Jump to content

English modal auxiliary verbs: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Minor correction
(5 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown)
Line 2: Line 2:
{{English grammar}}
{{English grammar}}
{{wiktionary|Appendix:English modal verbs}}
{{wiktionary|Appendix:English modal verbs}}
The '''English modal auxiliary verbs''' are a subset of the [[English auxiliary verbs]] used mostly to express [[linguistic modality|modality]] (properties such as possibility and obligation).{{Efn|Although there are non-auxiliary modal verbs in English, such as "require" and "oblige", with the aim of brevity this article often uses "modal" or "modal verb" to mean "modal auxiliary verb".}} They can most easily be distinguished from other verbs by their [[defective verb|defectiveness]] (they do not have participles or plain forms{{efn|The plain form of a verb is exemplified by ''beware'' and by the form ''be'' of the verb ''be'': ''You should '''beware''' of the dog''; ''You should '''be''' careful''. It is distinguished from the plain present form of the verb, exemplified by ''am'', ''are'', and ''were''. For any verb aside from ''be'' that is not defective, the plain and plain present forms have identical pronunciation and spelling.<ref name="CamGEL">{{Cite book |last1=Huddleston |first1=Rodney | title=The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language |last2=Pullum |first2=Geoffrey K. | authorlink1=Rodney Huddleston | authorlink2=Geoffrey K. Pullum | publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2002 |location=Cambridge| isbn=978-0-521-43146-0}}</ref>{{Rp|page=104}}<ref name="aarts">{{Cite book| first=Bas | last=Aarts | title=Oxford Modern English Grammar | location=Oxford | publisher=Oxford University Press | year=2011 | isbn=978-0-19-953319-0}}</ref>{{Rp|pages=83–85}}}}) and by their lack of the ending {{nbh}}(''e'')''s'' for the third-person singular.<ref name="CompGEL">{{Cite book | author-last1=Quirk | author-first1=Randolph | author-first2=Sidney | author-last2=Greenbaum | author-first3=Geoffrey | author-last3=Leech | author-first4=Jan | author-last4=Svartvik | authorlink1=Randolph Quirk | authorlink2=Sidney Greenbaum | authorlink3=Geoffrey Leech | authorlink4=Jan Svartvik | year=1985 | title=A Comprehensive Grammar of the English Language | location=London | publisher=Longman | isbn=978-0-582-51734-9}}</ref>
The '''English modal auxiliary verbs''' are a subset of the [[English auxiliary verbs]] used mostly to express [[linguistic modality|modality]] (properties such as possibility and obligation).{{Efn|Although there are non-auxiliary modal verbs in English, such as "require" and "oblige", with the aim of brevity this article often uses "modal" or "modal verb" to mean "modal auxiliary verb".}} They can most easily be distinguished from other verbs by their [[defective verb|defectiveness]] (they do not have participles or plain forms{{efn|The plain form of a verb is exemplified by ''beware'' and by the form ''be'' of the verb ''be'': ''You should '''beware''' of the dog''; ''You should '''be''' careful''. It is distinguished from the plain present form of the verb, exemplified by ''am'', ''are'', and ''were''. For any verb aside from ''be'' that is not defective, the plain and plain present forms have identical pronunciation and spelling.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=104}}{{sfnp|Aarts|2011|pp=83–85}}}}) and by their lack of the ending {{nbh}}(''e'')''s'' for the third-person singular.{{sfnp|Quirk|Greenbaum|Leech|Svartvik|1985|loc={{page needed|date=January 2024}}}}


The central English modal auxiliary verbs are ''can'' (with ''could''), ''may'' (with ''might''), ''shall'' (with ''should''), ''will'' (with ''would''), and ''must''. A few other verbs are sometimes classed as modals: ''ought'', and (in certain uses) ''dare'', ''need'' and ''use'' {{IPA|/jus/|lang=en}}. Other expressions, notably ''had better'', share some of their characteristics.
The central English modal auxiliary verbs are ''can'' (with ''could''), ''may'' (with ''might''), ''shall'' (with ''should''), ''will'' (with ''would''), and ''must''. A few other verbs are sometimes classed as modals: ''ought'', and (in certain uses) ''dare'', ''need'' and ''use'' {{IPA|/jus/|lang=en}}. Other expressions, notably ''had better'', share some of their characteristics.
Line 10: Line 10:
A list of what tend to be regarded as modal auxiliary verbs in Modern English, along with their [[Inflection|inflected]] forms, is shown in the following table.
A list of what tend to be regarded as modal auxiliary verbs in Modern English, along with their [[Inflection|inflected]] forms, is shown in the following table.


Contractions are only shown if their orthography is distinctive. There are also unstressed versions that are typically, although not necessarily, written in the standard way.<ref name="palmer1988" />{{Rp|pages=242–248}} Where there is a blank, the modal auxiliary verb lacks this form. (A corresponding lexical verb may have the form. For example, although the lexical verb ''need'' has a preterite form, the modal auxiliary verb ''need'' does not.)
Contractions are only shown if their orthography is distinctive. There are also unstressed versions that are typically, although not necessarily, written in the standard way.{{sfnp|Palmer|1988|pp=242–248}} Where there is a blank, the modal auxiliary verb lacks this form. (A corresponding lexical verb may have the form. For example, although the lexical verb ''need'' has a preterite form, the modal auxiliary verb ''need'' does not.)


