Comparison of voting rules
A joint Politics and Economics series |
Social choice and electoral systems |
---|
Mathematics portal |
Electoral systems are the rules for conducting elections. Comparisons between different systems can focus on different aspects: on suffrage or rules for voter eligibility; on candidate eligibility and the rules governing political parties; on the way elections are scheduled, sequenced, and combined; or on the rules for determining the winner within a given election (also called the "election rule" or "voting method").
With electoral systems one can also focus on the internal voting mechanism that reviews, for instance, in how far the voters' choices are reflected in the outcome. The mechanism can help show that candidates need to focus differently to improve their odds of winning a seat.
Direct Comparisons Between First-Past-The-Post and Proportional Voting
Though there are many different systems, including a large number of combinations of systems, there are two voting systems that are truly not like the other; it can therefore be helpful in viewing the differences among just these two to attain a quick understanding about electoral systems and why the differences are important indeed. The two systems are:
First-past-the-post: A single candidate wins the seat of a single district, county or nation, by getting the most votes in a geographical area.
Proportional voting: The entire outcome of votes in a municipality or nation translates collectively into the outcome of the seats.
- Where a geographical connection is automatically incorporated in the electoral outcomes in nations with first-part-the-post (or winner-take-all), there is no certainty about geographical representation in proportional voting. It may play a role with the selection of the candidates, but when geographically inclined voters need to be alert whether candidates are from their own region or area and vote appropriately.
- In first-past-the-post, voters are represented by a single representative, whether they voted for the candidate or someone else. With proportional voting, virtually every voter can point to the representative they voted for.
- Decisions made in first-past-the-post are won with a majority of the votes by people who won their seats with a majority of the constituents' votes. In effect, this strong dual mechanism diminishes the constituents' importance in the decision; when a seat can be obtained with 51 percent, and a decision can subsequently be made with 51 percent of the council members, the voters' input can be declared as diminished. Decisions made in proportional voting are won with a majority of the votes by the people who got their seats based on the direct distribution of the constituents' votes, virtually a 100 percent translation. In effect, this strong single mechanism (or weak dual mechanism) binds the representative close to his or her voters.
- Nations with a first-part-the-post system tend to have a stabilizing factor built in because third-party candidates will have a harder time beating out candidates from Party One and Party Two. Not often will cabinets be based on coalitions and can therefore be considered strong. In general, the two major parties will have no problem absorbing third-party issues as their own, covering any gaps both forgot to cover collectively. Both parties may therefore deliver close to what the voters want. Contrast this with the absence of built-in stability of proportional voting, in which two, sometimes three parties or more, need to cooperate to obtain a workable majority. From this, the character can become visible how one system is more accustomed to being directive whereas the other is more collaborative in nature.
- Nations with first-past-the-post have a focus on the center of the constituency. To win a seat, one must appeal to as many voters as possible, and extreme positions do not help in garnering as many votes as possible. Naturally, a weak position in important issues will not help a candidate either, but it can help not saying much about prickly situations. In proportional voting, the focus can follow a party-based policy, and the political message can be quite honest and direct. It is possible that a party obtains seats appealing to voters on the issue of animal rights only. One should recognize how in both systems candidates and representatives handle information differently because the win of the seat is based on a different system.
Mathematical criteria
Attitudes towards systems are highly influenced by the systems' impact on groups that one supports or opposes, which can make the objective comparison of electoral systems difficult. There are several ways to address this problem. For example, criteria can be defined mathematically, such that any voting method either passes or fails. This gives perfectly objective results, but their practical relevance is still arguable. Another approach is to define ideal criteria that no voting method passes perfectly, and then see how often or how close to passing various methods are over a large sample of simulated elections. This gives results which are practically relevant, but the method of generating the sample of simulated elections can still be arguably biased. A final approach is to create imprecisely defined criteria, and then assign a neutral body to evaluate each method according to these criteria. This approach can look at aspects of voting methods which the other two approaches miss, but both the definitions of these criteria and the evaluations of the methods are still inevitably subjective.
To compare methods fairly and independently of political ideologies, voting theorists use voting method criteria, which define potentially desirable properties of voting methods mathematically.
Using criteria to compare methods does not make the comparison completely objective. For example, it is relatively easy to devise a criterion that is met by one's preferred voting method, and by very few other methods. Doing this, one can then construct a biased argument for the criterion, instead of arguing directly for the method. There is no ultimate authority on which criteria should be considered.
The following criteria, which apply to single-winner voting methods, are considered to be desirable by many voting theorists:
Result criteria (absolute)
These are criteria that state that, if the set of ballots is a certain way, a certain candidate must or must not win.
