and the Inheritance of Acquired Characters'']. Volume 194: 793-805.
*Burkhardt, Richard. (1995). ''The Spirit of System: Lamarck and Evolutionary Biology''. Harvard University Press.
*Burkhardt, Richard. (1995). ''The Spirit of System: Lamarck and Evolutionary Biology''. Harvard University Press.
*Madaule, Madeleine Barthélemy. (1982). ''Lamarck, the Mythical Precursor''. Mit Press.
*Madaule, Madeleine Barthélemy. (1982). ''Lamarck, the Mythical Precursor''. Mit Press.
*{{cite journal |doi=10.1038/sj.embor.7401060}}
*Liu, Yongsheng. (2007). [http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1973965/ ''Like father like son: a fresh review of the inheritance of acquired characteristics'']. ''EMBO Reports'' 8: 798-803.
*Gissis, Snait. Jablonka, Eva. Zeligowski, Anna. (2011). ''Transformations of Lamarckism: From Subtle Fluids to Molecular Biology''. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0262015141
*Gissis, Snait. Jablonka, Eva. Zeligowski, Anna. (2011). ''Transformations of Lamarckism: From Subtle Fluids to Molecular Biology''. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0262015141
*{{cite journal |doi=10.1038/ng.1062}}
*Peng, Wayne. (2012). [http://www.nature.com/ng/journal/v44/n1/full/ng.1062.html ''Lamarckian viral defense in worms'']. Nature Genetics. Volume 44: 15.
*{{cite journal |doi=10.1126/science.341.6150.1055}}
*Pennisi, Elizabeth. (2013). [http://www.sciencemag.org/content/341/6150/1055.summary ''Evolution Heresy? Epigenetics Underlies Heritable Plant Traits'']. Science Magazine.


==External links==
==External links==

Revision as of 14:39, 27 December 2013

Lamarckism (or Lamarckian inheritance) is the idea that an organism can pass on characteristics that it acquired during its lifetime to its offspring (also known as heritability of acquired characteristics or soft inheritance). It is named after the French biologist Jean-Baptiste Lamarck (1744–1829), who incorporated the action of soft inheritance into his evolutionary theories as a supplement to his concept of an inherent progressive tendency driving organisms continuously towards greater complexity, in parallel but separate lineages with no extinction. Lamarck did not originate the idea of soft inheritance, which proposes that individual efforts during the lifetime of the organisms were the main mechanism driving species to adaptation, as they supposedly would acquire adaptive changes and pass them on to offspring. Template:Evolution theories When Charles Darwin published his theory of evolution by natural selection in On the Origin of Species, he continued to give credence to what he called "use and disuse inheritance", but rejected other aspects of Lamarck's theories. Later, Mendelian genetics supplanted the notion of inheritance of acquired traits, eventually leading to the development of the modern evolutionary synthesis, and the general abandonment of the Lamarckian theory of evolution in biology. Despite this abandonment, interest in Lamarckism has continued (2009) as studies in the field of epigenetics have highlighted the possible inheritance of behavioral traits acquired by the previous generation.Cite error: The <ref> tag has too many names (see the help page).[1]

History

Jean-Baptiste Lamarck

Between 1794 and 1796 Erasmus Darwin wrote Zoonomia suggesting "that all warm-blooded animals have arisen from one living filament... with the power of acquiring new parts" in response to stimuli, with each round of "improvements" being inherited by successive generations. Subsequently Jean-Baptiste Lamarck repeated in his Philosophie Zoologique of 1809 the folk wisdom that characteristics which were "needed" were acquired (or diminished) during the lifetime of an organism then passed on to the offspring. He incorporated this mechanism into his thoughts on evolution, seeing it as resulting in the adaptation of life to local environments.

Lamarck founded a school of French Transformationism which included Étienne Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire, and which corresponded with a radical British school of anatomy based in the extramural anatomy schools in Edinburgh which included the surgeon Robert Knox and the comparative anatomist Robert Edmund Grant. In addition, the Regius Professor of Natural History, Robert Jameson, was the probable author of an anonymous paper in 1826 praising "Mr. Lamarck" for explaining how the higher animals had "evolved" from the "simplest worms" – this was the first use of the word "evolved" in a modern sense. As a young student, Charles Darwin was tutored by Grant, and worked with him on marine creatures.

The Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation, authored by Robert Chambers in St Andrews and published anonymously in England in 1844, proposed a theory which combined radical phrenology with Lamarckism, causing political controversy for its radicalism and unorthodoxy, but exciting popular interest and preparing a huge and prosperous audience for Darwin.

Darwin's Origin of Species proposed natural selection as the main mechanism for development of species, but did not rule out a variant of Lamarckism as a supplementary mechanism.[2] Darwin called his Lamarckian hypothesis Pangenesis, and explained it in the final chapter of his book Variation in Plants and Animals under Domestication, after describing numerous examples to demonstrate what he considered to be the inheritance of acquired characteristics. Pangenesis, which he emphasised was a hypothesis, was based on the idea that somatic cells would, in response to environmental stimulation (use and disuse), throw off 'gemmules' or 'pangenes' which travelled around the body (though not necessarily in the bloodstream). These pangenes were microscopic particles that supposedly contained information about the characteristics of their parent cell, and Darwin believed that they eventually accumulated in the germ cells where they could pass on to the next generation the newly acquired characteristics of the parents. Darwin's half-cousin, Francis Galton carried out experiments on rabbits, with Darwin's cooperation, in which he transfused the blood of one variety of rabbit into another variety in the expectation that its offspring would show some characteristics of the first. They did not, and Galton declared that he had disproved Darwin's hypothesis of Pangenesis, but Darwin objected, in a letter to Nature, that he had done nothing of the sort, since he had never mentioned blood in his writings. He pointed out that he regarded Pangenesis as occurring in Protozoa and plants, which have no blood.[3]