{| class="wikitable" | style="margin-left: auto; margin-right: auto; border: none;"
{| class="wikitable" | style="margin-left: auto; margin-right: auto; border: none;"
Line 36: Line 36:
| none
| none
|-
|-
! style="text-align:right;" | may{{Efn|"[T]here is evidence that for some speakers [of Standard English] ''may'' and ''might'' have diverged to the extent that they are no longer inflectional forms of a single lexeme, but belong to distinct lexemes, ''may'' and ''might'', each of which – like ''must'' – lacks a preterite.&nbsp;.&nbsp;.&nbsp;."<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=109}}}}
! style="text-align:right;" | may{{Efn|"[T]here is evidence that for some speakers [of Standard English] ''may'' and ''might'' have diverged to the extent that they are no longer inflectional forms of a single lexeme, but belong to distinct lexemes, ''may'' and ''might'', each of which – like ''must'' – lacks a preterite.&nbsp;.&nbsp;.&nbsp;."{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=109}}}}
|''may''
|''may''
|
|
Line 81: Line 81:
| marginal
| marginal
|-
|-
! style="text-align:right;" | need{{Efn|name=NPI|An [[Negative polarity item|NPI]], rare for speakers of Standard American English.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=109}}}}
! style="text-align:right;" | need{{Efn|name=NPI|An [[Negative polarity item|NPI]], rare for speakers of Standard American English.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=109}}}}
|''need''
|''need''
|
|
Line 108: Line 108:
| none
| none
|-
|-
! style="text-align:right;" | used{{Efn|Pronounced {{IPA|/just/|lang=en}} (rhyming with "roost"). Auxiliary verb form ''used'' should be distinguished from the homonymous adjective ''used'', as in ''I've got (very) used to it''.<ref>{{Cite book | first=R. W. | last=Zandvoort | title=A Handbook of English Grammar | edition=7th | location=London | publisher=Longman | year=1975 | isbn=978-0-582-55339-2}}</ref>{{Rp|page=85}} (The [[homograph]]ic verb form ''used'' {{IPA|/juzd/|lang=en}}, rhyming with "refused", is lexical only.) "For many speakers [of Standard English], especially younger ones", ''use'' {{IPA|/jus/|lang=en}} is exclusively a lexical verb.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=115}} }}
! style="text-align:right;" | used{{Efn|Pronounced {{IPA|/just/|lang=en}} (rhyming with "roost"). Auxiliary verb form ''used'' should be distinguished from the homonymous adjective ''used'', as in ''I've got (very) used to it''.{{sfnp|Zandvoort|1975|p=85}} (The [[homograph]]ic verb form ''used'' {{IPA|/juzd/|lang=en}}, rhyming with "refused", is lexical only.) "For many speakers [of Standard English], especially younger ones", ''use'' {{IPA|/jus/|lang=en}} is exclusively a lexical verb.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=115}} }}
|
|
|
|
Line 123: Line 123:


====Auxiliary verbs====
====Auxiliary verbs====
Modal auxiliary verbs are a subset of [[English auxiliary verbs|auxiliary verbs]], and thus meet the criteria for these. For lists of these criteria, see the article [[English auxiliary verbs]]; but among them are that the verbs: (i) can [[subject–auxiliary inversion|invert with their subjects]] (notably in questions, '''''Must I''' go?''), (ii) can be negated with ''not'' (''I '''must not''' go''; '''''Must I not''' go?''),<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=94–107}} and (iii) have negative inflected forms (''won't'', ''wouldn't'').<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=91}}
Modal auxiliary verbs are a subset of [[English auxiliary verbs|auxiliary verbs]], and thus meet the criteria for these. For lists of these criteria, see the article [[English auxiliary verbs]]; but among them are that the verbs: (i) can [[subject–auxiliary inversion|invert with their subjects]] (notably in questions, '''''Must I''' go?''), (ii) can be negated with ''not'' (''I '''must not''' go''; '''''Must I not''' go?''),{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=94–107}} and (iii) have negative inflected forms (''won't'', ''wouldn't'').{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=91}}


====No untensed forms====
====No untensed forms====
To illustrate untensed forms, those of the irregular lexical verb ''take'' and the non-modal auxiliary verb ''be'' are the plain ''take'' and ''be'' (as in ''Take it!'', ''I didn't take it'', and ''Don't be silly''), the gerund-participles ''taking'' and ''being'', and the past participles ''taken'' and ''been''.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=74–75}}
To illustrate untensed forms, those of the irregular lexical verb ''take'' and the non-modal auxiliary verb ''be'' are the plain ''take'' and ''be'' (as in ''Take it!'', ''I didn't take it'', and ''Don't be silly''), the gerund-participles ''taking'' and ''being'', and the past participles ''taken'' and ''been''.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=74–75}}


Modal auxiliary verbs lack untensed forms. Attempting to use them brings ungrammatical results:
Modal auxiliary verbs lack untensed forms. Attempting to use them brings ungrammatical results:
Line 152: Line 152:
*{{asterisk}}''It can being a surprise.''
*{{asterisk}}''It can being a surprise.''


If they are modal auxiliary verbs, then ''ought'' and ''used'' are exceptions to this (although ''ought'' is increasingly used with a bare infinitival clause complement).<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=109, 115}}
If they are modal auxiliary verbs, then ''ought'' and ''used'' are exceptions to this (although ''ought'' is increasingly used with a bare infinitival clause complement).{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=109, 115}}


Bare infinitival clause complements are not unique to modal auxiliary verbs. ''Do'' is a non-modal auxiliary verb that takes one (''Did you move the piano?''); ''help'' is a lexical verb that can do so (''I helped move the piano'').
Bare infinitival clause complements are not unique to modal auxiliary verbs. ''Do'' is a non-modal auxiliary verb that takes one (''Did you move the piano?''); ''help'' is a lexical verb that can do so (''I helped move the piano'').
Line 163: Line 163:
Compare lexical verb ''eat'' in *''If I were an elephant, I ate more apples'', and non-modal auxiliary verb ''be'' in *''If I were an elephant, I was able to eat more apples''.
Compare lexical verb ''eat'' in *''If I were an elephant, I ate more apples'', and non-modal auxiliary verb ''be'' in *''If I were an elephant, I was able to eat more apples''.


''Must'' satisfies this only for a minority of speakers, and it is questionable whether ''had better'' does so.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=109, 113}}
''Must'' satisfies this only for a minority of speakers, and it is questionable whether ''had better'' does so.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=109, 113}}


''The Cambridge Grammar'' comments on ''may'' that:
''The Cambridge Grammar'' comments on ''may'' that:


<blockquote>here there is evidence that for some speakers ''may'' and ''might'' have diverged to the extent that they are no longer inflectional forms of a single lexeme, but belong to distinct lexemes, ''may'' and ''might'', each of which – like ''must'' – lacks a preterite....<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=109}}</blockquote>
<blockquote>here there is evidence that for some speakers ''may'' and ''might'' have diverged to the extent that they are no longer inflectional forms of a single lexeme, but belong to distinct lexemes, ''may'' and ''might'', each of which – like ''must'' – lacks a preterite....{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=109}}</blockquote>


''Used'' does not satisfy this.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=115}}
''Used'' does not satisfy this.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=115}}


====Preterite usable in the main clause for modal remoteness====
====Preterite usable in the main clause for modal remoteness====
Line 176: Line 176:
If similarly intended (as a doubtful or reluctant contemplation of an option for the future), attempts at this with a lexical or non-modal auxiliary verb are ungrammatical: *''I '''drove''' there, I suppose''; *''I '''was''' going to drive there, I suppose''.
If similarly intended (as a doubtful or reluctant contemplation of an option for the future), attempts at this with a lexical or non-modal auxiliary verb are ungrammatical: *''I '''drove''' there, I suppose''; *''I '''was''' going to drive there, I suppose''.


