Jump to content

Catharsis: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
revert unconstructive edits; please discuss at talk page
Wran (talk | contribs)
Undid revision 551892301 by Omnipaedista (talk)revert from misleading, oversimplified, personal pov edit
Line 2: Line 2:
{{Distinguish|Cathexis}}
{{Distinguish|Cathexis}}
{{Confusing|date=November 2012}}
{{Confusing|date=November 2012}}
'''Catharsis''' (from the Greek {{lang|el|[[wiktionary:κάθαρσις|κάθαρσις]]}} {{transl|el|''katharsis''}} meaning "purification" or "cleansing"), is a sudden emotional breakdown or climax that constitutes overwhelming feelings of great pity, sorrow, laughter, or any extreme change in emotion that results in renewal, restoration, and revitalization.
'''Catharsis''', (Katharsis) a transliteration of ancient Greek {{lang|el|[[wiktionary:κάθαρσις|κάθαρσις]]}} bears a range of meanings such as "purgation," "purification," "cleansing, and "clarification." It represents the wide range of effects that philosphers and critics have suggested take place under the stimulus of powerful and effective artistic representations. It has most commonly been applied to an effect of the emotions of pity and fear in tragedy but it can be used more widely to recognize the effect of other art forms on the emotiona they evoke or any marked change in feeling that results in such effects as renewal, restoration, and revitalization.


==Dramatic uses==
==Dramatic uses==

Revision as of 14:22, 24 April 2013

Catharsis, (Katharsis) a transliteration of ancient Greek κάθαρσις bears a range of meanings such as "purgation," "purification," "cleansing, and "clarification." It represents the wide range of effects that philosphers and critics have suggested take place under the stimulus of powerful and effective artistic representations. It has most commonly been applied to an effect of the emotions of pity and fear in tragedy but it can be used more widely to recognize the effect of other art forms on the emotiona they evoke or any marked change in feeling that results in such effects as renewal, restoration, and revitalization.

Dramatic uses

Catharsis is a term in dramatic art that describes the effect of tragedy (or comedy and quite possibly other artistic forms)[1] principally on the audience (although some have speculated on characters in the drama as well). Nowhere does Aristotle explain the meaning of "catharsis" as he is using that term in the definition of tragedy in the Poetics (1449b21-28). G.F. Else "shows that both of these views have no basis in the text of the Poetics, but are derived from the use of catharsis in other Aristotelian and non-Aristotelian contexts," scholar Leon Golden writes.[2] For this reason a number of diverse interpretations of the meaning of this term have arisen. D.W. Lucas (Aristotle: Poetics, Oxford, 1968)[3] in an authoritative edition of the Poetics comprehensively covers the various nuances inherent in the meaning of the term in an Appendix devoted to "Pity, Fear, and Katharsis". Lucas (pp. 276–79) recognizes the possibility of catharsis bearing some aspect of the meaning of "purification, purgation, and 'intellectual clarification'" although his discussion of these terms is not always, or perhaps often, in the precise form with which other influential scholars have treated them. And Lucas himself does not accept any one of these interpretations as his own but adopts a rather different one based on "the Greek doctrine of Humours" which has not received wide subsequent acceptance. Purgation and purification, used in previous centuries, as the common interpretations of catharsis are still in wide use today.[4] More recently, in the twentieth century, the interpretation of catharsis as "intellectual clarification" has arisen as a rival to the older views in describing the effect of catharsis on members of the audience.

Purgation and purification

In his works prior to Poetics, Aristotle had used the term catharsis purely in its medical sense (usually referring to the evacuation of the katamenia—the menstrual fluid or other reproductive material).[5] Here, however, he employs it as a medical metaphor. F. L. Lucas maintains, therefore, that purification and cleansing are not proper translations for catharsis; that it should rather be rendered as purgation. "It is the human soul that is purged of its excessive passions."[6] Gerald F. Else, "Aristotle's Poetics: The Argument, Cambridge, Mass., 1957, p.440 made the following argument against the "purgation" theory: "It presupposes that we come to the tragic drama (unconsciously, if you will) as patients to be cured, relieved, restored to psychic health. But there is not a word to support this in the "Poetics", not a hint that the end of drama is to cure or alleviate pathological states. On the contrary it is evident in every line of the work that Aristotle is presupposing "normal" auditors, normal states of mind and feeling, normal emotional and aesthetic experience."

Lessing sidesteps the medical attribution. He translates catharsis as a purification, an experience that brings pity and fear into their proper balance: "In real life," he explained, "men are sometimes too much addicted to pity or fear, sometimes too little; tragedy brings them back to a virtuous and happy mean."[7] Tragedy is then a corrective; through watching tragedy, the audience learns how to feel these emotions at proper levels.