1880 to 1930

Edward Drinker Cope

The period of the history of evolutionary thought between Darwin's death in the 1880s and the foundation of population genetics in the 1920s, and the beginnings of the modern evolutionary synthesis in the 1930s is sometimes called the eclipse of Darwinism by some historians of science, because during that time many scientists and philosophers accepted the reality of evolution but doubted whether natural selection was the main evolutionary mechanism.[4] Theories involving the inheritance of acquired characteristics were among the most popular alternatives to natural selection, and scientists who felt that such Lamarckian mechanisms were the key to evolution were called neo-Lamarckians. Proponents included the British botanist George Henslow who studied the effects of environmental stress on the growth of plants in the belief that such environmentally induced variation might explain much of plant evolution, and the American entomologist Alpheus Packard who studied blind animals living in caves and wrote a book in 1901 about Lamarck and his work.[5][6] Also included were a number of paleontologists like Edward Drinker Cope and Alpheus Hyatt who felt that the fossil record showed orderly, almost linear, patterns of development that they felt were better explained by Lamarckian mechanisms than by natural selection. Some people including Cope and Darwin critic Samuel Butler felt that inheritance of acquired characteristics would let organisms shape their own evolution, since organisms that acquired new habits would change the use patterns of their organs, which would kick-start Lamarckian evolution. They considered this philosophically superior to Darwin's mechanism of random variation acted on by selective pressures. Lamarckism also appealed to those, like the philosopher Herbert Spencer and the German anatomist Ernst Haeckel, who saw evolution as an inherently progressive process.[5] The German zoologist Theodor Eimer combined Larmarckism with ideas about orthogenesis.[7] With the development of the modern synthesis of the theory of evolution and a lack of evidence for either a mechanism or even the heritability of acquired characteristics, Lamarckism largely fell from favor.

In the 1920s, experiments by Paul Kammerer on amphibians, particularly the midwife toad, appeared to find evidence supporting Lamarckism, but his specimens with supposedly acquired black foot-pads were found to have been tampered with. In The Case of the Midwife Toad Arthur Koestler surmised that the tampering had been done by a Nazi sympathiser to discredit Kammerer for his political views, and that his research might actually have been valid. However most biologists believe that Kammerer was a fraud and even among those who believe he was not dishonest most believe that he misinterpreted the results of his experiments.[8]

After 1930

A form of Lamarckism was revived in the Soviet Union of the 1930s when Trofim Lysenko promoted Lysenkoism which suited the ideological opposition of Joseph Stalin to genetics. This ideologically driven research influenced Soviet agricultural policy which in turn was later blamed for crop failures.[9]

The biologist Ernest MacBride was a supporter of Lamarckian evolution.[10] Herbert Graham Cannon a British zoologist defended Lamarckism in his book Lamarck and Modern Genetics in 1959.[11]

Since 1988 certain scientists have produced work proposing that Lamarckism could apply to single celled organisms. A version of Lamarckian acquisition in higher order animals is still posited in certain branches of psychology, as, for example, in the Jungian racial memory.

Neo-Lamarckism is a theory of inheritance based on a modification and extension of Lamarckism, essentially maintaining the principle that genetic changes can be influenced and directed by environmental factors.

Lamarck's theory

The long neck of the giraffe is often used as an example in explanations of Lamarckism.

The identification of Lamarckism with the inheritance of acquired characteristics is regarded by some as an artifact of the subsequent history of evolutionary thought, repeated in textbooks without analysis. Stephen Jay Gould wrote that late 19th century evolutionists "re-read Lamarck, cast aside the guts of it ... and elevated one aspect of the mechanics - inheritance of acquired characters - to a central focus it never had for Lamarck himself."[12] He argued that "the restriction of "Lamarckism" to this relatively small and non-distinctive corner of Lamarck's thought must be labelled as more than a misnomer, and truly a discredit to the memory of a man and his much more comprehensive system".[13] Gould advocated defining "Lamarckism" more broadly, in line with Lamarck's overall evolutionary theory.

Lamarck incorporated two ideas into his theory of evolution, in his day considered to be generally true:

  1. Use and disuse – Individuals lose characteristics they do not require (or use) and develop characteristics that are useful.
  2. Inheritance of acquired traits – Individuals inherit the traits of their ancestors.

Examples of what is traditionally called "Lamarckism" would include:

  • Giraffes stretching their necks to reach leaves high in trees (especially Acacias), strengthen and gradually lengthen their necks. These giraffes have offspring with slightly longer necks (also known as "soft inheritance").
  • A blacksmith, through his work, strengthens the muscles in his arms. His sons will have similar muscular development when they mature.