Other than when used for [[Sequence of tenses|backshift]], ''should'' has diverged in meaning so far from ''shall'' as to be usable here only with difficulty. As they lack preterite forms, ''must'', ''ought'' and ''need'' cannot be used in this way, and so this criterion does not apply to them.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=108–110}} And ''used'' describes the past, not the present or future.
Other than when used for [[Sequence of tenses|backshift]], ''should'' has diverged in meaning so far from ''shall'' as to be usable here only with difficulty. As they lack preterite forms, ''must'', ''ought'' and ''need'' cannot be used in this way, and so this criterion does not apply to them.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=108–110}} And ''used'' describes the past, not the present or future.


====Comments====
====Comments====
Line 188: Line 188:
Even for lexical verbs, preterite forms have uses besides referring to the past; but for modal auxiliary verbs such uses are particularly important: ('''''Could''' you pass me the sauce?''; ''Without my phone I '''might''' easily be lost''; ''You '''should''' work harder''; ''I '''would''' avoid that street'').
Even for lexical verbs, preterite forms have uses besides referring to the past; but for modal auxiliary verbs such uses are particularly important: ('''''Could''' you pass me the sauce?''; ''Without my phone I '''might''' easily be lost''; ''You '''should''' work harder''; ''I '''would''' avoid that street'').


'''''Ought''''', '''''dare''''', '''''need''''', and '''''used''''' satisfy some of the criteria above, and are more (''ought'', ''dare'', ''need'') or less (''used'') often categorized as modal verbs.<ref>See Palmer, F. R., ''Mood and Modality'', 2nd ed (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), p.&nbsp;33, and ''A Linguistic Study of the English Verb'' (London: Longmans, 1965).</ref> '''''Had better''''' is sometimes called a modal idiom.
'''''Ought''''', '''''dare''''', '''''need''''', and '''''used''''' satisfy some of the criteria above, and are more (''ought'', ''dare'', ''need'') or less (''used'') often categorized as modal verbs.{{sfnp|Palmer|2001|p=33}}{{sfnp|Palmer|1965|loc={{page needed|date=January 2024}}}} '''''Had better''''' is sometimes called a modal idiom.


Other [[English auxiliary verbs]] appear in a variety of different forms and are not regarded as modal verbs. These are:
Other [[English auxiliary verbs]] appear in a variety of different forms and are not regarded as modal verbs. These are:
Line 194: Line 194:
* ''have'', used as an auxiliary verb in [[perfect aspect]] constructions and the idiom ''[[have got]] (to)''; it is also used in ''have to'', which has modal meaning, but here (as when denoting [[possession (linguistics)|possession (very broadly understood)]]) ''have'' only rarely follows auxiliary verb syntax;
* ''have'', used as an auxiliary verb in [[perfect aspect]] constructions and the idiom ''[[have got]] (to)''; it is also used in ''have to'', which has modal meaning, but here (as when denoting [[possession (linguistics)|possession (very broadly understood)]]) ''have'' only rarely follows auxiliary verb syntax;
* ''do'', see [[do-support|''do''-support]];
* ''do'', see [[do-support|''do''-support]];
* ''to'', of ''to''-infinitival clauses (if ''to'' is a defective verb, and not a [[English subordinators|subordinator]]).<ref name=levine_company>{{Cite journal| last=Levine| first=Robert D.| date=2012| title=Auxiliaries: ''To''{{`}}s company| journal=Journal of Linguistics| language=en| volume=48|issue=1|pages=187–203| doi=10.1017/S002222671100034X|issn=0022-2267}}</ref>
* ''to'', of ''to''-infinitival clauses (if ''to'' is a defective verb, and not a [[English subordinators|subordinator]]).{{sfnp|Levine|2012|pp=187–204}}


===Lists of modal auxiliary verbs===
===Lists of modal auxiliary verbs===
Five recent scholarly descriptions of verbs disagree among themselves on the [[Extension (semantics)|extension]] of modal auxiliary verb: on which verbs are modal auxiliary verbs.
Five recent scholarly descriptions of verbs disagree among themselves on the [[Extension (semantics)|extension]] of modal auxiliary verb: on which verbs are modal auxiliary verbs.


They agree that '''can''' (with '''could'''), '''may''' (with '''might'''), '''must''', '''shall''' (with '''should''') and '''will''' with ('''would''') are, or are among, the "central modal auxiliaries" (''[[A Comprehensive Grammar of the English Language]]'', 1985),<ref name="CompGEL" />{{Rp|pages=135–136}} "secondary or modal auxiliaries" ([[Frank R. Palmer|F.&nbsp;R. Palmer]], 1988),<ref name="palmer1988">{{Cite book | last=Palmer | first=F. R. | author-link=Frank R. Palmer | title=The English Verb | location=London | publisher=Longman | year=1988 | isbn=978-0-582-01470-1 | edition=2nd}}</ref>{{Rp|page=26}} "modal auxiliaries" (Anthony R. Warner, 1993), <ref name="warner">{{Cite book | last=Warner | first=Anthony R. | title=English Auxiliaries: Structure and History | series=Cambridge Studies in Linguistics 66 | location=Cambridge | publisher=Cambridge University Press | year=1993 | isbn=978-0-521-30284-5}}</ref>{{Rp|page=11}} "central members of the modal auxiliary class" (''[[The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language]]'', 2002),<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=108–109}} or "core modal verbs" (Bas Aarts, 2011).<ref name="aarts" />{{Rp|pages=280–298}}
They agree that '''can''' (with '''could'''), '''may''' (with '''might'''), '''must''', '''shall''' (with '''should''') and '''will''' with ('''would''') are, or are among, the "central modal auxiliaries" (''[[A Comprehensive Grammar of the English Language]]'', 1985),{{sfnp|Quirk|Greenbaum|Leech|Svartvik|1985|pp=135–136}} "secondary or modal auxiliaries" ([[Frank R. Palmer|F.&nbsp;R. Palmer]], 1988),{{sfnp|Palmer|1988|p=26}} "modal auxiliaries" (Anthony R. Warner, 1993),{{sfnp|Warner|1993|p=11}} "central members of the modal auxiliary class" (''[[The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language]]'', 2002),{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=108–109}} or "core modal verbs" (Bas Aarts, 2011).{{sfnp|Aarts|2011|pp=280–298}}


Among these five verbs, ''The Cambridge Grammar'' selects the pair ''can'' and ''will'' (with ''could'' and ''would'') as "the most straightforward of the modal auxiliaries"<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=108}} (and Peter Collins agrees<ref name="collins_mqm">{{Cite book | first=Peter | last=Collins | title=Modals and Quasi-modals in English | series=Language and Computers: Studies in Practical Linguistics 67 | location=Amsterdam | publisher=Rodopi | year=2009 | isbn=978-90-420-2532-5}}</ref>{{Rp|page=14}}).
Among these five verbs, ''The Cambridge Grammar'' selects the pair ''can'' and ''will'' (with ''could'' and ''would'') as "the most straightforward of the modal auxiliaries"{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=108}} (and Peter Collins agrees{{sfnp|Collins|2009|p=14}}).


