Jump to content

Theistic finitism

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Finite God)

Theistic finitism, also known as finitistic theism or finite godism, is the belief in a deity that is limited.[1][2] It has been proposed by some philosophers and theologians to solve the problem of evil. Most finitists accept the absolute goodness of God but reject omnipotence.[3]

Definition

[edit]

Finitistic theism denies that God is omnipotent.[1] Ray Harbaugh Dotterer in his book The Argument for a Finitist Theology (1917) summarized the argument for theistic finitism:

God can not be thought to be at once omnipotent and perfectly good. If we say that he is omnipotent, that his sovereignty is complete, that all events that occur are willed by him; then it follows that he is responsible for the actual world, which is partly evil, and, accordingly, that he is not perfectly good. If we begin at the other end, and say God is perfectly good, then we must deny that he is omnipotent.[4]

The idea that God is and must be infinite has been a nearly universal belief amongst monotheists. Only a minority of thinkers have advanced the idea of a finite deity.[5]

History

[edit]

The idea of a finite God has been traced to Plato's Timaeus. Plato's God was not an omnipotent Creator but a Demiurge struggling to control recalcitrant "stuff" or "matter". To Plato, matter was infected with evil, uncreated by God.[6]

William James (1842–1910) was a believer in a finite God which he used to explain the problem of evil.[7][8][9] James rejected the divine authorship of the Bible and the idea of a perfect God. He defined God as a "combination of ideality and (final) efficacity" and preferred a finite God that is "cognizant and responsive in some way".[10][11] James's finite God was not omnipotent, omnipresent, omniscient or a creator of the universe.[7][11][12]

Theologian Clarence Beckwith (1849–1931) suggested that Horace Bushnell (1802–1876) was a finitist. According to Beckwith "one of the earliest attempts in America to show that God was finite was made by Horace Bushnell in his God in Christ (1849).[13][14]

A minority of historical freethinkers and rationalists advocated a finite God in opposition to the God in Abrahamic religions. H. G. Wells advocated a finite God in his book God the Invisible King (1917). Rannie Belle Baker in his book The Concept of a Limited God (1934) identified Gustav Fechner, Charles Renouvier, William James and John Stuart Mill as admitting the concept of a finite God.[15] F. C. S. Schiller conceived of a finite, evolving God that is limited in power.[16][17]

Another advocate of theistic finitism was Peter Bertocci (1910–1989) who proposed that "God is all-good but not all-powerful".[1] Most finitists have held that God is personal, although a few such as Henry Nelson Wieman (1884–1975) have stated God is impersonal.[1]

Philosopher Edgar S. Brightman (1884–1953) defended theistic finitism in his book A Philosophy of Religion, published in 1940. Brightman stated that theistic finitism began with Plato and he traced the idea through history to Marcion, Mani and Manichaeism, Pierre Bayle, John Stuart Mill, H. G. Wells and others.[18] Brightman developed the concept of a finite God to solve the problem of evil. He held the view that God is an infinite personal spirit but his power is limited.[19] Brightman suggested that Wells was first "to devote an entire book to the concept of God's finiteness".[18] Wells dissociated his God in any respect from the biblical God.[20] Albert C. Knudson stated that John Stuart Mill was the first modern writer to advocate a finite God.[21]

Rufus Burrow, Jr. a professor of Christian thought, has argued (2012) that Brightman was different from most other finitists as he held the view that God remains infinite in many ways.[22] This was in opposition to Plato and H. G. Wells. Burrow noted that Brightman characterized God as a "finite-infinite God".[22] Charles Hartshorne who rejected omnipotence also argued for a finite-infinite God.[23][24]

Other advocates of theistic finitism were Hartley Burr Alexander, John Elof Boodin, Dewitt H. Parker, William Pepperell Montague and W. T. Stace.[24][25]

Recent

[edit]

Conservative rabbi Harold Kushner defended theistic finitism in his book When Bad Things Happen to Good People, published in 1981.[1][26]