Lamarck stated the following two laws:

  1. Première Loi. Dans tout animal qui n' a point dépassé le terme de ses développemens, l' emploi plus fréquent et soutenu d' un organe quelconque, fortifie peu à peu cet organe, le développe, l' agrandit, et lui donne une puissance proportionnée à la durée de cet emploi ; tandis que le défaut constant d' usage de tel organe, l'affoiblit insensiblement, le détériore, diminue progressivement ses facultés, et finit par le faire disparoître.
  2. Deuxième Loi. Tout ce que la nature a fait acquérir ou perdre aux individus par l' influence des circonstances où leur race se trouve depuis long-temps exposée, et, par conséquent, par l' influence de l' emploi prédominant de tel organe, ou par celle d' un défaut constant d' usage de telle partie ; elle le conserve par la génération aux nouveaux individus qui en proviennent, pourvu que les changemens acquis soient communs aux deux sexes, ou à ceux qui ont produit ces nouveaux individus.[14]

English translation:

  1. In every animal which has not passed the limit of its development, a more frequent and continuous use of any organ gradually strengthens, develops and enlarges that organ, and gives it a power proportional to the length of time it has been so used; while the permanent disuse of any organ imperceptibly weakens and deteriorates it, and progressively diminishes its functional capacity, until it finally disappears.
  2. All the acquisitions or losses wrought by nature on individuals, through the influence of the environment in which their race has long been placed, and hence through the influence of the predominant use or permanent disuse of any organ; all these are preserved by reproduction to the new individuals which arise, provided that the acquired modifications are common to both sexes, or at least to the individuals which produce the young.[15]

In essence, a change in the environment brings about change in "needs" (besoins), resulting in change in behavior, bringing change in organ usage and development, bringing change in form over time — and thus the gradual transmutation of the species.

However, as historians of science such as Michael Ghiselin and Stephen Jay Gould have pointed out, none of these views were original to Lamarck.[16][17] On the contrary, Lamarck's contribution was a systematic theoretical framework for understanding evolution. He saw evolution as comprising two processes;

  1. Le pouvoir de la vie (a complexifying force) - in which the natural, alchemical movements of fluids would etch out organs from tissues, leading to ever more complex construction regardless of the organ's use or disuse. This would drive organisms from simple to complex forms.
  2. L'influence des circonstances (an adaptive force) - in which the use and disuse of characters led organisms to become more adapted to their environment. This would take organisms sideways off the path from simple to complex, specialising them for their environment.

Neo-Lamarckism

Pierre-Paul Grassé

Unlike neo-Darwinism, the term neo-Lamarckism refers more to a loose grouping of largely heterodox theories and mechanisms that emerged after Lamarck's time, than to any coherent body of theoretical work.

In a series of experiments from 1869 to 1891, Charles-Édouard Brown-Séquard cut the sciatic nerve of the leg and spinal cord in the dorsal regions of guinea pigs, causing an abnormal nervous condition resembling epilepsy; these were then bred and produced epileptic offspring.[18] Although some scientists considered this evidence for Lamarckian inheritance, the experiments were not Lamarckian, as they did not address the use and disuse of characteristics in response to the environment.[19] The results from the experiment were not duplicated by other scientists.[20] One explanation for the results was that they show a transmitted disease, and not evidence for the inheritance of an acquired characteristic.[21] Brown-Séquard's experiments are now considered anomalous and alternative explanations have been suggested.[22]

The French botanist Gaston Bonnier, conducting experiments in the French Alps in 1884 and the Pyrenees in 1886, studied structural changes induced by growing plants at various altitudes and transplanting them to others. Bonnier believed he had proven acquired adaptive characteristics; however, he did not weed, cultivate, fertilize or protect his plant specimens from native vegetation. In the 1920s his experiments were analysed and attributed to genetic contamination rather than Lamarckian inheritance.[23]

In a series of experiments (in 1891, 1893 and 1895) on the action of light on the coloration of flatfish, the British marine biologist Joseph Thomas Cunningham directed light upon the lower sides of flatfishes by means of a glass-bottomed tank placed over a mirror. He discovered the influence of light in producing pigments on the lower sides of flatfishes and gave his results a Lamarckian interpretation.[24][25][26] Other scientists wrote that Cunningham had received some definite results, but that they were open to more than one interpretation.[27] The geneticist William Bateson was not convinced that the cause of the increase in pigmentation was from the illumination. George Romanes wrote approvingly of Cunningham's interpretation.[28] Thomas Hunt Morgan (1903) criticized the experiments and did not believe the results were evidence for Lamarckism.[29]

In the late 19th century Frederick Merrifield exposed caterpillars and chrysalids to significantly high and low temperatures, and discovered permanent changes in some offspring's wing patterns. Swiss biologist Max Standfuss led 30 years of intensive breeding experiments with European butterflies and after several generations, found similar preserved variations even generations after the cessation of exposing them to low temperatures.[30] Standfuss was a Lamarckian and attributed the results of his experiments as direct changes to the environment.[31] In 1940 Richard Goldschmidt interpreted these results without invoking Lamarckian inheritance, and in 1998 Ernst Mayr wrote that results reported by Standfuss and others on the effects of abnormal temperatures on Lepidoptera are difficult to interpret.[32]

In 1910 the American zoologist Charles Rupert Stockard (1879-1939) tested the effects of alcohol intoxication on the offspring of pregnant guinea pigs. Stockard discovered that repeated alcohol intoxication in the guinea pigs produced defects and malformations in their offspring that was passed down to two or more generations. His results were challenged by the biologist Raymond Pearl who performed the same experiments with chickens. Pearl discovered that the offspring of the chickens that had been exposed to alcohol were not defected but were healthy.[33] He attributed his findings to the detrimental effects of alcohol only on the eggs and sperm which were already weak, the strong eggs and sperm were unaffected by alcohol intoxication. Pearl argued that his results had a Darwinian, not a Lamarckian explanation.[34]

