Fallacy
A fallacy is an argument which provides poor reasoning in support of its conclusion. Fallacies differ from other bad arguments in that many people find them psychologically persuasive. That is, people will mistakenly take a fallacious argument to provide good reasons to believe its conclusion. An argument can be fallacious whether or not its conclusion is true.
Fallacies can be categorized in a number of ways. For example, formal fallacies rely on an incorrect logical step; informal fallacies do not rely on incorrect logical deduction. Verbal fallacies use some property of language to mislead, for example, ambiguity or verbosity.
Fallacies are also often concerned with causality, which is not strictly addressed by logic. They may also involve implicit (or unstated) assumptions.
Fallacies often exploit emotional triggers in the listener or interlocutor. For example, an argument may appeal to patriotism or family or may exploit an intellectual weakness of the listener. Fallacious arguments may also take advantage of social relationships between people. For example, citing an important individual's support for a view on any other subject than the one discussed in order to encourage listeners to either agree or disagree with that person.
Considered by themselves, fallacies can often seem obviously bad. However, arguments are often structured using rhetorical patterns that obscure the logical argument - deliberately or not - making fallacies difficult to diagnose. Also, the component parts of the fallacy may be spread over a large period of time.
Material fallacies
The taxonomy of material fallacies is widely adopted by modern logicians and is based on that of Aristotle, Organon (Sophistici elenchi). This taxonomy is as follows:
- Fallacy of Accident: a generalization that disregards exceptions
- Example
- Argument: Cutting people is a crime. Surgeons cut people. Therefore, surgeons are criminals.
- Problem: Cutting people is only sometimes a crime.
- Also called destroying the exception, a dicto simpliciter ad dictum secundum quid
- Example
- Converse Fallacy of Accident: argues from a special case to a general rule
- Example
- Argument: Every swan I have seen is white, so it must be true that all swans are white.
- Problem: What one has seen is a subset of the entire set. One cannot have seen all swans.
- Also called reverse accident, destroying the exception, a dicto secundum quid ad dictum simpliciter
- Example
- Irrelevant Conclusion: diverts attention away from a fact in dispute rather than address it directly.
- Example
- Argument: Kim Jong Il believes that war is justifiable therefore it must be justifiable.
- Problem: Kim Jong Il can be wrong. (In particular this is an appeal to authority).
- Special cases:
- purely personal considerations (argumentum ad hominem),
- popular sentiment (argumentum ad populum--appeal to the majority; appeal to loyalty.),
- fear (argumentum ad baculum),
- conventional propriety (argumentum ad verecundiam--appeal to authority)
- to arouse pity for getting one's conclusion accepted (argumentum ad misericordiam)
- proving the proposition under dispute without any certain proof (argumentum ad ignoratiam)
- Also called Ignoratio Elenchi, a "red herring"
- Example
- Affirming the Consequent: draws a conclusion from premises that do not support that conclusion by assuming Q implies P on the basis that P implies Q
- Example:
- Argument: If a person runs barefoot, then his feet hurt. Socrates' feet hurt. Therefore, Socrates ran barefoot.
- Problem: Other things, such as tight sandals, can result in sore feet.
- Example:
- Denying the antecedent: draws a conclusion from premises that do not support that conclusion by assuming Not P implies Not Q on the basis that P implies Q
- Example
- Argument: If it is raining out, it must be cloudy. It is not raining out. Therefore, it is not cloudy.
- Problem: There does not have to be rain to have clouds.
- Example
- Begging the question: demonstrates a conclusion by means of premises that assume that conclusion.
- Example
- Argument: Billy must be telling the truth, because I have heard him say the same thing many times before.
- Problem: Billy may be consistent in what he says, but he may have been lying the whole time.
- Also called Petitio Principii, Circulus in Probando, arguing in a circle, assuming the answer. It is worth noting that a circular argument may actually be both logically and factually correct. Circularity itself has no bearing on the truth or falseness of the argument at all, the fallacy is to use a circular argument as a proof of truth.
- Example
- Fallacy of False Cause or Non Sequitur: incorrectly assumes one thing is the cause of another. Non Sequitur is Latin for "It does not follow."
- Example
- Argument: Our nation will prevail because God is great.
- Problem: There is no necessary cause and effect between God's greatness and a nation prevailing. Simply because God can be considered great does not mean a nation will prevail.