- Majority criterion (MC)
- Will a candidate always win who is ranked as the unique favorite by a majority of voters? This criterion comes in two versions:
- Ranked majority criterion, in which an option which is merely preferred over the others by a majority must win. (Passing the ranked MC is denoted by "yes", because it implies also passing the following:)
- Rated majority criterion, in which only an option which is uniquely given a perfect rating by a majority must win. The ranked and rated MC are synonymous for ranked voting methods, but not for rated or graded ones. The ranked MC, but not the rated MC, is incompatible with the IIA criterion explained below.
- Mutual majority criterion (MMC)
- Will a candidate always win who is among a group of candidates ranked above all others by a majority of voters? This also implies the majority loser criterion – if a majority of voters prefers every other candidate over a given candidate, then does that candidate not win? Therefore, of the methods listed, all pass neither or both criteria, except for Borda, which passes Majority Loser while failing Mutual Majority.
- Condorcet criterion
- Will a candidate always win who beats every other candidate in pairwise comparisons? (This implies the majority criterion, above.)
- Condorcet loser criterion (cond. loser)
- Will a candidate never win who loses to every other candidate in pairwise comparisons?
Result criteria (relative)
These are criteria that state that, if a certain candidate wins in one circumstance, the same candidate must (or must not) win in a related circumstance.
- Independence of Smith-dominated alternatives (ISDA)
- Does the outcome never change if a Smith-dominated candidate is added or removed (assuming votes regarding the other candidates are unchanged)? Candidate C is Smith-dominated if there is some other candidate A such that C is beaten by A and every candidate B that is not beaten by A etc. Note that although this criterion is classed here as nominee-relative, it has a strong absolute component in excluding Smith-dominated candidates from winning. In fact, it implies all of the absolute criteria above.
- Independence of irrelevant alternatives (IIA)
- Does the outcome never change if a non-winning candidate is added or removed (assuming voter preferences regarding the other candidates are unchanged)?[1] For instance, plurality rule fails IIA; adding a candidate X can cause the winner to change from W to Y even though Y receives no more votes than before.
- Local independence of irrelevant alternatives (LIIA)
- Does the outcome never change if the alternative that would finish last is removed? (And could the alternative that finishes second fail to become the winner if the winner were removed?)
- Independence of clone alternatives (cloneproof)
- Does the outcome never change if non-winning candidates similar to an existing candidate are added? There are three different phenomena which could cause a method to fail this criterion:
- Spoilers
- Candidates which decrease the chance of any of the similar or clone candidates winning, also known as a spoiler effect.
- Teams
- Sets of similar candidates whose mere presence helps the chances of any of them winning.
- Crowds
- Additional candidates who affect the outcome of an election without either helping or harming the chances of their factional group, but instead affecting another group.
- Monotonicity criterion (monotone)
- If candidate W wins for one set of ballots, will W still always win if those ballots change to rank W higher? (This also implies that you cannot cause a losing candidate to win by ranking him lower.)
- Consistency criterion (CC)
- If candidate W wins for one set of ballots, will W still always win if those ballots change by adding another set of ballots where W also wins?
- Participation criterion (PC)
- Is voting honestly always better than not voting at all? (This is grouped with the distinct but similar Consistency Criterion in the table below.[2])
- Reversal symmetry (reversal)
- If individual preferences of each voter are inverted, does the original winner never win?
Ballot-counting criteria
These are criteria which relate to the process of counting votes and determining a winner.
- Polynomial time (polytime)
- Can the winner be calculated in a runtime that is polynomial in the number of candidates and linear in the number of voters?
- Resolvable
- Can the winner be calculated in almost all cases, without using any random processes such as flipping coins? That is, are exact ties, in which the winner could be one of two or more candidates, vanishingly rare in large elections?
- Summability (summable)
- Can the winner be calculated by tallying ballots at each polling station separately and simply adding up the individual tallies? The amount of information necessary for such tallies is expressed as an order function of the number of candidates N. Slower-growing functions such as O(N) or O(N2) make for easier counting, while faster-growing functions such as O(N!) might make it harder to catch fraud by election administrators.[citation needed]
Strategy criteria
These are criteria that relate to a voter's incentive to use certain forms of strategy. They could also be considered as relative result criteria; however, unlike the criteria in that section, these criteria are directly relevant to voters; the fact that a method passes these criteria can simplify the process of figuring out one's optimal strategic vote.
- Later-no-harm criterion, and later-no-help criterion
- Can voters be sure that adding a later preference to a ballot will not harm or help any candidate already listed?[3]
- No favorite betrayal (NFB)
- Can voters be sure that they do not need to rank any other candidate above their favorite in order to obtain a result they prefer?[4]
Ballot format
These are issues relating to the expressivity or information content of a valid ballot.