In a series of experiments Francis Bertody Sumner (1874-1945) reared several generations of white mice under different conditions of temperature and relative humidity.[35] Sumner discovered that the white mice at 20°C to 30°C developed longer bodies, tails and hind feet which were also transmitted to their offspring over a number of generations, however, later results were not entirely consistent and the experiments ended in uncertainty.[36]

In the 1920s, Harvard University researcher William McDougall studied the abilities of rats to correctly solve mazes. He found that offspring of rats that had learned the maze were able to run it faster. The first rats would get it wrong 165 times before being able to run it perfectly each time, but after a few generations it was down to 20. McDougall attributed this to some sort of Lamarckian evolutionary process.[37] Oscar Werner Tiegs and Wilfred Eade Agar later showed McDougall's results to be incorrect, caused by poor experimental controls.[38][39][40][41][42]

The Russian physiologist Ivan Pavlov claimed to have observed a similar phenomenon in white mice being subject to a conditioned reflex experiment involving food and the sound of a bell. He wrote that with each generation, the mice became easier to condition. In 1926 Pavlov announced that there had been a fatal flaw in his experiment and retracted his claim to have demonstrated Lamarckian inheritance.[43] In other experiments Coleman Griffith (1920, 1922) and John Detlefson (1923, 1925) reared rats in cages on a rotating table for three months. The rats adapted to the rotating condition to such an extent that when the rotation was stopped they showed signs of disequilibration and other physiological conditions which were inherited for several generations.[44][45][46][47] In 1933 Roy Dorcus replicated their experiments but obtained different results as the rotated rats did not manifest any abnormalities of posture described by Griffith and Detlefson.[48] Other studies revealed that the same abnormalities could occur in rats without rotation if they were suffering from an ear infection thus the results were interpreted as a case of infection, not Lamarckian inheritance.[49]

Between 1918 and 1924 two American scientists Michael F. Guyer and Elizabeth A. Smith performed experiments in which fowl serum antibodies for rabbit lens-protein were injected into pregnant rabbits which resulted in defects in the eyes of some of their offspring that were inherited through eight generations.[50] Their experiments were criticized and were not repeated by other scientists.[51] In the 1930s the German geneticist Victor Jollos (1887-1941) in a series of experiments claimed evidence for inherited changes induced by heat treatment in Drosophila melanogaster.[52] His experiments were described as Lamarckian however Jollos was not an advocate of Lamarckian evolution and attributed the results from his experiments as evidence for directed mutagenesis. American scientists were unable to replicate his results.[53]

The American paleontologist Edward Drinker Cope was a neo-Lamarckian as he believed that an organism could respond to any challenge by choosing to adapt to a new way of life.[54] The British anthropologist Frederic Wood Jones and the South African paleontologist Robert Broom supported a neo-Lamarckian view of human evolution as opposed to the Darwinian view. The German anthropologist Hermann Klaatsch relied on a neo-Lamarckian model of evolution to try and explain the origin of bipedalism. Neo-Lamarckism remained influential in biology until the 1940s when the role of natural selection was reasserted in evolution as part of the modern evolutionary synthesis.[55]

In the 1970s the immunologist Ted Steele, formerly of the University of Wollongong, and colleagues, proposed a neo-Lamarckian mechanism to try to explain why homologous DNA sequences from the VDJ gene regions of parent mice were found in their germ cells and seemed to persist in the offspring for a few generations. The mechanism involved the somatic selection and clonal amplification of newly acquired antibody gene sequences that were generated via somatic hyper-mutation in B-cells. The mRNA products of these somatically novel genes were captured by retroviruses endogenous to the B-cells and were then transported through the blood stream where they could breach the soma-germ barrier and retrofect (reverse transcribe) the newly acquired genes into the cells of the germ line. Although Steele was advocating this theory for the better part of two decades, little more than indirect evidence was ever acquired to support it. An interesting attribute of this idea is that it strongly resembles Darwin's own theory of pangenesis, except in the soma to germ line feedback theory, pangenes are replaced with realistic retroviruses.Cite error: A <ref> tag is missing the closing </ref> (see the help page).

Neo-Lamarckism was dominant in French biology for more than a century. French scientists who supported neo-Lamarckism included Edmond Perrier (1844-1921), Alfred Giard (1846-1908), Gaston Bonnier (1853-1922) and Pierre-Paul Grassé (1895-1985).[56]

Ideological neo-Lamarckism

Neo-Lamarckian versions of evolution were widespread in the late 19th century. The idea that living things could to some degree choose the characteristics that would be inherited allowed them things to be in charge of their own destiny as opposed to the Darwinian view, which made them puppets at the mercy of the environment. Such ideas were more popular than natural selection in the late 19th century as it made it possible for biological evolution to fit into a framework of a divine or naturally willed plan, thus the neo-Lamarckian view of evolution was often advocated by proponents of orthogenesis.[57] According to historian of biology Peter J. Bowler:

One of the most emotionally compelling arguments used by the neo-Lamarckians of the late nineteenth century was the claim that Darwinism was a mechanistic theory which reduced living things to puppets driven by heredity. The selection theory made life into a game of Russian roulette, where life or death was predetermined by the genes one inherited. The individual could do nothing to mitigate bad heredity. Lamarckism, in contrast, allowed the individual to choose a new habit when faced with an environmental challenge and shape the whole future course of evolution.[58]

Supporters of neo-Lamarckism such as George Bernard Shaw and Arthur Koestler claimed that Lamarckism is more humane, and optimistic than Darwinism.[59]

Current views

Epigenetic inheritance

Illustration of a DNA molecule that is methylated at the two center cytosines. DNA methylation plays an important role for epigenetic gene regulation in development and disease.