- Special cases
- post hoc ergo propter hoc: believing that temporal succession implies a causal relation.
- Example
- Argument: After my son had his vaccine, he developed autism. Therefore, the vaccine caused autism.
- Problem: The characteristics of autism may generally become noticeable at the age just following the typical age children receive vaccinations.
- Example
- cum hoc ergo propter hoc: believing that happenstance implies causal relation (aka as fallacy of causation versus correlation: assumes that correlation implies causation).
- Example
- Argument: More cows die in India in the summer months. More ice cream is consumed in summer months. Therefore, the consumption of ice cream in the summer months is killing Indian cows.
- Problem: It is hotter in the summer, resulting in both the death of cows and the consumption of ice cream.
- Example
- post hoc ergo propter hoc: believing that temporal succession implies a causal relation.
- Example
- Fallacy of Many Questions: groups more than one question in the form of a single question
- Example
- Argument: Is it true that you no longer beat your wife?
- Problem: A yes or no answer will still be an admission of guilt to beating your wife at some point.
- Also called Plurium Interrogationum
- Example
- Straw man: A straw man argument is an informal fallacy based on misrepresentation of an opponent's position.
- Example
- Argument Person A: Sunny days are good.
- Argument Person B: If all days were sunny, we'd never have rain, and without rain, we'd have famine and death. You are obviously wrong.
- Problem: B has falsely framed A's argument to imply that A says that only sunny days are good, and has argued against that assertion instead of the assertion A has made.
- Example
Example
Consider the following argument which claims to prove that pie is delicious:
- Pie is food.
- Food is delicious.
- Therefore, pie is delicious.
This particular argument has the form of a categorical syllogism. In this case "Pie is food" and "Food is delicious" act as premises. The first assumption is almost true by definition: pie is a foodstuff edible by humans. The second assumption is less clear; it could mean any one of the following:
- All food is delicious.
- One particular type of food is delicious.
- Most food is delicious.
- To me, all food is delicious.
- Some food is delicious.
Only the first interpretation validates the second premise. If the interlocutor grants this interpretation then the argument is valid; the interlocutor is essentially conceding the point. However, the interlocutor is more likely to believe that some food is not delicious. In this case, the speaker must prove the assertion that pie is a unique type of universally delicious food. This is a disguised form of the original thesis. In this case, the speaker commits the logical fallacy of begging the question.
Verbal fallacies
Verbal fallacies are those in which a conclusion is obtained by improper or ambiguous use of words. They are generally classified as follows.
- Equivocation consists in employing the same word in two or more senses, e.g. in a syllogism, the middle term being used in one sense in the major and another in the minor premise, so that in fact there are four not three terms
- Example Argument: All heavy things have a great mass; this is heavy fog; therefore this fog has a great mass.
- Problem: Heavy describes more than just weight. In the case of fog it means that the fog is dense not that it has a great mass.
- Connotation fallacies occur when a dysphemistic word is substituted for the speaker's actual quote and used to discredit the argument. It is a form of attribution fallacy.
- Amphibology is the result of ambiguity of grammatical structure
- Example: The position of the adverb "only" in the a sentence starting with "He only said that" results in a sentence in which it is uncertain as to which of the other three words the speaker is intending to modify with the adverb.
- Fallacy of Composition "From Each to All". Arguing from some property of constituent parts, to the conclusion that the composite item has that property. This can be acceptable (i.e., not a fallacy) with certain arguments such as spatial arguments (e.g. "all the parts of the car are in the garage, therefore the car is in the garage")
- Example Argument: All the band members (constituent parts) are highly skilled, therefore the band (composite item) is highly skilled.
- Problem: The band members may be skilled musicians but not in the same styles of music.
- Division, the converse of the preceding, arguing from a property of the whole, to each constituent part
- Example Argument: "The university (the whole) is 700 years old, therefore, all the staff (each part) are 700 years old".
- Problem: Each and every person currently on staff is younger than 200 years. The university continues to exist even when, one by one, each and every person on the original staff leaves and is replaced by a younger person. See Theseus's Ship paradox.
- Proof by verbosity, sometimes colloquially referred to as argumentum verbosium - a rhetorical technique that tries to persuade by overwhelming those considering an argument with such a volume of material that the argument sounds plausible, superficially appears to be well-researched, and it is so laborious to untangle and check supporting facts that the argument might be allowed to slide by unchallenged.
