Jump to content

Zeno of Elea: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
No edit summary
The dates were so wrong
Line 25: Line 25:


== Life =='''
== Life =='''
Little is known for certain about Zeno's life. Although written nearly a century after Zeno's death, the primary source of biographical information about Zeno is the dialogue of [[Plato]] called the [[Parmenides (dialogue)|''Parmenides'']].<ref>[[Plato]] (370 BC). [http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/parmenides.html ''Parmenides''], translated by Benjamin Jowett. Internet Classics Archive.</ref> In the dialogue, Plato describes a visit to [[History of Athens|Athens]] by Zeno and Parmenides, at a time when Parmenides is "about 65," Zeno is "nearly 40" (''Parmenides'' 127b) and [[Socrates]] is "a very young man" (''Parmenides'' 127c). Assuming an age for Socrates of around 20, and taking the date of Socrates' birth as 456 bc. gives an approximate date of birth for Zeno of 456 bc. ad
Little is known for certain about Zeno's life. Although written nearly a century after Zeno's death, the primary source of biographical information about Zeno is the dialogue of [[Plato]] called the [[Parmenides (dialogue)|''Parmenides'']].<ref>[[Plato]] (370 BC). [http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/parmenides.html ''Parmenides''], translated by Benjamin Jowett. Internet Classics Archive.</ref> In the dialogue, Plato describes a visit to [[History of Athens|Athens]] by Zeno and Parmenides, at a time when Parmenides is "about 65," Zeno is "nearly 40" (''Parmenides'' 127b) and [[Socrates]] is "a very young man" (''Parmenides'' 127c). Assuming an age for Socrates of around 20, and taking the date of Socrates' birth as 469 bc. gives an approximate date of birth for Zeno of 490 bc. ad


Plato says that Zeno was "tall and fair to look upon" and was "in the days of his youth … reported to have been beloved by Parmenides" (''Parmenides'' 127b).
Plato says that Zeno was "tall and fair to look upon" and was "in the days of his youth … reported to have been beloved by Parmenides" (''Parmenides'' 127b).

Revision as of 21:04, 2 November 2010

Zeno of Elea
Bornca. 490 BC
Diedca. 430 BC (aged around 60)
EraPre-Socratic philosophy
RegionWestern Philosophy
SchoolEleatic school
Main interests
Metaphysics, Ontology
Notable ideas
Zeno's paradoxes

Zeno of Elea (Template:PronEng, Greek: Ζήνων ὁ Ἐλεάτης) (ca. 490 BC? – ca. 430 BC?) was a pre-Socratic Greek philosopher of southern Italy and a member of the Eleatic School founded by Parmenides. Aristotle called him the inventor of the dialectic.[1] He is best known for his paradoxes, which Bertrand Russell has described as "immeasurably subtle and profound".[2]

== Life == Little is known for certain about Zeno's life. Although written nearly a century after Zeno's death, the primary source of biographical information about Zeno is the dialogue of Plato called the Parmenides.[3] In the dialogue, Plato describes a visit to Athens by Zeno and Parmenides, at a time when Parmenides is "about 65," Zeno is "nearly 40" (Parmenides 127b) and Socrates is "a very young man" (Parmenides 127c). Assuming an age for Socrates of around 20, and taking the date of Socrates' birth as 469 bc. gives an approximate date of birth for Zeno of 490 bc. ad

Plato says that Zeno was "tall and fair to look upon" and was "in the days of his youth … reported to have been beloved by Parmenides" (Parmenides 127b).

Other perhaps less reliable details of Zeno's life are given by Diogenes Laërtius in his Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers,[4] where it is reported that he was the son of Teleutagoras, but the adopted son of Parmenides, was "skilled to argue both sides of any question, the universal critic," and that he was arrested and perhaps killed at the hands of a tyrant of Elea.

According to Plutarch, Zeno attempted to kill the tyrant Demylus, and failing to do so, "with his own teeth bit off his tongue, he spit it in the tyrant’s face."[5] 'Bold text

Works

Although many ancient writers refer to the writings of Zeno, none of his writings survive intact.

Plato says that Zeno's writings were "brought to Athens for the first time on the occasion of" the visit of Zeno and Parmenides (Parmenides 127c). Plato also has Zeno say that this work, "meant to protect the arguments of Parmenides" (Parmenides 128c), was written in Zeno's youth, stolen, and published without his consent (Parmenides 128e). Plato has Socrates paraphrase the "first thesis of the first argument" of Zeno's work as follows: "if being is many, it must be both like and unlike, and this is impossible, for neither can the like be unlike, nor the unlike like" (Parmenides 127d,e).

According to Proclus in his Commentary on Plato's Parmenides, Zeno produced "not less than forty arguments revealing contradictions" (p. 29), but only nine are now known.

Zeno's arguments are perhaps the first examples of a method of proof called reductio ad absurdum, literally meaning to reduce to the absurd. Parmenides is said[citation needed] to be the first individual to implement this style of argument. This form of argument soon became known as the epicheirema (ἐπιχείρημα). In Book VII of his Topica, Aristotle says that an epicheirema is a dialectical syllogism. It is a connected piece of reasoning which an opponent has put forward as true. The disputant sets out to break down the dialectical syllogism. This destructive method of argument was maintained by him to such a degree that Seneca the Younger commented a few centuries later, If I accede to Parmenides there is nothing left but the One; if I accede to Zeno, not even the One is left.[6]

Zeno of Elea shows Youths the Doors to Truth and Falsity (Veritas et Falsitas). Fresco in the Library of El Escorial, Madrid.

Zeno's paradoxes

Zeno's paradoxes have puzzled, challenged, influenced, inspired, infuriated, and amused philosophers, mathematicians, and physicists for over two millennia. The most famous are the so-called "arguments against motion" described by Aristotle in his Physics.[7]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Cited in Diogenes Laërtius 8.57 and 9.25.
  2. ^ Russell, p. 347: "In this capricious world nothing is more capricious than posthumous fame. One of the most notable victims of posterity's lack of judgement is the Eleatic Zeno. Having invented four arguments all immeasurably subtle and profound, the grossness of subsequent philosophers pronounced him to be a mere ingenious juggler, and his arguments to be one and all sophisms. After two thousand years of continual refutation, these sophisms were reinstated, and made the foundation of a mathematical renaissance..."
  3. ^ Plato (370 BC). Parmenides, translated by Benjamin Jowett. Internet Classics Archive.
  4. ^ Diogenes Laërtius. The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, literally translated by C.D. Yonge. London: Henry G. Bohn, 1853. Scanned and edited for Peithô's Web.
  5. ^ Plutarch, Against Colotes
  6. ^ Zeno in The Presocratics, Philip Wheelwright ed., The Odyssey Press, 1966, Pages 106-107.
  7. ^ Aristotle (350 BC). Physics, translated by R.P. Hardie and R.K. Gaye. Internet Classics Archive.

References

  • Plato; Fowler, Harold North (1925) [1914]. Plato in twelve volumes. 8, The Statesman.(Philebus).(Ion). Loeb Classical Library. trans. W. R. M. Lamb. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard U.P. ISBN 9780434991648. OCLC 222336129.
  • Proclus; Morrow, Glenn R.; Dillon, John M. (1992) [1987]. Proclus' Commentary on Plato's Parmenides. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. ISBN 9780691020891. OCLC 27251522.
  • Russell, Bertrand (1996) [1903]. The Principles of Mathematics. New York, NY: Norton. ISBN 9780393314045. OCLC 247299160.
  • Hornschemeier, Paul (2007). The Three Paradoxes. Seattle, WA: Fantagraphics Books.

Further reading

Template:Persondata