All five accord '''ought''', '''need''' and '''dare''' a less clear or merely a marginal membership.<ref name="CompGEL" />{{Rp|pages=138–140}}<ref name="palmer1988" />{{Rp|page=26}}<ref name="warner" />{{Rp|page=11}}<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=109–111}}<ref name="aarts" />{{Rp|pages=298–301}}
All five accord '''ought''', '''need''' and '''dare''' a less clear or merely a marginal membership.{{sfnp|Quirk|Greenbaum|Leech|Svartvik|1985|pp=138–140}}{{sfnp|Palmer|1988|p=26}}{{sfnp|Warner|1993|p=11}}{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=109–111}}{{sfnp|Aarts|2011|pp=298–301}}


''A Comprehensive Grammar'' and Warner do likewise for '''use''';<ref name="CompGEL" />{{Rp|pages=138, 140}}<ref name="warner" />{{Rp|page=11}} the other three deny that it is a modal auxiliary verb.<ref name="palmer1988" />{{Rp|page=170}}<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=115}}<ref name="aarts" />{{Rp|pages=273–274}} For this reason it is primarily discussed not in this article but in the article [[English auxiliary verbs]].)
''A Comprehensive Grammar'' and Warner do likewise for '''use''';{{sfnp|Quirk|Greenbaum|Leech|Svartvik|1985|pp=138, 140}}{{sfnp|Warner|1993|p=11}} the other three deny that it is a modal auxiliary verb.{{sfnp|Palmer|1988|p=170}}{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=115}}{{sfnp|Aarts|2011|pp=273–274}} For this reason it is primarily discussed not in this article but in the article [[English auxiliary verbs]].)


As for '''would''' in '''would rather''', '''would sooner''' and '''would as soon''', and '''have''' in '''had better''', '''had best''' and '''had rather''', only ''The Cambridge Grammar'' notes all six, but each of the other four discussions of auxiliary verbs notes three or more. Of the three to six idioms that each discussion does note, there is no variation in the status that it accords to them. Warner calls the three that he notes – ''would rather'', ''had better'', ''had rather'' – modal auxiliaries.<ref name="warner" />{{Rp|page=11}} Palmer says that the same three are ''not'' modal auxiliaries.<ref name="palmer1988" />{{Rp|pages=170–171}} Both ''A Comprehensive Grammar'' and Aarts use the term modal idiom for a choice of five.<ref name="CompGEL" />{{Rp|pages=141–143}}<ref name="aarts" />{{Rp|pages=303–304}} ''The Cambridge Grammar'' sees modal characteristics in all six uses of these two auxiliary verbs.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=108, 113}}
As for '''would''' in '''would rather''', '''would sooner''' and '''would as soon''', and '''have''' in '''had better''', '''had best''' and '''had rather''', only ''The Cambridge Grammar'' notes all six, but each of the other four discussions of auxiliary verbs notes three or more. Of the three to six idioms that each discussion does note, there is no variation in the status that it accords to them. Warner calls the three that he notes – ''would rather'', ''had better'', ''had rather'' – modal auxiliaries.{{sfnp|Warner|1993|p=11}} Palmer says that the same three are ''not'' modal auxiliaries.{{sfnp|Palmer|1988|pp=170–171}} Both ''A Comprehensive Grammar'' and Aarts use the term modal idiom for a choice of five.{{sfnp|Quirk|Greenbaum|Leech|Svartvik|1985|pp=141–143}}{{sfnp|Aarts|2011|pp=303–304}} ''The Cambridge Grammar'' sees modal characteristics in all six uses of these two auxiliary verbs.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=108, 113}}


''A Comprehensive Grammar'' calls both '''have got''' (''I{{`}}'''ve got''' to go now'') and '''be to''' (''You '''are to''' hand over the cash'') modal idioms.<ref name="CompGEL" />{{Rp|pages=141–143}} None of the other discussions agrees.<ref name="palmer1988" />{{Rp|pages=128–131, 141–143}}<ref name="warner" />{{Rp|page=46}}<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=111–114}}<ref name="aarts" />{{Rp|pages=301–302, 304–305}}
''A Comprehensive Grammar'' calls both '''have got''' (''I{{`}}'''ve got''' to go now'') and '''be to''' (''You '''are to''' hand over the cash'') modal idioms.{{sfnp|Quirk|Greenbaum|Leech|Svartvik|1985|pp=141–143}} None of the other discussions agrees.{{sfnp|Palmer|1988|pp=128–131, 141–143}}{{sfnp|Warner|1993|p=46}}{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=111–114}}{{sfnp|Aarts|2011|pp=301–302, 304–305}}


Palmer calls ''be bound''/''able''/''going''/''willing to'' and ''have'' (''got'') ''to'' semi-modals.<ref name="palmer1988" />{{Rp|page=106}} ''A Comprehensive Grammar'' calls ''be able''/''about''/''apt''/{{Word break (optional)}}''bound''/''due''/''going''/{{Word break (optional)}}''likely''/''meant''/''obliged''/{{Word break (optional)}}''supposed''/''willing to'' and ''have to'' semi-auxiliaries, adding that "The boundaries of this category are not clear".<ref name="CompGEL" />{{Rp|pages=143–146}}
Palmer calls ''be bound''/''able''/''going''/''willing to'' and ''have'' (''got'') ''to'' semi-modals.{{sfnp|Palmer|1988|p=106}} ''A Comprehensive Grammar'' calls ''be able''/''about''/''apt''/{{Word break (optional)}}''bound''/''due''/''going''/{{Word break (optional)}}''likely''/''meant''/''obliged''/{{Word break (optional)}}''supposed''/''willing to'' and ''have to'' semi-auxiliaries, adding that "The boundaries of this category are not clear".{{sfnp|Quirk|Greenbaum|Leech|Svartvik|1985|pp=143–146}}