- Accent, which occurs only in speaking and consists of emphasizing the wrong word in a sentence. e.g., "He is a fairly good pianist," according to the emphasis on the words, may imply praise of a beginner's progress, or an expert's deprecation of a popular hero, or it may imply that the person in question is a deplorable pianist.[citation needed]
- Figure of Speech, the confusion between the metaphorical and ordinary uses of a word or phrase.
- Example: The sailor was at home on the sea.
- Problem: The expression 'to be at home' does not literally mean that one's domicile is in that location.
- Fallacy of Misplaced Concretion, identified by Whitehead in his discussion of metaphysics, this refers to the reification of concepts which exist only in discourse.
Example 1
Tom argues:
- Joe is a good tennis player.
- Therefore, Joe is 'good', that is to say a 'morally' good person.
Here the problem is that the word good has different meanings, which is to say that it is an ambiguous word. In the premise, Tom says that Joe is good at some particular activity, in this case tennis. In the conclusion, Tom states that Joe is a morally good person. These are clearly two different senses of the word "good". The premise might be true but the conclusion can still be false: Joe might be the best tennis player in the world but a rotten person morally. However, it is not legitimate to infer he is a bad person on the ground there has been a fallacious argument on the part of Tom. Nothing concerning Joe's moral qualities is to be inferred from the premise. Appropriately, since it plays on an ambiguity, this sort of fallacy is called the fallacy of equivocation, that is, equating two incompatible terms or claims.
Example 2
One posits the argument:
- Nothing is better than eternal happiness.
- Eating a hamburger is better than nothing.
- Therefore, eating a hamburger is better than eternal happiness.
This argument has the appearance of an inference that applies transitivity of the two-placed relation is better than, which in this critique we grant is a valid property. The argument is an example of syntactic ambiguity. In fact, the first premise semantically does not predicate an attribute of the subject, as would for instance the assertion
- A potato is better than eternal happiness.
In fact it is semantically equivalent to the following universal quantification:
- Everything fails to be better than eternal happiness.
So instantiating this fact with eating a hamburger, it logically follows that
- Eating a hamburger fails to be better than eternal happiness.
Note that the premise A hamburger is better than nothing does not provide anything to this argument. This fact really means something such as
- Eating a hamburger is better than eating nothing at all.
Thus this is a fallacy of equivocation.
Deductive fallacy
In philosophy, the term logical fallacy properly refers to a formal fallacy: a flaw in the structure of a deductive argument which renders the argument invalid.
However, it is often used more generally in informal discourse to mean an argument which is problematic for any reason, and thus encompasses informal fallacies as well as formal fallacies. – valid but unsound claims or bad nondeductive argumentation – .
The presence of a formal fallacy in a deductive argument does not imply anything about the argument's premises or its conclusion (see fallacy fallacy). Both may actually be true, or even more probable as a result of the argument (e.g. appeal to authority), but the deductive argument is still invalid because the conclusion does not follow from the premises in the manner described. By extension, an argument can contain a formal fallacy even if the argument is not a deductive one; for instance an inductive argument that incorrectly applies principles of probability or causality can be said to commit a formal fallacy.
Formalisms and frameworks used to understand fallacies
A different approach to understanding and classifying fallacies is provided by argumentation theory; see for instance the van Eemeren, Grootendorst reference below. In this approach, an argument is regarded as an interactive protocol between individuals which attempts to resolve a disagreement. The protocol is regulated by certain rules of interaction, and violations of these rules are fallacies. Many of the fallacies in the list below are best understood as being fallacies in this sense.
Other systems of classification
Of other classifications of fallacies in general the most famous are those of Francis Bacon and J. S. Mill. Bacon (Novum Organum, Aph. 33, 38 sqq.) divided fallacies into four Idola (Idols, i.e. False Appearances), which summarize the various kinds of mistakes to which the human intellect is prone. With these should be compared the Offendicula of Roger Bacon, contained in the Opus maius, pt. i. J. S. Mill discussed the subject in book v. of his Logic, and Jeremy Bentham's Book of Fallacies (1824) contains valuable remarks. See Rd. Whateley's Logic, bk. v.; A. de Morgan, Formal Logic (1847) ; A. Sidgwick, Fallacies (1883) and other textbooks.