Forms of 'soft' or epigenetic inheritance within organisms have been suggested as neo-Lamarckian in nature by such scientists as Eva Jablonka and Marion J. Lamb. In addition to 'hard' or genetic inheritance, involving the duplication of genetic material and its segregation during meiosis, there are other hereditary elements that pass into the germ cells also. These include things like methylation patterns in DNA and chromatin marks, both of which regulate the activity of genes. These are considered "Lamarckian" in the sense that they are responsive to environmental stimuli and can differentially affect gene expression adaptively, with phenotypic results that can persist for many generations in certain organisms.[60] In 2008, Jablonka and Lamb published a paper which claimed there is evidence for Lamarckian epigenetic control systems causing evolutionary changes and the mechanisms underlying epigenetic inheritance can also lead to saltational changes that reorganize the epigenome.[61]

Interest in Lamarckism has increased, as studies in the field of epigenetics have highlighted the possible inheritance of behavioral traits acquired by the previous generation. A 2009 study examined foraging behavior in chickens as a function of stress,[62] concluding:

Our findings suggest that unpredictable food access caused seemingly adaptive responses in feeding behavior, which may have been transmitted to the offspring by means of epigenetic mechanisms, including regulation of immune genes. This may have prepared the offspring for coping with an unpredictable environment.... Transmissions of information across generations which does not involve traditional inheritance of DNA-sequence alleles is often referred to as soft inheritance [63] or 'Lamarckian inheritance'.[62]

The evolution of acquired characteristics has also been shown in human populations who have experienced starvation, resulting in altered gene function in both the starved population and their offspring.[64] The process of DNA methylation is thought to be behind such changes.

In October 2010, further evidence linking food intake to traits inherited by the offspring were shown in a study of rats conducted by several Australian universities.[65] The study strongly suggested that fathers can transfer a propensity for obesity to their daughters as a result of the fathers' food intake, and not their genetics (or specific genes), prior to the conception of the daughter. A "paternal high-fat diet" was shown to cause cell dysfunction in the daughter, which in turn led to obesity for the daughter. Felicia Nowak, et al. reported at The Endocrine Society meeting in June 2013 that obese male rats passed on the tendency to obesity to their male offspring.[66]

Several studies, one conducted by researchers at MIT and another by researchers at the Tufts University School of Medicine, have rekindled the debate once again. As reported in MIT's Technology Review in February 2009, "The effects of an animal's environment during adolescence can be passed down to future offspring ... The findings provide support for a 200-year-old theory of evolution that has been largely dismissed: Lamarckian evolution, which states that acquired characteristics can be passed on to offspring."[67] A report investigating the inheritance of resistance to viral infection in the nematode Caenorhabditis elegans suggests that small RNA molecules may be inherited in a non Mendelian fashion and provide resistance to infection.[68]

A scientific study (Akimoto et al. 2007) on epigenetic inheritance in rice plants came to the conclusion that "gene expression is flexibly tuned by methylation, allowing plants to gain or lose particular traits which are heritable as far as methylation patterns of corresponding genes are maintained. This is in support of the concept of Lamarckian inheritance, suggesting that acquired traits are heritable."[69] Another study (Sano, 2010) wrote that observations suggest that acquired traits are heritable in plants as far as the acquired methylation pattern is stably transmitted which is consistent with Lamarckian evolution.[70] Handel and Ramagopalan, 2010 have written that there is evidence that epigenetic alterations such as DNA methylation and histone modifications, are transmitted transgenerationally as a mechanism for environmental influences to be passed from parents to offspring. According to Handel and Romagopalan "epigenetics allows the peaceful co-existence of Darwinian and Lamarckian evolution."[71]

In their book An Introduction to Zoology (2012) Joseph Springer and Dennis Holley wrote:

Lamarck and his ideas were ridiculed and discredited. In a strange twist of fate, Lamarck may have the last laugh. Epigenetics, an emerging field of genetics, has shown that Lamarck may have been at least partially correct all along. It seems that reversible and heritable changes can occur without a change in DNA sequence (genotype) and that such changes may be induced spontaneously or in response to environmental factors - Lamarck's "acquired traits". Determining which observed phenotypes are genetically inherited and which are environmentally induced remains an important and on going part of the study of genetics, developmental biology, and medicine.[72]

Eugene Koonin has written that the prokaryotic CRISPR system and Piwi-interacting RNA could be classified as Lamarckian and came to the conclusion "Both Darwinian and Lamarckian modalities of evolution appear to be important, and reflect different aspects of the interaction between populations and the environment."[73]

A study in 2013 reported that mutations caused by a father's lifestyle can be inherited by his children through multiple generations.[74] A Swedish study showed that exercise changes the epigenetic pattern of genes that affect fat storage in the body.[75]

Commenting on this, Science Daily explained,

The cells of the body contain DNA, which contains genes. We inherit our genes and they cannot be changed. The genes, however, have 'methyl groups' attached which affect what is known as 'gene expression' -- whether the genes are activated or deactivated. The methyl groups can be influenced in various ways, through exercise, diet and lifestyle, in a process known as 'DNA methylation'.[76]

