Jump to content

Argumentum ad baculum: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
m Examples: Typography
m The non-fallacious ad baculum: consistency of layout
Line 22: Line 22:
:x does not want Q and will act to prevent it.
:x does not want Q and will act to prevent it.
:Therefore, x will reject P.
:Therefore, x will reject P.
The fallacy in the argument lies in assuming that the truth value of "x accepts P" is related to the truth value of P itself. Whether x does actually accept P, and whether P is true can not be inferred from the available statements. However, the argument can be changed into a valid [[modus tollens]] by changing the conclusion. For example:
The fallacy in the argument lies in assuming that the truth value of "x accepts P" is related to the truth value of P itself. Whether x does actually accept P, and whether P is true can not be inferred from the available statements. However, the argument can be changed into a valid [[modus tollens]] by changing the conclusion.

=== Example: ===
:If [[Denial of Peter|Peter does not deny knowing Jesus]], he will be arrested by the Romans.
:If [[Denial of Peter|Peter does not deny knowing Jesus]], he will be arrested by the Romans.
:Peter does not want to be arrested by Romans.
:Peter does not want to be arrested by Romans.

Revision as of 14:41, 18 December 2015

Argumentum ad baculum (Latin for "argument to the cudgel" or "appeal to the stick"), also known as appeal to force, is an argument where force, coercion, or the threat of force, is given as a justification. It is a specific case of the negative form of an argument to the consequences. For this reason, it is sometimes referred to as the "Might Makes Right" fallacy.[citation needed]

The fallacious ad baculum

A fallacious logical argument based on argumentum ad baculum generally proceeds as follows:

If x accepts P as true, then Q.
x acts to prevent Q and succeeds, so Q ist not true.
Therefore, P is not true.

This form of argument is an informal fallacy, because the attack on Q may not necessarily reveal anything about the truth value of the premise P. This fallacy has been identified since the Middle Ages by many philosophers. This is a special case of argumentum ad consequentiam, or "appeal to consequences".

Examples

  • Employee: “I do not think the company should invest its money in this project.”
    Employer: “Say that again and you will be fired.”
  • “If you do not believe in God, you will be imprisoned.”
  • “A Smith & Wesson beats four aces.” —Canada Bill Jones

The non-fallacious ad baculum

This argument is of the form:

If x accepts P, then Q.
x does not want Q and will act to prevent it.
Therefore, x will reject P.

The fallacy in the argument lies in assuming that the truth value of "x accepts P" is related to the truth value of P itself. Whether x does actually accept P, and whether P is true can not be inferred from the available statements. However, the argument can be changed into a valid modus tollens by changing the conclusion.

Example:

If Peter does not deny knowing Jesus, he will be arrested by the Romans.
Peter does not want to be arrested by Romans.
Therefore, Peter denies knowing Jesus.

Note that this argument does not assert or come to any conclusion on whether Peter actually knows Jesus (cf. the fallacious conclusion "Therefore, Peter does not know Jesus").

See also

References