Fallacies in the media and politics
Fallacies are used frequently by pundits in the media and politics. When one politician says to another, "You don't have the moral authority to say X", this could be an example of the argumentum ad hominem or personal attack fallacy; that is, attempting to disprove X, not by addressing validity of X but by attacking the person who asserted X. Arguably, the politician is not even attempting to make an argument against X, but is instead offering a moral rebuke against the interlocutor. For instance, if X is the assertion:
- The military uniform is a symbol of national strength and honor.
Then ostensibly, the politician is not trying to prove the contrary assertion. If this is the case, then there is no logically fallacious argument, but merely a personal opinion about moral worth. Thus identifying logical fallacies may be difficult and dependent upon context.
In the opposite direction is the fallacy of argument from authority. A classic example is the ipse dixit—"He himself said it" argument—used throughout the Middle Ages in reference to Aristotle. A modern instance is "celebrity spokespersons" in advertisements: a product is good and you should buy/use/support it because your favorite celebrity endorses it.
An appeal to authority is always a logical fallacy, though it can be an appropriate form of rational argument if, for example, it is an appeal to expert testimony [citation needed] . In this case, the expert witness must be recognized as such and all parties must agree that the testimony is appropriate to the circumstances. This form of argument is common in legal situations.
By definition, arguments with logical fallacies are invalid, but they can often be (re)written in such a way that they fit a valid argument form. The challenge to the interlocutor is, of course, to discover the false premise, i.e. the premise that makes the argument unsound.
See also
- List of fallacies
- Attacking Faulty Reasoning
- Truth
- Evidence
- List of cognitive biases
- Cognitive distortion
- Sophistry
References
This article includes a list of references, related reading, or external links, but its sources remain unclear because it lacks inline citations. (January 2009) |
- Aristotle, On Sophistical Refutations, De Sophistici Elenchi.
- William of Ockham, Summa of Logic (ca. 1323) Part III.4.
- John Buridan, Summulae de dialectica Book VII.
- Francis Bacon, the doctrine of the idols in Novum Organum Scientiarum, Aphorisms concerning The Interpretation of Nature and the Kingdom of Man, XXIIIff.
- The Art of Controversy | Die Kunst, Recht zu behalten - The Art Of Controversy (bilingual), by Arthur Schopenhauer (also known as "Schopenhauers 38 stratagems")
- John Stuart Mill, A System of Logic - Raciocinative and Inductive. Book 5, Chapter 7, Fallacies of Confusion.
- C. L. Hamblin, Fallacies. Methuen London, 1970.
- Fearnside, W. Ward and William B. Holther, Fallacy: The Counterfeit of Argument, 1959.
- Vincent F. Hendricks, Thought 2 Talk: A Crash Course in Reflection and Expression, New York: Automatic Press / VIP, 2005, ISBN 87-991013-7-8
- D. H. Fischer, Historians' Fallacies: Toward a Logic of Historical Thought, Harper Torchbooks, 1970.
- Douglas N. Walton, Informal logic: A handbook for critical argumentation. Cambridge University Press, 1989.
- F. H. van Eemeren and R. Grootendorst, Argumentation, Communication and Fallacies: A Pragma-Dialectical Perspective, Lawrence Erlbaum and Associates, 1992.
- Warburton Nigel, Thinking from A to Z, Routledge 1998.
- T. Edward Damer. Attacking Faulty Reasoning, 5th Edition, Wadsworth, 2005. ISBN 0-534-60516-8
- Sagan, Carl, "The Demon-Haunted World: Science As a Candle in the Dark". Ballantine Books, March 1997 ISBN 0-345-40946-9, 480 pgs. 1996 hardback edition: Random House, ISBN 0-394-53512-X, xv+457 pages plus addenda insert (some printings). Ch.12.
External links
- Fallacy files contains categorization of fallacies with examples.
- 42 informal logical fallacies explained by Dr. Michael C. Labossiere (including examples)
- Humbug! The skeptic’s field guide to spotting fallacies in thinking – textbook on fallacies
- List of fallacies with clear examples
- Logical Fallacies and the Art of Debate
- Logical Fallacies.Info
- An Informal Fallacy Primer
- Stephen Downes Guide to the Logical Fallacies
- BadArguments.org