A 2013 study in Nature reported that mice trained to fear the smell of a chemical called acetophenone passed their fear onto at least two generations.[77][78] An article on the study in the New Scientist titled Mouse memory inheritance may revitalise Lamarckism wrote "While it needs to be corroborated, this finding seems consistent with Lamarckian inheritance. It is, however, based on epigenetics: changes that tweak the action of genes, not the genes themselves. So it fits with natural selection – and may yet give Lamarck's name a sheen of respectability."[79]

Guy Barry in a neuroscience paper in 2013 has written Darwin's hypothesis pangenesis coupled with "Lamarckian somatic cell-derived epigenetic modifications" and de novo RNA and DNA mutations can explain the evolution of the human brain.[80]

Lamarckian elements also appear in the hologenome theory of evolution.

Criticism

The botanist Conway Zirkle (1946) pointed out that Lamarck did not originate the hypothesis that acquired characters were heritable, therefore it is incorrect to refer to it as Lamarckism:

What Lamarck really did was to accept the hypothesis that acquired characters were heritable, a notion which had been held almost universally for well over two thousand years and which his contemporaries accepted as a matter of course, and to assume that the results of such inheritance were cumulative from generation to generation, thus producing, in time, new species. His individual contribution to biological theory consisted in his application to the problem of the origin of species of the view that acquired characters were inherited and in showing that evolution could be inferred logically from the accepted biological hypotheses. He would doubtless have been greatly astonished to learn that a belief in the inheritance of acquired characters is now labeled “Lamarckian,” although he would almost certainly have felt flattered if evolution itself had been so designated.[81]

The evolutionary biologist T. Ryan Gregory has written epigenetic inheritance should not be considered "Lamarckian". According to Gregory; Lamarck did not claim the environment imposed direct effects on organisms, instead Lamarck "argued that the environment created needs to which organisms responded by using some features more and others less, that this resulted in those features being accentuated or attenuated, and that this difference was then inherited by offspring." Gregory has stated that "Lamarckian" evolution in the context of epigenetics is actually closer to the view held by Darwin rather than by Lamarck.[82]

Although the reality of epigenetic inheritance is not doubted (as many experiments have validated it), its significance to the evolutionary process is uncertain. Most neo-Darwinians consider epigenetic inheritance modifications to not be inherited past one or two generations, so are not a stable basis for evolutionary change.[83][84]

In a paper titled Weismann Rules! Epigenetics and the Lamarckian Temptation (2007), David Haig writes that research into epigenetic processes does allow a Lamarckian element in evolutionary theory but the processes do not challenge the main tenets of the modern evolutionary synthesis like modern Lamarckians have claimed. Haig argued for the primary of DNA and evolution of epigenetic switches by natural selection.[85] Haig has also written there is a "visceral attraction" to Lamarckian evolution from the public and some scientists as it posits the world with a meaning, in which organisms can shape their own evolutionary destiny.[86]

In 2009, Douglas Futuyma wrote "There is no evidence yet that epigenetic variation contributes to evolutionary change, and considerable difference of opinion on whether or not it is likely to do so."[87]

Thomas Dickens and Qazi Rahman have written epigenetic mechanisms such as DNA methylation and histone modification are genetically inherited under the control of natural selection and do not challenge the modern synthesis. Dickens and Rahman have taken issue with the claims of Eva Jablonka and Marion Lamb on Lamarckian epigenetic processes.[88]

Jerry Coyne has written that "lots of studies show us that Lamarckian inheritance doesn’t operate" and epigenetic changes are rarely passed on to future generations, thus do not serve as the basis of evolutionary change.[89]