Intellectual clarification

In the twentieth century something like a paradigm shift took place in the interpretation of catharsis with a number of scholars contributing to the argument in support of the intellectual clarification concept. The following works can be usefully consulted in this regard: L. Golden, "Aristotle on Tragic and Comic Mimesis," Atlanta, 1992, S. Halliwell, "Aristotle's Poetics," London, 1986, D. Keesey, "On Some Recent Interpretations of Catharsis, "The Classical World", (1979) 72.4, 193-205. The clarification theory of catharsis would be fully consistent, as other interpretations are not, with Aristotle's argument in chapter 4 of the Poetics (1448b4-17) that the essential pleasure of mimesis is the intellectual pleasure of "learning and inference".

It is generally understood that Aristotle's theory of mimesis and catharsis are responses to Plato's negative view of artistic mimesis on an audience. Plato argued that the most common forms of artistic mimesis were designed to evoke from an audience powerful emotions such as pity, fear, and ridicule which override the rational control that defines the highest level of our humanity and lead us to wallow unacceptably in orgies of emotion and passion. Aristotle's concept of catharsis, in all of the major senses attributed to it, contradicts Plato's view by providing a mechanism that generates the rational control of irrational emotions. All of the commonly held interpretations of catharsis, purgation, purification, and clarification are considered by most scholars to represent a homeopathic process in which pity and fear accomplish the catharsis of emotions like themselves. For an alternate view of catharsis as an allopathic process in which pity and fear produce a catharsis of emotions unlike pity and fear, see E. Belfiore, "Tragic Pleasures: Aristotle on Plot and Emotion." Princeton, 1992, 260 ff.

Achieving catharsis in literary analysis

Catharsis can only be achieved by an accurate and persuasive analysis of character and action in a drama. Below is such an analysis by the distinguished British scholar E.R. Dodds directed at the character of Oedipus in the paradigmatic Aristotelian tragedy, Oedipus Rex:

"...what fascinates us is the spectacle of a man freely choosing, from the highest motives a series of actions which lead to his own ruin. Oedipus might have left the plague to take its course; but pity for the sufferings of his people compelled him to consult Delphi. When Apollo's word came back, he might still have left the murder of Laius uninvestigated; but piety and justice required him to act. He need not have forced the truth from the reluctant Theban herdsman; but because he cannot rest content with a lie, he must tear away the last veil from the illusion in which he has lived so long. Teiresias, Jocasta the herdsman, each in turn tries to stop him, but in vain; he must read the last riddle, the riddle of his own life. The immediate cause of Oedipus' ruin is not "fate or "the gods"—no oracle said that he must discover the truth—and still less does it lie in his own weakness; what causes his ruin is his own strength and courage, his loyalty to Thebes, and his loyalty to the truth." (E.R. Dodds, "On Misunderstanding the Oedipus Rex," "Greece and Rome 13 ((1966) p.43."

The cogent logic of Dodds' analysis makes it possible for us to argue for the existence of a catharsis for diverse reasons based on any of the three major interpretations we have discussed: purgation, purification, intellectual clarification.

There have been, for political or aesthetic reasons, deliberate attempts made to subvert the effect of catharsis in theatre. For example, Bertolt Brecht viewed catharsis as a pap (pablum) for the bourgeois theatre audience, and designed dramas which left significant emotions unresolved, intending to force social action upon the audience. Brecht reasoned that the absence of a cathartic resolution would require the audience to take political action in the real world, in order to fill the emotional gap they had experienced vicariously. This technique can be seen as early as his agit-prop play The Measures Taken.[citation needed]

"Catharsis" before tragedy

Catharsis before the sixth-century rise of tragedy is, for the Western World, essentially a historical footnote to the Aristotelian conception. The practice of purification had not yet appeared in Homer, as later Greek commentators noted:[8] the Aithiopis, an epic set in the Trojan War cycle, narrates the purification of Achilles after his murder of Thersites. Catharsis describes the result of measures taken to cleanse away blood-guilt—"blood is purified through blood" (Burkert 1992:56), a process in the development of Hellenistic culture in which the oracle of Delphi took a prominent role. The classic example—Orestes—belongs to tragedy, but the procedure given by Aeschylus is ancient: the blood of a sacrificed piglet is allowed to wash over the blood-polluted man, and running water washes away the blood.[9] The identical ritual is represented, Burkert informs us (1992:57), on a krater found at Canicattini, wherein it is shown being employed to cure the daughters of Proetus from their madness, caused by some ritual transgression. To the question of whether the ritual obtains atonement for the subject, or just healing, Burkert answers: "To raise the question is to see the irrelevance of this distinction" (1992:57).