==Etymology==
==Etymology==
Line 222: Line 222:
{{Anchor|etymology_must}}The verb ''must'' comes from Old English ''moste'', part of the verb ''[[wikt:motan|motan]]'' ("be able/obliged (to do something)"). This was another preterite-present verb, of which ''moste'' was in fact the preterite (the present form ''mot'' gave rise to ''[[wikt:mote|mote]]'', which was used as a modal verb in Early Modern English; but ''must'' has now lost its past connotations and has replaced ''mote''). Similarly, ''ought'' was originally a past form—it derives from ''ahte'', preterite of ''[[wikt:agan|agan]]'' ("own"), another Old English preterite-present verb, whose present tense form ''ah'' has [[Doublet (linguistics)|also given]] the modern (regular) verb ''owe'' (and ''ought'' was formerly used as a past tense of ''owe'').
{{Anchor|etymology_must}}The verb ''must'' comes from Old English ''moste'', part of the verb ''[[wikt:motan|motan]]'' ("be able/obliged (to do something)"). This was another preterite-present verb, of which ''moste'' was in fact the preterite (the present form ''mot'' gave rise to ''[[wikt:mote|mote]]'', which was used as a modal verb in Early Modern English; but ''must'' has now lost its past connotations and has replaced ''mote''). Similarly, ''ought'' was originally a past form—it derives from ''ahte'', preterite of ''[[wikt:agan|agan]]'' ("own"), another Old English preterite-present verb, whose present tense form ''ah'' has [[Doublet (linguistics)|also given]] the modern (regular) verb ''owe'' (and ''ought'' was formerly used as a past tense of ''owe'').


The verb ''dare'' also originates from a preterite-present verb, ''durran'' ("dare"), specifically its present tense ''dear(r)'', although in its non-modal uses in Modern English it is conjugated regularly. However, ''need'' comes from the regular Old English verb ''neodian'' (meaning "be necessary")—the alternative third person form ''need'' (in place of ''needs''), which has become the norm in modal uses, became common in the 16th century.<ref>''[[Oxford English Dictionary]]'', Second Edition, entry for "need".</ref>
The verb ''dare'' also originates from a preterite-present verb, ''durran'' ("dare"), specifically its present tense ''dear(r)'', although in its non-modal uses in Modern English it is conjugated regularly. However, ''need'' comes from the regular Old English verb ''neodian'' (meaning "be necessary")—the alternative third person form ''need'' (in place of ''needs''), which has become the norm in modal uses, became common in the 16th century.{{sfnp|OED|1989}}


==Preterite forms{{Anchor|Past forms}}{{Anchor|Preterite forms}}==
==Preterite forms{{Anchor|Past forms}}{{Anchor|Preterite forms}}==
Line 290: Line 290:


==Weak forms==
==Weak forms==
Most of the modals have negative inflected forms: ''can't'', ''won't'', etc. Although these started as weak forms (contractions), they are so no longer.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=91}} Genuine contractions are:<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=1613}}
Most of the modals have negative inflected forms: ''can't'', ''won't'', etc. Although these started as weak forms (contractions), they are so no longer.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=91}} Genuine contractions are:{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=1613}}


* ''can'' {{IPA|/ˈkæn/|lang=en}} → {{IPA|/kən/|lang=en}}
* ''can'' {{IPA|/ˈkæn/|lang=en}} → {{IPA|/kən/|lang=en}}
Line 302: Line 302:
When ''shall'' and ''should'' are first-person replacements for ''will'' and ''would'', they too may take the weak forms ''{{nbh}}ll'' and ''{{nbh}}d''.{{Citation needed|date=December 2023}}
When ''shall'' and ''should'' are first-person replacements for ''will'' and ''would'', they too may take the weak forms ''{{nbh}}ll'' and ''{{nbh}}d''.{{Citation needed|date=December 2023}}


A combination like ''should have'' is normally reduced to {{IPA|/ʃʊd(h)əv/}} or just {{IPA|/ʃʊdə/}} ''shoulda''. Also, ''ought to'' can become {{IPA|/ɔːtə/}} ''oughta''.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=1615}} See [[weak and strong forms in English]].
A combination like ''should have'' is normally reduced to {{IPA|/ʃʊd(h)əv/}} or just {{IPA|/ʃʊdə/}} ''shoulda''. Also, ''ought to'' can become {{IPA|/ɔːtə/}} ''oughta''.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=1615}} See [[weak and strong forms in English]].


== Effect of negation ==
== Effect of negation ==
Either or both of two kinds of negation can apply to a construction using a modal auxiliary verb. What is called internal negation is limited to the subordinate clause. The difference between ''He '''might''' have overheard you'' and ''He '''might not''' have overheard you'' (with internal negation) is that between "It is possible that he overheard you" and "It is possible that he did not overhear you".<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=175}}
Either or both of two kinds of negation can apply to a construction using a modal auxiliary verb. What is called internal negation is limited to the subordinate clause. The difference between ''He '''might''' have overheard you'' and ''He '''might not''' have overheard you'' (with internal negation) is that between "It is possible that he overheard you" and "It is possible that he did not overhear you".{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=175}}


By contrast, what is called external negation applies to the matrix clause. The difference between ''He '''could''' have overheard you'' and ''He '''couldn't''' have overheard you'' (with external negation) is that between "It is possible that he overheard you" and "It is not possible that he overheard you".<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=175}}
By contrast, what is called external negation applies to the matrix clause. The difference between ''He '''could''' have overheard you'' and ''He '''couldn't''' have overheard you'' (with external negation) is that between "It is possible that he overheard you" and "It is not possible that he overheard you".{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=175}}


''Not'' can be moved into the subordinate clause. ''He '''might have not''' overheard you'' has the same meaning as ''He might not have overheard you''; but ''He '''could have not''' overheard you'' means "It is possible that he did not overhear you".<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=175, 1216}}
''Not'' can be moved into the subordinate clause. ''He '''might have not''' overheard you'' has the same meaning as ''He might not have overheard you''; but ''He '''could have not''' overheard you'' means "It is possible that he did not overhear you".{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=175, 1216}}


The two kinds of negation can be combined. ''He '''can't have not''' overheard you'' means "It is not possible that he did not overhear you".<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=175, 1216}}
The two kinds of negation can be combined. ''He '''can't have not''' overheard you'' means "It is not possible that he did not overhear you".{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=175, 1216}}


Likewise, the difference between ''You '''mustn't''' apologize'' and ''You '''needn't''' apologize'' is that the former shows internal negation, inverting the necessity; the latter external negation, negating the necessity.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=176}}
Likewise, the difference between ''You '''mustn't''' apologize'' and ''You '''needn't''' apologize'' is that the former shows internal negation, inverting the necessity; the latter external negation, negating the necessity.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=176}}