- Ballot type
- What information is the voter given on the ballot?
- Equal ranks
- Can a valid ballot express equal support for more than one candidate (and not just equal opposition to more than one)?
- Over 2 ranks
- Can a ballot express more than two levels of support/opposition for different candidates?
Weakness
Note on terminology: A criterion is said to be "weaker" than another when it is passed by more voting methods. Frequently, this means that the conditions for the criterion to apply are stronger. For instance, the majority criterion (MC) is weaker than the multiple majority criterion (MMC), because it requires that a single candidate, rather than a group of any size, should win. That is, any method which passes the MMC also passes the MC, but not vice versa; while any required winner under the MC must win under the MMC, but not vice versa.
Comparisons
Compliance of selected single-winner methods
The following table shows which of the above criteria are met by several single-winner methods.
Sort: | ||||||||||||||||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Criterion Method |
Majority | Maj. loser |
Mutual maj. |
Condorcet | Cond. loser |
Smith/ ISDA |
LIIA | IIA | Cloneproof | Monotone | Consistency | Participation | Reversal symmetry |
Polytime/ resolvable |
Summable | Later-no- | No favorite betrayal |
Ballot type |
Ranks | |||
Harm | Help | = | >2 | |||||||||||||||||||
Approval | Rated |
No | No | No |
No | No |
Yes | Yes |
Yes |
Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | O(N) | Yes | O(N) | No | Yes |
Yes | Approvals | Yes | No |
Borda count | No | Yes | No | No |
Yes | No | No | No | Teams | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | O(N) | Yes | O(N) | No | Yes | No | Ranking | No | Yes |
Bucklin | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | No | No | No | No | Yes | No | No | No | O(N) | Yes | O(N) | No | Yes | If equal preferences | Ranking | Yes | Yes |
Copeland | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No |
Teams, crowds |
Yes | No |
No |
Yes | O(N2) | No | O(N2) | No |
No | No |
Ranking | Yes | Yes |
IRV (AV) | Yes | Yes | Yes | No |
Yes | No |
No | No | Yes | No | No | No | No | O(N2) | Yes[g] | O(N!) |
Yes | Yes | No | Ranking | No | Yes |
Kemeny– |
Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | No |
Spoilers | Yes | No [i] |
No |
Yes | O(N!) | Yes | O(N2) |
No |
No | No |
Ranking | Yes | Yes |
Majority judgment |
Rated |
Yes |
No |
No |
No | No |
Yes | Yes |
Yes | Yes | No |
No |
Depends |
O(N) | Yes | O(N) |
No |
Yes | Yes | Scores |
Yes | Yes |
Minimax | Yes | No | No | Yes |
No | No | No | No |
Spoilers | Yes | No |
No |
No | O(N2) | Yes | O(N2) | No |
No | No |
Ranking | Yes | Yes |
Plurality/FPTP | Yes | No | No | No |
No | No |
No | No | Spoilers | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | O(N) | Yes | O(N) | — |
— |
No | Single mark | — | No |
Score voting | No | No | No | No |
No | No |
Yes | Yes |
Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | O(N) | Yes | O(N) | No | Yes | Yes | Scores | Yes | Yes |
Ranked pairs | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | No |
Yes | Yes | No |
No |
Yes | O(N4) | Yes | O(N2) | No |
No | No |
Ranking | Yes | Yes |
Runoff voting | Yes | Yes | No | No |
Yes | No |
No | No | Spoilers | No | No | No | No | O(N) |
Yes | O(N) |
Yes | Yes |
No | Single mark | — | No |
Schulze | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No |
Yes | Yes | No |
No |
Yes | O(N3) | Yes | O(N2) | No |
No | No |
Ranking | Yes | Yes |
STAR voting |
No[z] | Yes | No |
No |
Yes | No |
No | No | No | Yes | No | No | No |
O(N) | Yes | O(N2) | No | No | No[ac] | Scores | Yes | Yes |
Sortition, |
No | No | No | No |
No | No |
Yes | Yes | No | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | O(1) | No | O(1) | Yes | Yes | Yes | None | — | — |
Random ballot |
No | No | No | No |
No | No |
Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | O(N) | No | O(N) | Yes | Yes | Yes | Single mark | — | No |
This table is not comprehensive. For example, Coombs' method, which satisfies many of the criteria, is not included.
Compliance of party-based multi-winner methods
The following table shows which of the above criteria are met by several party-based multiple winner methods.