Philosopher Frank B. Dilley noted in 2000 that theistic finitism is rarely discussed in modern philosophical literature.[27]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b c d e Geisler, Norman; Watkins, William D. (1989). Finite Godism: A World with a Finite God. In Worlds Apart: A Handbook on World Views. Wipf and Stock Publishers. pp. 187-216. ISBN 1-59244-126-2
  2. ^ McKim, Donald K. (1996). Westminster Dictionary of Theological Terms. Westminster John Knox Press. p. 278. ISBN 0-664-22089-4
  3. ^ Sahakian, William S; Sahakian, Mabel Lewis. (1974). Realms of Philosophy. Schenkman Publishing Company. p. 319. "Theistic Finitism is meant the belief that God is limited in some capacity or quality, usually power or goodness; either he lacks absolute power or absolute goodness. The majority of Finitists accept the absolute goodness of God while relinquishing belief in his omnipotence".
  4. ^ Dotterer, Ray Harbaugh. (1917). The Argument for a Finitist Theology. New Era Printing Company. p. 23
  5. ^ Hudson, Yeager. Omnipotence: Must God Be Infinite?. In Creighton Peden, Larry E. Axel. (1989). God, Values, and Empiricism: Issues in Philosophical Theology. Mercer University Press. p. 92. ISBN 0-86554-360-7
  6. ^ Clark, Ted R. (1955). "The Doctrine of a Finite God". Review & Expositor. 52 (1): 21–43. doi:10.1177/003463735505200103.
  7. ^ a b Barnard, George William. (1997). Exploring Unseen Worlds: William James and the Philosophy of Mysticism. State University of New York Press. p. 251. ISBN 0-7914-3223-8 "James's theology answer to the problem of evil is strikingly simple, but theologically daring: God is not all-powerful, all-knowing, or all-pervasive, but rather, is finite."
  8. ^ Weidenbaum, Jonathan. (2013) William James’s Argument for a Finite Theism. In Diller J., Kasher A. (eds) Models of God and Alternative Ultimate Realities. Springer. pp. 323-331. ISBN 978-94-007-5218-4
  9. ^ Stepanenko, Walter Scott (2018). "Jamesian Finite Theism and the Problems of Suffering". European Journal for Philosophy of Religion. 10 (4): 1–25. doi:10.24204/ejpr.v10i4.1966.
  10. ^ Kamber, Richard. (2016). William James: Essays and Lectures. Routledge. p. 159. ISBN 978-1138457393
  11. ^ a b Pomerlaeau, Wayne P. (1998). Western Philosophies Religion. Ardsley House Publishers. p. 492. ISBN 978-1-880157-62-6
  12. ^ Schwartz, Robert. (2015). Rethinking Pragmatism: From William James to Contemporary Philosophy. Wiley. p. 25. ISBN 978-0-470-67469-7
  13. ^ Bushnell, Horace (2010) [1876]. God in Christ : three discourses, delivered at New Haven, Cambridge, and Andover : with a preliminary dissertation on language. Ann Arbor, Mich.: Scholarly Publishing Office, University of Michigan Library. ISBN 978-1-4255-3727-2. OCLC 678632613., includes a preliminary dissertation arguing that language is inadequate to express things of the spirit.
  14. ^ Beckwith, Clarence Augustine. (1922). The Idea of God: Historical, Critical, Constructive. New York: Macmillan. p. 214
  15. ^ Waterhouse, E. S. (1934). "The Concept of a Limited God: A Study in the Philosophy of Personalism by Rannie Belle Baker". Philosophy. 9 (36): 488–489. doi:10.1017/S0031819100030357.
  16. ^ Schiller, F. C. S. (1917). "Omnipotence". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. 18: 247–270. JSTOR 4543943.
  17. ^ Abel, Reuben. (1955). The Pragmatic Humanism of F. C. S. Schiller. King's Crown Press. pp. 132-133
  18. ^ a b Brightman, Edgar S. (1940). Historical Sketch of Theistic Finitism. In A Philosophy of Religion. New York: Prentice-Hall, Inc. pp. 286-301
  19. ^ Erickson, Millard J. (1998). Finitism: Rejection of Omnipotence. In Christian Theology. Baker Books. pp. 439-442. ISBN 978-0-8010-2182-4
  20. ^ Wagar, W. Warren. (2004). H. G. Wells: Traversing Time. Wesleyan University Press. p. 154. ISBN 978-0819567253
  21. ^ Knudson, Albert C. (1924). Present Tendencies in Religious Thought. The Abingdon Press. p. 306
  22. ^ a b Burrow, Rufus Jr. (2012). The Finite-Infinite God. In God and Human Dignity: The Personalism, Theology, and Ethics of Martin Luther King, Jr. University of Notre Dame Press. ISBN 978-0-268-02194-8
  23. ^ Hartshorne, Charles (1967). "The Dipolar Conception of Deity". The Review of Metaphysics. 21 (2): 273–289. JSTOR 20124563.
  24. ^ a b Ford, Lewis S. (1978). "In What Sense is God Infinite?: A Process Perspective" (PDF). The Thomist: A Speculative Quarterly Review. 42 (1): 1–13. doi:10.1353/tho.1978.0033.
  25. ^ Ferm, Vergilius Ture Anselm. (1959). An Encyclopedia of Religion. Littlefield, Adams & Co. pp. 279-280
  26. ^ Michael, Martin. (1990). The Finite God Theodicy. In Atheism: A Philosophical Justification. Temple University Press. pp. 436-438. ISBN 0-87722-642-3
  27. ^ Dilley, Frank B. (2000). "A Finite God Reconsidered". International Journal for Philosophy of Religion. 47 (1): 29–41. doi:10.1023/A:1003838717365. JSTOR 40036433. S2CID 169766359.

Further reading

[edit]