Whether negating a modal auxiliary verb brings negation of the subordinate or the matrix clause (internal or external negation respectively) thus depends on the particular verb (and this in turn partly depends on the strength of the modality that the verb expresses), and there may be other determining factors as well. However: {{Anchor|negative_interrogatives_external}}"Negative interrogatives, used as questions biased towards a positive answer, have external negation irrespective of the strength of the modality [.&nbsp;.&nbsp;.] A special case of this is in tags: ''We must stop soon, mustn't we?''"<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=205}}
Whether negating a modal auxiliary verb brings negation of the subordinate or the matrix clause (internal or external negation respectively) thus depends on the particular verb (and this in turn partly depends on the strength of the modality that the verb expresses), and there may be other determining factors as well. However: {{Anchor|negative_interrogatives_external}}"Negative interrogatives, used as questions biased towards a positive answer, have external negation irrespective of the strength of the modality [.&nbsp;.&nbsp;.] A special case of this is in tags: ''We must stop soon, mustn't we?''"{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=205}}


== Usage of specific verbs ==
== Usage of specific verbs ==
Line 323: Line 323:
The modal verb ''can'' expresses possibility in a [[dynamic modality|dynamic]], [[deontic modality|deontic]], or [[epistemic modality|epistemic]] sense, that is, in terms of innate ability, permissibility, or probability. For example:
The modal verb ''can'' expresses possibility in a [[dynamic modality|dynamic]], [[deontic modality|deontic]], or [[epistemic modality|epistemic]] sense, that is, in terms of innate ability, permissibility, or probability. For example:
*Dynamic
*Dynamic
**Ability:<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=185}} ''You needn't struggle with your Tamil when talking to me: I '''can speak English''''' ("I am capable of speaking English"; "I know how to speak English")
**Ability:{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=185}} ''You needn't struggle with your Tamil when talking to me: I '''can speak English''''' ("I am capable of speaking English"; "I know how to speak English")
**Existential:<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=184}} ''Most siblings get along at least tolerably well, but there '''can be strong rivalry between them''''' (such rivalry does sometimes occur)
**Existential:{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=184}} ''Most siblings get along at least tolerably well, but there '''can be strong rivalry between them''''' (such rivalry does sometimes occur)
**The reasonable/acceptable:<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=184}} ''You '''can be a few minutes late'''; nobody will mind''
**The reasonable/acceptable:{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=184}} ''You '''can be a few minutes late'''; nobody will mind''
**The circumstantially possible:<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=184}} ''Petrol left for months in an unused car '''can wreck its fuel line''''' (This is the result of a predictable chemical process that is not being prevented.)
**The circumstantially possible:{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=184}} ''Petrol left for months in an unused car '''can wreck its fuel line''''' (This is the result of a predictable chemical process that is not being prevented.)
*Deontic:<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=183}} ''Smoking is forbidden anywhere in this building, but you '''can smoke behind the bicycle shed''''' ("You are permitted to smoke here")
*Deontic:{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=183}} ''Smoking is forbidden anywhere in this building, but you '''can smoke behind the bicycle shed''''' ("You are permitted to smoke here")
*Epistemic:<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=181}} ''He did the "Ironman" in under seven hours? That '''can't be true'''.'' ("It is impossible for that to be true.")
*Epistemic:{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=181}} ''He did the "Ironman" in under seven hours? That '''can't be true'''.'' ("It is impossible for that to be true.")


The preterite form ''could'' is used as the past tense or remote conditional form of ''can'' in the above meanings (see {{slink||Preterite forms}} above). It is also used to express likelihood: ''We could be in trouble here.'' It is preferable to use ''could'', ''may'' or ''might'' rather than ''can'' when expressing likelihood in a particular situation{{Citation needed|date=December 2023}} (as opposed to the general case, as in the "rivalry" example above, where ''can'' or ''may'' is used).
The preterite form ''could'' is used as the past tense or remote conditional form of ''can'' in the above meanings (see {{slink||Preterite forms}} above). It is also used to express likelihood: ''We could be in trouble here.'' It is preferable to use ''could'', ''may'' or ''might'' rather than ''can'' when expressing likelihood in a particular situation{{Citation needed|date=December 2023}} (as opposed to the general case, as in the "rivalry" example above, where ''can'' or ''may'' is used).


Both ''can'' and ''could'' can be used to make requests:<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=865}} '''''Can'''/'''could''' you pass me the cheese?'' means "Please pass me the cheese" (where ''could'' is more polite<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=940}}). Either can be used with ''possibly'': '''''Can'''/'''could''' you '''possibly''' pass me the cheese?''<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=768, 770}} Requests with ''can't'' may sound impatient ('''''Can't''' you be quiet?'')<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=940}}
Both ''can'' and ''could'' can be used to make requests:{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=865}} '''''Can'''/'''could''' you pass me the cheese?'' means "Please pass me the cheese" (where ''could'' is more polite{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=940}}). Either can be used with ''possibly'': '''''Can'''/'''could''' you '''possibly''' pass me the cheese?''{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=768, 770}} Requests with ''can't'' may sound impatient ('''''Can't''' you be quiet?''){{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=940}}


It is common to use ''can'' with verbs of perception such as ''see'', ''hear'', etc., as in ''I can see a tree''.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=185}} [[Grammatical aspect|Aspectual]] distinctions can be made, such as ''I could see it'' (ongoing state) vs. ''I saw it'' (event).{{Citation needed|date=December 2023}}
It is common to use ''can'' with verbs of perception such as ''see'', ''hear'', etc., as in ''I can see a tree''.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=185}} [[Grammatical aspect|Aspectual]] distinctions can be made, such as ''I could see it'' (ongoing state) vs. ''I saw it'' (event).{{Citation needed|date=December 2023}}


''Could have'' expresses past ability or possibility, either in some [[counterfactual conditional|counterfactual]] circumstance: ''I could have told him if I had seen him''; ''I could have told him yesterday'' (but I didn't).
''Could have'' expresses past ability or possibility, either in some [[counterfactual conditional|counterfactual]] circumstance: ''I could have told him if I had seen him''; ''I could have told him yesterday'' (but I didn't).
Line 340: Line 340:
''Can have...'' is less common than ''may have...''.{{Citation needed|date=December 2023}}
''Can have...'' is less common than ''may have...''.{{Citation needed|date=December 2023}}