Criterion Method |
Proportional in theory | Proportional in practice | Semi-proportional
a majority of voters cannot force the result to be one such that they win all seats |
Not breakable voting method does not have a potential strategic voting feedback loop |
Monotone | Consistency | Participation | Are there tiers of members? | Is local representation required? | Is there voter selection of individual candidates? | Ballot Type |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
General ticket | No | No | No | No, 2 party domination | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | No — all seats are filled from one pre-determined list | Single mark for one list |
Closed party-list | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes (unless few seats or high first seat threshold) | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | No — the ranking of candidates within the party's list determines the order by which the party's seats are filled | Single mark for one list |
Relatively closed party-list | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes (unless few seats or high first seat threshold) | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | Yes — a candidate needs to obtain a Hare quota to be guaranteed a seat, otherwise the ranking of candidates within the party's list determines the order by which the party's seats are filled | Single or limited marks for candidates within one list |
More open party-list | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes (unless few seats or high first seat threshold) | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | Yes — a candidate needs to obtain a proportion of the votes to be guaranteed a seat, otherwise the ranking of candidates within the party's list determines the order by which the party's seats are filled | Single or limited marks for candidates within one list |
Most open party-list | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes (unless few seats or high first seat threshold) | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | Yes — the number of votes every candidate receives determines the order by which the party's seats are filled | Single mark for one candidate within one list |
Party-list with panachage | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes (unless few seats or high first seat threshold) | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | Yes — the number of votes every candidate receives determines the order by which the party's seats are filled | Limited marks for candidates within all lists |
Unmodified Mixed-member proportional | No, strategic voters can manipulate the number of overhang seats | Yes, excluding disproportionalities caused by overhang seats — proportional tier members are selected to compensate for any disproportionality caused by the constituency tier, based off the proportional tier votes only | Yes | No, 2 party domination among single winner seats and overhang manipulation | Yes | No | Yes | Yes — constituency tier and proportional tier | Yes — single-member constituencies | Yes — constituency candidates are selected by a single-winner method; selection of proportional tier members may be done by any of the party-list methods mentioned above | Single mark or ranking for one constituency candidate; proportional tier marks depend on the exact method used for selection |
Best-loser Mixed-member proportional | No, strategic voters can manipulate the number of overhang seats | Yes, excluding disproportionalities caused by overhang seats — proportional tier members are selected to compensate for any disproportionality caused by the constituency tier, based off the party's totals | Yes | No, overhang manipulation, also 2 party domination among single winner seats | Yes | No | Yes | Yes — constituency tier and proportional tier | Yes — single-member constituencies | Yes — constituency candidates are selected by a single-winner method; proportional tier members are selected by a party-list method | Single mark or ranking for one constituency candidate; proportional tier determined by the constituency tier results |
Parallel voting | No | No — constituency tier and proportional tier members are selected independently of each other | Yes | No, 2 party domination among single winner districts and overhang manipulation | Yes | No | Yes | Yes — constituency tier and proportional tier | Yes — single-member constituencies | Yes — constituency candidates are selected by a single-winner method; proportional tier members are selected by a party-list method | Single mark or ranking for one constituency candidate; proportional tier marks depend on the exact method used for selection |
Scorporo | ? | Partially — constituency tier and proportional tier members are selected independently of each other, but the constituency winners' votes are subtracted from their respective party lists' totals | Yes | ? | No | No | No | Yes — constituency tier and proportional tier | Yes — single-member constituencies | Yes — constituency candidates are selected by a single-winner method; proportional tier members are selected by a party-list method | Single mark or ranking for one constituency candidate; proportional tier marks depend on the exact method used for selection |
Majority bonus system | Technically no because of bonus | Technically no because of bonus | Yes | No, 2 party domination among parties competing for bonus | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes — proportional tier and bonus tier | No | Not necessarily — selection of proportional tier members may be done by any of the party-list methods mentioned above | Proportional tier marks depend on the exact method used for selection; bonus tier determined by the proportional tier results |
Majority jackpot system | ? | No — however, the non-jackpot tier seats are distributed proportionally. | Yes | ? | No — the party gaining the jackpot gains an advantage over all others; the jackpot turns into a disadvantage for the most-voted-for party if it gained a greater share of seats than the jackpot | Yes | Yes | Yes — proportional tier and jackpot tier | No | Not necessarily — selection of proportional tier members may be done by any of the party-list methods mentioned above | Proportional tier marks depend on the exact method used for selection; jackpot tier determined by the proportional tier results |
Dual-member proportional | No, strategic voters can theoretically manipulate the number of overhang seats | Yes | Yes | ? | No | Yes | Yes | No | Yes — dual-member constituencies | Yes — the candidate with the most votes is guaranteed a seat, and the other is selected from among the best losers | Single mark for one candidate or pair of candidates |
Rural–urban proportional representation | No, strategic voters can manipulate the number of overhang seats | Partially — disproportionalities may be caused by use of STV in urban seats, as well as overhang rural seats — rural proportional tier members are selected to compensate for any disproportionality caused by the rural constituency tier, but no such compensation exists for urban disproportionalities | Yes | No, overhang manipulation, also 2 party domination among single winner districts | No | No | No | Yes — urban tier, rural constituency tier and rural proportional tier | Yes — urban constituencies and single-member rural constituencies | Yes — rural constituency candidates are selected by STV; rural constituency candidates are selected by a single-winner method; rural proportional tier members may be selected by a party-list method or from among the best losers in the rural constituencies | Ranking for urban constituency candidates; single mark or ranking for one rural constituency candidate; rural proportional tier marks depend on the exact method used for selection |
Compliance of non-majoritarian party agnostic multi-winner methods
The following table shows which of the above criteria are met by several multiple winner methods.