Therapeutic uses

In psychology, the term was first employed by Sigmund Freud's colleague Josef Breuer (1842–1925), who developed a "cathartic" treatment using hypnosis for persons suffering from hysterical symptoms. While under hypnosis, Breuer's patients were able to recall traumatic experiences, and through the process of expressing the original emotions that had been repressed and forgotten, they were relieved of their symptoms. Catharsis was also central to Freud's concept of psychoanalysis, but he replaced hypnosis with free association.[10]

The term catharsis has also been adopted by modern psychotherapy, particularly Freudian psychoanalysis, to describe the act of expressing, or more accurately, experiencing the deep emotions often associated with events in the individual's past which had originally been repressed or ignored, and had never been adequately addressed or experienced.

There has been much debate about the use of catharsis in the reduction of anger. Some scholars believe that "blowing off steam" may reduce physiological stress in the short term, but this reduction may act as a reward mechanism, reinforcing the behavior and promoting future outbursts.[11][12][13][14] However, other studies have suggested that using violent media may decrease hostility under periods of stress.[15] Moreover, Ed Watkins findings on the experiential retrieval of emotions seems to confirm a beneficial role of some kind of catharsis.[16] Interestingly, there's no "one size fits all" definition of "catharsis",[17] and this doesn't allow a clear definition of its use in therapeutical terms.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Thomas Scheff PhD Professor Emeritus of Sociology and Anthropology (1979). Catharsis in Healing, Ritual, and Drama. University of California, USA. ISBN 0-595-15237-6.
  2. ^ Golden, Leon. "Catharsis". Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association. 93: 51–60. {{cite journal}}: |access-date= requires |url= (help)
  3. ^ Lucas, DW (1977). Aristotle: Poetics. Oxford University Press, USA. ISBN 978-0198140245.
  4. ^ Michael P. Nichols, Ph D. (8 June 1977). Catharsis in Psychotherapy. John Wiley & Sons Inc, New York. ISBN 978-0470990643. {{cite book}}: Unknown parameter |coauthor= ignored (|author= suggested) (help)
  5. ^ Belifiore, Elizabeth S. Tragic Pleasures: Aristotle on Plot and Emotion, page 300. Princeton UP, 1992
  6. ^ Lucas, F.L. Tragedy in Relation to Aristotle's Poetics, page 24
  7. ^ Lucas, F.L. Tragedy in Relation to Aristotle's Poetics, page 23. Hogarth, 1928
  8. ^ Walter Burkert, 1992. The Orientalizing Revolution: Near Eastern Influence on Greek Culture in the Early Archaic Age, p.56. (Harvard University Press). This sub-section depends largely on Burkert.
  9. ^ Burkert notes parallels with a bilingual Akkadian-Sumerian ritual text: "the knowledgeable specialist, the sacrificial piglet, slaughter, contact with blood, and the subsequent cleansing with water" (1992:58).
  10. ^ Strickland, Bonnie, ed. (2001). Catharsis. Gale.
  11. ^ Bushman, BJ (1999-03). "Catharsis, aggression, and persuasive influence: self-fulfilling or self-defeating prophecies?". Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 76 (3): 367–376. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.76.3.367. PMID 10101875. {{cite journal}}: Check date values in: |date= (help); Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help)
  12. ^ Gannon, Theresa A. (2007). Aggressive offenders' cognition: theory, research, and practice. Vol. 35. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-0-470-03401-9. {{cite book}}: |work= ignored (help); Unknown parameter |editors= ignored (|editor= suggested) (help)
  13. ^ Baron, Robert A.; Deborah R. Richardson (2004). "Catharsis: does "getting it out of one's system" really help?". Human Aggression. Springer. ISBN 978-0-306-48434-6.
  14. ^ Denzler, Markus (2009-01). "How goal-fulfillment decreases aggression". Journal of Experimental Social Psychology. 45 (1): 90–100. doi:10.1016/j.jesp.2008.08.021. {{cite journal}}: Check date values in: |date= (help); Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help)
  15. ^ Ferguson, Christopher (2010). "The Hitman study: Violent video game exposure effects on aggressive behavior, hostile feelings and depression" (PDF). European Psychologist. 15 (2): 99–108. {{cite journal}}: Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help)
  16. ^ http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/15325900
  17. ^ http://primal-page.com/cathar.htm

References