{{anchor|cannot}}''Can'' may be negated by the addition of ''not'' {{IPA|/kən ˈnɒt/|lang=en}}, analogously to the addition of ''not'' to ''could'', ''may'', ''will'' and so forth. It can also be negated by inflection; its commoner inflected form is ''can't'' {{IPA|/ˈkɑnt/|lang=en}}, {{IPA|/ˈkɑnt/|lang=en}}, or {{IPA|/kant/|lang=en}} (in [[Received Pronunciation|RP]], [[General American English|General American]] and [[General Australian]] respectively). However, it has an alternative inflected form, ''cannot'' {{IPA|/ˈkænɒt/|lang=en}}. ''Can not'' and ''cannot'' thus differ in placement of the single stress. ''Can not'' is more formal than ''can't'', and does not invert with its subject (''Can't/*Cannot we leave now?'').<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=1611}}
{{anchor|cannot}}''Can'' may be negated by the addition of ''not'' {{IPA|/kən ˈnɒt/|lang=en}}, analogously to the addition of ''not'' to ''could'', ''may'', ''will'' and so forth. It can also be negated by inflection; its commoner inflected form is ''can't'' {{IPA|/ˈkɑnt/|lang=en}}, {{IPA|/ˈkɑnt/|lang=en}}, or {{IPA|/kant/|lang=en}} (in [[Received Pronunciation|RP]], [[General American English|General American]] and [[General Australian]] respectively). However, it has an alternative inflected form, ''cannot'' {{IPA|/ˈkænɒt/|lang=en}}. ''Can not'' and ''cannot'' thus differ in placement of the single stress. ''Can not'' is more formal than ''can't'', and does not invert with its subject (''Can't/*Cannot we leave now?'').{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=1611}}


Negated, ''could'' has the inflected form ''couldn't''.
Negated, ''could'' has the inflected form ''couldn't''.
Line 346: Line 346:
Negating ''can'' or ''could'' is external: it negates the matrix clause, expressing inability, impermissibility or impossibility (''I '''can't''' wear jeans''). This differs from ''may'' or ''might'' used to express possibility: ''It can't be true'' does not mean ''It may not be true''. Thus ''can't'' (or ''cannot'') is often used to express disbelief even in possibility, as ''must'' expresses belief in the certainty. When the reference is to the past, ''have'' is used: ''He can't/cannot have done it'' means "It is not possible that he did it" (compare ''He must have done it'').
Negating ''can'' or ''could'' is external: it negates the matrix clause, expressing inability, impermissibility or impossibility (''I '''can't''' wear jeans''). This differs from ''may'' or ''might'' used to express possibility: ''It can't be true'' does not mean ''It may not be true''. Thus ''can't'' (or ''cannot'') is often used to express disbelief even in possibility, as ''must'' expresses belief in the certainty. When the reference is to the past, ''have'' is used: ''He can't/cannot have done it'' means "It is not possible that he did it" (compare ''He must have done it'').


With special [[stress (linguistics)|stress]], internal negation is possible: ''I can {{Sc|not}} wear a suit, if I wish'' means "I am not compelled to wear a suit if I don't want to".<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=180, 184, 204, 804–805}}
With special [[stress (linguistics)|stress]], internal negation is possible: ''I can {{Sc|not}} wear a suit, if I wish'' means "I am not compelled to wear a suit if I don't want to".{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=180, 184, 204, 804–805}}


===''May'' and ''might''{{Anchor|may}}===
===''May'' and ''might''{{Anchor|may}}===
Line 360: Line 360:
''May'' can indicate permission for present or future actions, or be a polite directive: ''You may go now''. ''Might'' used in this way is milder: ''You might go now if you feel like it.'' Similarly, ''May I use your phone?'' is a request for permission; ''Might I use your phone?'' would be more hesitant or polite.
''May'' can indicate permission for present or future actions, or be a polite directive: ''You may go now''. ''Might'' used in this way is milder: ''You might go now if you feel like it.'' Similarly, ''May I use your phone?'' is a request for permission; ''Might I use your phone?'' would be more hesitant or polite.


A less common use of ''may'' is [[optative]] (to express a wish), as in ''May you live long and happy''<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=856, 944}} (see also [[English subjunctive]]).
A less common use of ''may'' is [[optative]] (to express a wish), as in ''May you live long and happy''{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=856, 944}} (see also [[English subjunctive]]).


''May have'' indicates uncertainty about a past circumstance, whereas ''might have'' can have that meaning, but it can also refer to possibilities that did not occur but could have (see also [[#Conditional sentences|conditional sentences]] above).
''May have'' indicates uncertainty about a past circumstance, whereas ''might have'' can have that meaning, but it can also refer to possibilities that did not occur but could have (see also [[#Conditional sentences|conditional sentences]] above).
Line 370: Line 370:
The inflected form ''mayn't'' is obsolete. The inflected form ''mightn't'' mostly appears in the tags of [[tag question]]s (''It might snow tonight, '''mightn't it'''?'') and in other questions expressing doubt ('''''Mightn't''' I come in if I took my boots off?'').
The inflected form ''mayn't'' is obsolete. The inflected form ''mightn't'' mostly appears in the tags of [[tag question]]s (''It might snow tonight, '''mightn't it'''?'') and in other questions expressing doubt ('''''Mightn't''' I come in if I took my boots off?'').


The result of negating ''may'' or ''might'' depends on whether the interpretation is [[Epistemic modality|epistemic]] (about likelihood) or [[Deontic modality|deontic]] (about permission). In epistemic senses, the negation is "internal", of the subordinate clause (''There '''may not''' be a vote on it this week''). In deontic senses, the negation is normally external (''You '''may not''' go to the party unless you finish your homework''), but with special [[stress (linguistics)|stress]], internal negation is possible: (''I may {{Sc|not}} attend church, if I wish'', meaning "I have permission not to attend church").<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=180, 182, 184, 204}}
The result of negating ''may'' or ''might'' depends on whether the interpretation is [[Epistemic modality|epistemic]] (about likelihood) or [[Deontic modality|deontic]] (about permission). In epistemic senses, the negation is "internal", of the subordinate clause (''There '''may not''' be a vote on it this week''). In deontic senses, the negation is normally external (''You '''may not''' go to the party unless you finish your homework''), but with special [[stress (linguistics)|stress]], internal negation is possible: (''I may {{Sc|not}} attend church, if I wish'', meaning "I have permission not to attend church").{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=180, 182, 184, 204}}


===''Shall'' and ''should''{{Anchor|should}} ===
===''Shall'' and ''should''{{Anchor|should}} ===
Line 377: Line 377:
With second- and third-person subjects, ''shall'' indicates a directive or prophecy: ''Cinderella, you shall go to the ball!'' It is often used in writing laws and specifications: ''Those convicted of violating this law shall be imprisoned for a term of not less than three years''; ''The device shall be able to operate within a normal temperature range.''
With second- and third-person subjects, ''shall'' indicates a directive or prophecy: ''Cinderella, you shall go to the ball!'' It is often used in writing laws and specifications: ''Those convicted of violating this law shall be imprisoned for a term of not less than three years''; ''The device shall be able to operate within a normal temperature range.''