Criterion Method |
Proportional | Monotone | Consistency | Participation | Cloneproof | No Favorite Betrayal |
Semihonest | Universally Liked Candidates | With Single Winner |
Ballot Type |
Complexity |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Monroe's | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | Approval or Range | Approvals or scores | 5 – Moderate/somewhat high (It's just difficult to compute, not to understand) | ||
Chamberlin-Courant Rule | |||||||||||
Elbert's | Approval or Range | Approvals or scores | 10 – Extremely High | ||||||||
Psi | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | No | Approval or Range | Approvals or scores | 4 – Moderate (The equation just looks scary) | |
Harmonic | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | No | Approval or Range | Approvals or scores | 4 – Moderate (The equation just looks scary) | |
Sequential Proportional Approval | Yes | Yes | No | Yes | No | No | No | Approval | Approvals | 2 – Simple | |
Re-weighted Range | Yes | Yes | No | Yes | No | No | No | Range | Scores | 3 – Simple/Moderate | |
Proportional Approval | Yes | Yes | No | Yes | No | No | No | Approval | Approvals | 3 – Simple/Moderate | |
Bid voting | Yes | No | No | Yes | Approval or Range | Approvals or scores | 4 – Moderate | ||||
Single Transferable Vote | Yes | No | No | No | Yes | No | No | Yes | Instant Runoff | Rankings | 5 – General principle is simple, specifics of implementation can be complex |
CPO-STV | Yes | No | No | No | Yes | No | No | Yes | A Condorcet method (depends on which one) | Rankings | 6 – Somewhat high |
Schulze STV | Yes | Yes | No | No | Yes | No | No | Yes | Schulze | Rankings | 7 – Somewhat high (easier if you understand single winner schulze) |
Expanding Approvals Rule | ? | ? | ? | ? | ? | ? | ? | ? | Approval | Approvals | ? |
Single Non Transferable Vote | No | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | No | — (not proportional) | Plurality | Single mark | 0 – Super simple |
Mini-max Outcome (not to be confused with other mini-max) | Approval | Approvals | ? (needs further research) | ||||||||
Sortition, Arbitrary Winner | No | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | — (not proportional) | Sortition, arbitrary winner | None | 0 – Super simple |
Single Random Ballot | No | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | — (not proportional) | Random Ballot | Limited marks | 0 – Super simple |
Multiple Random Ballots | Approaches | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | — (not proportional) | Random Ballot | Limited rankings | 0 – Super simple |
Compliance of majoritarian multi-winner methods
The following table shows which of the above criteria are met by several multiple winner methods. This table is incomplete. If you are an electoral scientist, for the sake of electoral science, please finish it!
Criterion Method |
Monotone | Consistency | Participation | Cloneproof | No favorite |
Semihonest | Smith set |
Condorcet |
Condorcet |
With single |
Ballot |
How hard is it to understand? |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Multiple Winner Approval | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | No | Approval | Approvals | 0 – Super
simple |
Multiple Winner Range | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | Yes | No | No | No | Range | Scores | 0 – Super
simple |
Multiple Winner Schulze | Yes | No | No | Yes | No | No | Yes | Yes | Yes | Schulze | Rankings | 6 – Somewhat hard |
At Large | Yes | Yes | Yes | No
(spoilers) |
No | No | No | No | No | Plurality | Limited marks | 0 – Super
simple |
Experimental criteria
It is possible to simulate large numbers of virtual elections on a computer and see how various voting methods compare in practical terms. Since such investigations are more difficult than simply proving that a given method does or does not satisfy a given mathematical criterion, results are not available for all methods. Also, these results are sensitive to the parameters of the model used to generate virtual elections, which can be biased either deliberately or accidentally.