See also

Template:Wikipedia books

References

  1. ^ . doi:10.1523/JNEUROSCI.5057-08.2009. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  2. ^ Desmond A. & Moore, J. (1991) Darwin Penguin Books p.617 "Darwin was loathe [sic?] to let go of the notion that a well-used and strengthened organ could be inherited"
  3. ^ . Bibcode:1871Natur...3..502D. doi:10.1038/003502a0. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help); Unknown parameter |doi_brokendate= ignored (|doi-broken-date= suggested) (help)
  4. ^ Quammen, David (2006). The Reluctant Mr. Darwin. Atlas Books. p. 216. ISBN 0-393-05981-2.
  5. ^ a b Bowler, Peter J. (2003). Evolution:The History of an Idea. University of California Press. pp. 236–244. ISBN 0-520-23693-9.
  6. ^ Quammen, David (2006). The Reluctant Mr. Darwin. Atlas Books. pp. 218, 220. ISBN 0-393-05981-2.
  7. ^ Quammen, David (2006). The Reluctant Mr. Darwin. Atlas Books. p. 221. ISBN 0-393-05981-2.
  8. ^ Bowler, Peter J. (2003). Evolution:The History of an Idea. University of California Press. pp. 245–246. ISBN 0-520-23693-9.
  9. ^ Davis Baird, Eric R. Scerri, Lee C. McIntyre. (2005). Philosophy of Chemistry: Synthesis of a New Discipline. Springer. p. 166
  10. ^ . doi:10.1080/00033798400200251. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  11. ^ Herbert Graham Cannon. (1975). Lamarck and Modern Genetics Greenwood Press Reprint. ISBN 0-8371-8173-9
  12. ^ Gould, Stephen J. "Shades of Lamarck", reprinted in The Panda's Thumb (1980) pp.65-71. Quote from page 66.
  13. ^ Gould, Stephen J. (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Harvard: Belknap Harvard. pp. 177–178. ISBN 0-674-00613-5.
  14. ^ Jean-Baptiste Lamarck Philosophie zoologique ch.7, p.235[dead link]
  15. ^ Jean-Baptiste Lamarck Zoological Philosophy trans. Hugh Elliot, 1914, p.113
  16. ^ The Imaginary Lamarck: a look at bogus "history" in schoolbooks by Michael Ghiselin
  17. ^ Gould, S.J. (2002) The Structure of Evolutionary Theory
  18. ^ Fredrick Blackmar Mumford. (1921). The Breeding of Animals. Macmillan. p. 209
  19. ^ Stephen Finney Mason. (1956). Main Currents of Scientific Thought: A History of the Sciences. Abelard-Schuman. p. 343. Also see Lamarck's Laws cited in Richard Burkhardt. (1995). The Spirit of System: Lamarck and Evolutionary Biology. Harvard University Press. p. 166
  20. ^ Martin Raitiere. (2012). The Complicity of Friends: How George Eliot, G. H. Lewes, and John Hughlings-Jackson Encoded Herbert Spencer's Secret. Bucknell University Press. p. 299
  21. ^ Henry Richardson Linville, Henry Augustus Kelly. (1906). Text Book Of General Zoology. Ginn & Company. p. 108
  22. ^ Aminoff, Michael J. (2011). Brown-Séquard: An improbable genius who transformed medicine. O.U.P. p. 192. ISBN 9780199780648.
  23. ^ Robert E. Kohler. (2002). Landscapes and Labscapes: Exploring the Lab-Field Border in Biology. University Of Chicago Press. p. 167. ISBN 978-0-226-45010-0
  24. ^ Cunningham, J. T. (1891). "An experiment concerning the absence of color from the lower sides of flat-fishes". Zool. Anzeiger. 14: 27–32.
  25. ^ . doi:10.1017/S0025315400049596. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  26. ^ . doi:/10.1017/S0025315400050761. {{cite journal}}: Check |doi= value (help); Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  27. ^ The Spectator. (1928). Volume 141. p. 25
  28. ^ Alan G. Cock, Donald R. Forsdyke. (2008). Treasure Your Exceptions: The Science and Life of William Bateson. Springer. pp. 132-133. ISBN 978-0387756875
  29. ^ Thomas Hunt Morgan. (1903). Evolution and Adaptation. The Macmillan company. pp. 257-259
  30. ^ Auguste Forel. (1929). The Sexual Question: A Scientific, Psychological, Hygienic and Sociological Study for the Cultured Classes. Physicians and Surgeons Book Company. p. 36
  31. ^ John Michels. (1896). Science: Volume 4. Moses King. p. 53
  32. ^ Richard Goldschmidt (1940). The Material Basis of Evolution. Yale University. pp. 266-267. Ernst Mayr. (1998). The Evolutionary Synthesis: Perspectives on the Unification of Biology. Harvard University Press. p. 348
  33. ^ L. Doncaster. (1910). Heredity in the Light of Recent Research. Cambridge University Press. p. 98
  34. ^ Mark S. Blumberg. (2010). Freaks of Nature: And what They Tell Us about Evolution and Development. Oxford University Press. pp. 69-70
  35. ^ Robert Thompson Young. (1922). Biology in America. R.G. Badger. p. 249
  36. ^ Charles Manning Child. (1947). Biographical Memoir of Francis Bertody Sumner, 1874-1945. In National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America Biographical Memoirs, Vol. 25. 146-73.
  37. ^ . doi:10.1111/j.2044-8295.1938.tb00882.x. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  38. ^ . doi:10.1098/rsbm.1957.0017. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  39. ^ W E Agar, F H Drummond (1935). "First report on a test of McDougall's Lamarckian experiment on the training of rats". Journal of Experimental Biology. 12: 191.
  40. ^ W E Agar, F H Drummond (1942). "Second report on a test of McDougall's Lamarckian experiment on the training of rats". Journal of Experimental Biology. 19: 158.
  41. ^ W E Agar, F H Drummond (1948). "Third report on a test of McDougall's Lamarckian experiment on the training of rats". Journal of Experimental Biology. 25: 103.
  42. ^ W E Agar, F H Drummond, M M Gunson (1954). "Fourth (final) report on a test of McDougall's Lamarckian experiment on the training of rats". Journal of Experimental Biology. 31: 308.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  43. ^ William McDougall. (1934). Religion and the Sciences of Life: With Other Essays on Allied Topics. Methuen & Co., Ltd. p. 180
  44. ^ Griffith, Coleman R. (1920). "The Effect upon the White Rat of Continued Bodily Rotation". The American Naturalist. 54 (635): 524–34. JSTOR 2456346.
  45. ^ . doi:10.1126/science.56.1459.676. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  46. ^ Detlefsen, J. A. (1923). "Are the Effects of Long-Continued Rotation in Rats Inherited?". Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society. 62 (5): 292–300. JSTOR 984462.