One desirable feature that can be explored in this way is maximum voter satisfaction, called in this context minimum Bayesian regret. Such simulations are sensitive to their assumptions, particularly with regard to voter strategy, but by varying the assumptions they can give repeatable measures that bracket the best and worst cases for a voting method.[5] To date, the only such simulation to compare a wide variety of voting methods was run by a range-voting advocate and was not published in a peer-reviewed journal.[6][7] It found that Range voting consistently scored as either the best method or among the best across the various conditions studied.[8]
Another aspect which can be compared through such Monte Carlo simulations is strategic vulnerability. According to the Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem, no voting method can be immune to strategic manipulation in all cases, but certainly some methods will have this problem more often than others. M. Balinski and R. Laraki, the inventors of the majority judgment method, performed such an investigation using a set of simulated elections based on the results from a poll of the 2007 French presidential election which they had carried out using rated ballots. Comparing range voting, Borda count, plurality voting, approval voting with two different absolute approval thresholds, Condorcet voting, and majority judgment, they found that range voting had the highest (worst) strategic vulnerability, while their own method majority judgment had the lowest (best).[9]
Balinski and Laraki also used the same information to investigate how likely it was that each of those methods, as well as runoff voting, would elect a centrist. Opinions differ on whether this is desirable or not. Some argue that methods which favor centrists are better because they are more stable; others argue that electing ideologically purer candidates gives voters more choice and a better chance to retrospectively judge the relative merits of those ideologies; while Balinski and Laraki argue that both centrist and extremist candidates should have a chance to win, to prevent forcing candidates into taking either position. According to their model, plurality, runoff voting, and approval voting with a higher approval threshold tended to elect extremists (100%, 98%, and 94% of the time, respectively); majority judgement elected both centrists and extremists (56% extremists); and range, Borda, and approval voting with a lower approval threshold elected centrists (6%; 0.25–13% depending on the number of candidates; and 6% extremists; respectively).[10] However, their model did not take into account voters' strategic reactions to the method used, such as "lesser of two evils" voting under plurality.
Simulated elections in a two-dimensional issue space can also be graphed to visually compare election methods; this illustrates issues like nonmonotonicity, clone-independence, and tendency to elect centrists vs extremists.[11]
"Soft" criteria
In addition to the above criteria, voting methods are judged using criteria that are not mathematically precise but are still important, such as simplicity, speed of vote-counting, the potential for fraud or disputed results, the opportunity for tactical voting or strategic nomination, and, for multiple-winner methods, the degree of proportionality produced.
The New Zealand Royal Commission on the Electoral System listed ten criteria for their evaluation of possible new electoral methods for New Zealand. These included fairness between political parties, effective representation of minority[12] or special interest groups, political integration, effective voter participation and legitimacy.
See also
- Ranking
- Rating[disambiguation needed]
- Arrow's impossibility theorem
- Condorcet paradox
- Cardinal utility and ordinal utility
Notes
- ^ Approval fails the majority criterion because it does not always elect a candidate preferred by over half of voters; however, it always elects the candidate approved by the most voters.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab ac ad ae af ag ah ai aj ak al am an ao ap aq ar Condorcet, Smith and Independence of Smith-dominated alternatives criteria are incompatible with Independence of irrelevant alternatives, Consistency, Participation, Later-no-harm, Later-no-help, and Favorite betrayal[clarification needed] criteria.
- ^ a b c d In Approval, Range, and Majority Judgment, if all voters have perfect information about each other's true preferences and use rational strategy, any Majority Condorcet or Majority winner will be strategically forced – that is, win in all of one or more strong Nash equilibria. In particular if every voter knows that "A or B are the two most-likely to win" and places their "approval threshold" between the two, then the Condorcet winner, if one exists and is in the set {A,B}, will always win. These methods also satisfy the majority criterion in the weaker sense that any majority can force their candidate to win, if it so desires. Laslier, J-F (2006), "Strategic approval voting in a large electorate" (PDF), IDEP Working Papers (405), Marseille, France
- ^ a b c Approval voting, range voting, and majority judgment satisfy IIA if it is assumed that voters rate candidates individually and independently of knowing the available alternatives in the election, using their own absolute scale. For this to hold, in some elections, some voters must use less than their full voting power or even abstain, despite having meaningful preferences among the available alternatives. If this assumption is not made, these methods fail IIA, as they become more ranked than rated methods.
- ^ The original Independence of clones criterion applied only to ranked voting methods. (T. Nicolaus Tideman, "Independence of clones as a criterion for voting rules", Social Choice and Welfare Vol. 4, No. 3 (1987), pp. 185–206.) Tideman notes that "in the spirit of independence of clones", "if there were two or more candidates who were so similar that every voter would rank them as tied if given the chance to rank them [...], then the number of perfect clones present would have no effect on whether the perfect clones were in the set of winning candidates under approval voting". So, Approval Voting satisfies this mathematical criterion by definition. However, there is some disagreement about whether considerations of the voter in the process of making up his vote could be tactically influenced by clones (in a way that a voter would dispossess a candidate of his approval when a clone of him is introduced) and whether the definition of clones have to be extended to these considerations additionally to the handling of actual votes.
- ^ Later-No-Harm and Later-No-Help assert that adding a later preference to a strictly ordered preference ballot should not help or harm an earlier preference. An Approval ballot records approvals but does not record explicit relative (e.g. later) preferences between approvals (while preferences exist from a voter's perspective). Meanwhile, a voter approving a less preferred candidate harms the probability of any other approved candidate winning, but does not help.
- ^ If the number of candidates grows faster than the square root of the number of voters, this may not be the case, as ties at any point in the process, even between two non-viable candidates, could affect the final result. If the rule for resolving such ties involves no randomness, though, the method does pass the criterion. [citation needed]
- ^ The number of piles that can be summed from various precincts is floor ((e−1) N!) − 1.
- ^ Kemeny-Young does not pass the consistency criterion for winner, but the consistency criterion for full rankings, that is, if the electorate is divided in two parts and in both parts Kemeny-Young chooses the same ranking, Kemeny-Young will also choose that ranking for the combined electorate.
- ^ Each prospective Kemeny-Young ordering has score equal to the sum of the pairwise entries that agree with it, and so the best ordering can be found using the pairwise matrix.
- ^ Bucklin voting, with skipped and equal-rankings allowed, meets the same criteria as Majority Judgment; in fact, Majority Judgment may be considered a form of Bucklin voting. Without allowing equal rankings, Bucklin's criteria compliance is worse; in particular, it fails Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives, which for a ranked method like this variant is incompatible with the Majority Criterion.
- ^ Majority Judgment does not always elect a candidate preferred over all others by over half of voters; however, it always elects the candidate uniquely top-rated by over half of voters.
- ^ Majority Judgment may elect a candidate uniquely least-preferred by over half of voters, but it never elects the candidate uniquely bottom-rated by over half of voters.
- ^ Majority Judgment fails the mutual majority criterion, but satisfies the criterion if the majority ranks the mutually favored set above a given absolute grade and all others below that grade.
- ^ Balinski and Laraki, Majority Judgment's inventors, point out that it meets a weaker criterion they call "grade consistency": if two electorates give the same rating for a candidate, then so will the combined electorate. Majority Judgment explicitly requires that ratings be expressed in a "common language", that is, that each rating have an absolute meaning. They claim that this is what makes "grade consistency" significant. Balinski M, MJ; Laraki, R (2007), A theory of measuring, electing and ranking, vol. 104, USA: National Academy of Sciences, pp. 8720–25
- ^ a b c d e In Majority Judgment, Ranked Pairs, and Schulze voting, there is always a regret-free semi-honest ballot for any voter, holding other ballots constant. That is, if they know enough about how others will vote (for instance, in the case of Majority Judgment, the winning candidate and their winning median score), there is always at least one way for them to participate without grading any less-preferred candidate above any more-preferred one. However, this can cease to hold if voters have insufficient information.
- ^ Majority judgment can actually pass or fail reversal symmetry depending on the rounding method used to find the median when there are even numbers of voters. For instance, in a two-candidate, two-voter race, if the ratings are converted to numbers and the two central ratings are averaged, then MJ meets reversal symmetry; but if the lower one is taken, it does not, because a candidate with ["fair","fair"] would beat a candidate with ["good","poor"] with or without reversal. However, for rounding methods which do not meet reversal symmetry, the odds of breaking it are comparable to the odds of an irresolvable (tied) result; that is, vanishingly small for large numbers of voters.
- ^ Majority Judgment is summable at order KN, where K, the number of ranking categories, is set beforehand.
- ^ Though Majority Judgment does not pass this or similar criteria, there are other similar median methods, such as those based on Bucklin voting, which can meet a related, weaker criterion: ranking an additional candidate below the median grade (rather than your own grade) of your favorite candidate, cannot harm your favorite. Balinski, M., and R. Laraki. “A Theory of Measuring, Electing, and Ranking.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 104, no. 21 (2007): 8720.