  47. ^ Detlefsen, J. A. (1925). "The inheritance of acquired characters". Physiological Reviews. 5 (2): 224–78.
  48. ^ . doi:10.1037/h0074715. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  49. ^ Studies from the Otho S. A. Sprague Memorial Institute. (1940). Volume 25. p. 162
  50. ^ . PMID 16576477. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  51. ^ Peter Medawar. (1985). Aristotle to Zoos: A Philosophical Dictionary of Biology. Harvard University Press. p. 169
  52. ^ . doi:10.1007/BF01984742. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  53. ^ Jonathan Harwood. (1993). Styles of Scientific Thought: The German Genetics Community, 1900-1933. The University of Chicago Press. pp. 121-131.
  54. ^ Peter J. Bowler. (2009). Evolution: The History of an Idea. University of California Press. p. 227. ISBN 978-0-520-26128-0
  55. ^ Bernard Wood. (2013). Wiley-Blackwell Encyclopedia of Human Evolution. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-118-65099-8
  56. ^ . doi:10.1007/s10739-010-9240-x. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  57. ^ Peter J. Bowler. (1992). The Eclipse of Darwinism: Anti-Darwinian Evolution Theories in the Decades around 1900. The Johns Hopkins University Press. ISBN 978-0-8018-4391-4
  58. ^ Peter J. Bowler. (2003). Evolution: The History of an Idea. University of California Press p. 367. ISBN 978-0-520-26128-0
  59. ^ James Richard Moore. (2002). History, Humanity and Evolution: Essays for John C. Greene. Cambridge University Press. p. 330. ISBN 978-0-521-52478-0
  60. ^ Eva Jablonka, Marion J. Lamb. (1995). Epigenetic Inheritance and Evolution: The Lamarckian Dimension. Oxford University Press.[page needed]
  61. ^ . doi:10.1590/S1415-47572008000300001. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  62. ^ a b . doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0006405. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)CS1 maint: unflagged free DOI (link)
  63. ^ . doi:10.1038/nrg1834. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  64. ^ . doi:10.1016/0028-2243(95)02149-M. INIST 3596539. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  65. ^ . doi:10.1038/nature09491. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  66. ^ Obese male mice father offspring with higher levels of body fat
  67. ^ http://www.technologyreview.com/biomedicine/22061[full citation needed]
  68. ^ . doi:10.1016/j.cell.2011.10.042. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  69. ^ . doi:10.1093/aob/mcm110. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  70. ^ . doi:10.4161/psb.5.4.10803. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  71. ^ . doi:10.1186/1471-2350-11-73. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)CS1 maint: unflagged free DOI (link)
  72. ^ Joseph Springer, Dennis Holley. (2012). An Introduction to Zoology. Jones & Bartlett Learning. p. 94
  73. ^ . doi:10.1186/1745-6150-4-42. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)CS1 maint: unflagged free DOI (link)
  74. ^ . doi:10.1096/fj.13-227694. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help); Unknown parameter |laydate= ignored (help); Unknown parameter |laysource= ignored (help); Unknown parameter |layurl= ignored (help)CS1 maint: unflagged free DOI (link)
  75. ^ . doi:10.1371/journal.pgen.1003572. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help); Unknown parameter |laydate= ignored (help); Unknown parameter |laysource= ignored (help); Unknown parameter |layurl= ignored (help)CS1 maint: unflagged free DOI (link)
  76. ^ Cite error: The named reference ScienceDaily was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  77. ^ . doi:10.1038/nn.3594. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help); Unknown parameter |laydate= ignored (help); Unknown parameter |laysource= ignored (help); Unknown parameter |layurl= ignored (help)
  78. ^ . doi:10.1038/nature.2013.14272. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  79. ^ "Mouse memory inheritance may revitalise Lamarckism". New Scientist. 4 December 2013.
  80. ^ . doi:10.3389/fnins.2013.00224. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)CS1 maint: unflagged free DOI (link)
  81. ^ Zirkle, Conway (1946). "The Early History of the Idea of the Inheritance of Acquired Characters and of Pangenesis". Transactions of the American Philosophical Society. 35 (2): 91–151. JSTOR 1005592. {{cite journal}}: Unknown parameter |month= ignored (help)
  82. ^ T. Ryan Gregory. (2008). Lamarck didn’t say it, Darwin did. Evolver Zone.[unreliable source?]
  83. ^ Jerry Coyne. (2010). Epigenetics: the light and the way?. Why Evolution is True.[unreliable source?]
  84. ^ Jerry Coyne. (2013). Epigenetics smackdown at the Guardian. Why Evolution is True.[unreliable source?]
  85. ^ . doi:10.1007/s10539-006-9033-y. Modern neo-Darwinists do not deny that epigenetic mechanisms play an important role during development nor do they deny that these mechanisms enable a variety of adaptive responses to the environment. Recurrent, predictable changes of epigenetic state provide a useful set of switches that allow genetically-identical cells to acquire differentiated functions and allow facultative responses of a genotype to environmental changes (provided that 'similar' changes have occurred repeatedly in the past). However, most neo-Darwinists would claim that the ability to adaptively switch epigenetic state is a property of the DNA sequence (in the sense that alternative sequences would show different switching behavior) and that any increase of adaptedness in the system has come about by a process of natural selection. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  86. ^ . doi:10.3998/ptb.6959004.0003.004. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  87. ^ Douglas Futuyma. (2009). Evolution. Sinauer Associates.[page needed]
  88. ^ . doi:10.1098/rspb.2012.0273. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Missing or empty |title= (help)
  89. ^ Jerry Coyne. (2013). More puffery about epigenetics, and my usual role as go-to curmudgeon. Why Evolution is True.[unreliable source?]

Further reading

External links