- ^ In fact, Majority Judgment ballots use ratings expressed in "common language" rather than numbers, that is, that each rating have an absolute meaning.
- ^ a b A variant of Minimax that counts only pairwise opposition, not opposition minus support, fails the Condorcet criterion and meets later-no-harm.
- ^ a b Since plurality does not allow marking later preferences on the ballot at all, it is impossible to either harm or help a favorite candidate by marking later preferences, and so it trivially passes both Later-No-Harm and Later-No-Help. However, because it forces truncation, it shares some problems with methods that merely encourage truncation by failing Later-No-Harm. Similarly, though to a lesser degree, because it doesn't allow voters to distinguish between all but one of the candidates, it shares some problems with methods which fail Later-No-Help, which encourage voters to make such distinctions dishonestly.
- ^ a b Once for each round.
- ^ That is, second-round votes cannot help or harm candidates already eliminated.
- ^ Later preferences are only possible between the two candidates who make it to the second round.
- ^ STAR voting will elect a majority candidate X if X is in the runoff, and X's voters can guarantee they make the runoff by strategically giving the highest score to X and the lowest score to all opponents. However, if there are two or more opponents that get any points from X's voters, these opponents could shut X out of the runoff. Thus, STAR fails the majority criterion.
- ^ As with the majority criterion, STAR voting fails the mutual majority criterion. However, the more candidates are in the mutual majority set, the greater the chance that at least one of them will be in the runoff, and thus be guaranteed to win.
- ^ STAR does not define a full outcome ordering, only a winner. With any number of candidates besides 3, the winner cannot stay the same if the ballots are reversed.
- ^ In STAR voting, in order for favorite betrayal to be strategically advantageous, four separate things must be true: the favorite candidate X must be in the runoff under an honest vote, X must lose the runoff under an honest vote, the betrayal beneficiary Y must not be in the runoff under an honest vote, and the Y must win the runoff under a strategic vote.
- ^ Sortition, uniformly randomly chosen candidate is winner. Arbitrary winner, some external entity, not a voter, chooses the winner. These methods are not, properly speaking, voting methods at all, but are included to show that even a non-voting method can still pass some of the criteria.
- ^ Random ballot, uniformly randomly chosen ballot determines winner. This and closely related methods are of mathematical interest because they are the only possible methods which are truly strategy-free, that is, your best vote will never depend on anything about the other voters. However, this method is not generally considered as a serious proposal for a practical method.
References
- ^ Vasiljev, Sergei (April 1, 2008), Cardinal Voting: The Way to Escape the Social Choice Impossibility, SSRN eLibrary, SSRN 1116545. Note that in practice, voters could change their votes depending on who is in the race (especially in cardinal voting methods). However, this possibility is ignored, because if it were accounted for, no deterministic method could possibly pass this criterion.
- ^ Consistency implies participation, but not vice versa. For example, range voting complies with participation and consistency, but median ratings satisfies participation and fails consistency.
- ^ Woodall, Douglas (December 1994), "Properties of Preferential Election Rules", Voting Matters (3)
- ^ Small, Alex (August 22, 2010), Geometric construction of voting methods that protect voters' first choices, arXiv:1008.4331, Bibcode:2010arXiv1008.4331S
- ^ Poundstone, William (2008), Gaming the Vote: Why Elections Aren't Fair (and What We Can Do About It), New York: Hill and Young, p. 239
- ^ WDS, "Appendix" (PDF), Range vote (unpublished paper), Temple, archived from the original (PDF) on March 26, 2009
{{citation}}
: Unknown parameter|deadurl=
ignored (|url-status=
suggested) (help) - ^ Poundstone 2008, p. 257: "Range voting is still largely a samizdat enterprise on the fringes of social choice theory. The most glaring example must be Smith's pivotal 2000 paper. It has never been published in a journal."
- ^ Poundstone 2008, p. 240.
- ^ Balinski, M; Laraki, R (2011) [2007], "Election by Majority Judgement: Experimental Evidence", in Dolez, Bernard; Grofman, Bernard; Laurent, Annie (eds.), In Situ and Laboratory Experiments on Electoral Law Reform: French Presidential Elections, Springer
- ^ Balinski & Laraki 2007.
- ^ These two-dimensional graphs are called Yee diagrams after their inventor, Ka-Ping Yee. His website includes some sample graphs.
- ^ The ballot limited designation is technically possible only if the members of the majority, dividing their votes, cannot determine, individually, the minority appointment: Buonomo, Giampiero (2001). "L''emicollegio' sceglie il rappresentante di minoranza (o di maggioranza)". Diritto&Giustizia Edizione Online. – via Questia (subscription required)