''Shall'' is sometimes used in requests for advice or confirmation of a suggestion: ''Shall I read now?''; ''What shall we wear?''<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.myenglishteacher.eu/blog/english-grammar-shall-vs-should-with-examples/|title=English Grammar: Usage of Shall vs Should with Examples|first=Anastasia|last=Koltai|website=My English Teacher|date=February 21, 2013}}</ref>
''Shall'' is sometimes used in requests for advice or confirmation of a suggestion: ''Shall I read now?''; ''What shall we wear?''{{sfnp|Koltai|2013}}


''Should'' is sometimes used as a first-person equivalent to ''would'' (in its conditional and "future-in-the-past" uses), in the same way that ''shall'' can replace ''will''. ''Should'' is also used for a protasis with future reference: either with the preposition ''if'' (''If you should meet her, please give her this'') or with subject–auxiliary inversion (''Should you meet her, please give her this'').
''Should'' is sometimes used as a first-person equivalent to ''would'' (in its conditional and "future-in-the-past" uses), in the same way that ''shall'' can replace ''will''. ''Should'' is also used for a protasis with future reference: either with the preposition ''if'' (''If you should meet her, please give her this'') or with subject–auxiliary inversion (''Should you meet her, please give her this'').
Line 387: Line 387:
The negative inflections are ''shan't'' and ''shouldn't''.
The negative inflections are ''shan't'' and ''shouldn't''.


Negating ''should'' negates the subordinate clause: the negation is internal (''You '''shouldn't''' use botox'').<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=187, 204}} (To negate the meaning of ''I should'', one may use''I ought not to'' or ''I am not supposed to''.)
Negating ''should'' negates the subordinate clause: the negation is internal (''You '''shouldn't''' use botox'').{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=187, 204}} (To negate the meaning of ''I should'', one may use''I ought not to'' or ''I am not supposed to''.)


As for any modal auxiliary, a negative interrogative ('''''Shouldn't''' you check your credit card statement?'') instead negates the matrix clause.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=205}}
As for any modal auxiliary, a negative interrogative ('''''Shouldn't''' you check your credit card statement?'') instead negates the matrix clause.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=205}}


===''Will'' and ''would'' {{Anchor|will}}===
===''Will'' and ''would'' {{Anchor|will}}===
Line 396: Line 396:
* ''Will'' can express [[habitual aspect]] or [[dynamic modality]]; for example, ''He will make mistakes'' (in which ''will'' is usually stressed somewhat) may mean that he seems often to make them.
* ''Will'' can express [[habitual aspect]] or [[dynamic modality]]; for example, ''He will make mistakes'' (in which ''will'' is usually stressed somewhat) may mean that he seems often to make them.


''Will'' also has these uses as a modal:<ref name=Fleischman>Fleischman, Suzanne, ''The Future in Thought and Action'', Cambridge University Press, 1982, pp. 86–97.</ref><ref name="Comrie tense">Comrie, Bernard, ''Tense'', Cambridge University Press, 1985, pp. 21, 47–48.</ref>
''Will'' also has these uses as a modal:{{sfnp|Fleischman|1982|pp=86–97}}{{sfnp|Comrie|1985|pp=21, 47–48}}
* It can express strong probability with present time reference, as in ''That will be John at the door''.
* It can express strong probability with present time reference, as in ''That will be John at the door''.
* It can be used to give an indirect order, as in ''You will do it right now''.
* It can be used to give an indirect order, as in ''You will do it right now''.
Line 408: Line 408:


As an aspect marker, ''would'' is used for
As an aspect marker, ''would'' is used for
* Expression of habitual aspect in past time, as in ''Back then, I would eat early and would walk to school.''<ref>{{Cite web |url=http://ultralingua.com/onlinedictionary/references/spanish/conditional.htm | website=UltraLingua Online Dictionary & Grammar | title=Conditional tense |url-status=dead |archive-url=http://arquivo.pt/wayback/20091011013417/http://ultralingua.com/onlinedictionary/references/spanish/conditional.htm |archive-date=2009-10-11}}</ref><ref>{{Cite web |url=https://studyspanish.com/verbs/lessons/conditional.htm |website=Study Spanish | title=The Conditional Tense}}</ref>
* Expression of habitual aspect in past time, as in ''Back then, I would eat early and would walk to school.''{{sfnp|Ultralingua|n.d.}}{{sfnp|StudySpanish|n.d.}}


Both ''will'' and ''would'' can be used with ''have'' (''will have'', ''would have''), either to form the future perfect and conditional perfect forms already referred to, or to express [[perfective aspect]] in their other meanings (e.g. ''there will have been an arrest order'', expressing strong probability).
Both ''will'' and ''would'' can be used with ''have'' (''will have'', ''would have''), either to form the future perfect and conditional perfect forms already referred to, or to express [[perfective aspect]] in their other meanings (e.g. ''there will have been an arrest order'', expressing strong probability).
Line 414: Line 414:
The negative inflections are ''won't'' and ''wouldn't''. For contracted forms of ''will'' and ''would'' themselves, see "[[#Weak forms|Weak forms]]", above.
The negative inflections are ''won't'' and ''wouldn't''. For contracted forms of ''will'' and ''would'' themselves, see "[[#Weak forms|Weak forms]]", above.


Negating ''will'' or ''would'' is "internal": it negates the subordinate clause. (''I '''won't''' be surprised if it rains'' means ''I will be unsurprised if it rains''.) But as for any modal auxiliary, a negative interrogative ('''''Won't'''''/'''''Wouldn't''' we submit them in person?'') negates the matrix clause.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=193, 205}}
Negating ''will'' or ''would'' is "internal": it negates the subordinate clause. (''I '''won't''' be surprised if it rains'' means ''I will be unsurprised if it rains''.) But as for any modal auxiliary, a negative interrogative ('''''Won't'''''/'''''Wouldn't''' we submit them in person?'') negates the matrix clause.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=193, 205}}


====''Would rather'', ''would sooner'', and ''would as soon''{{Anchor|would_rather_etc}}==== <!-- There's a link to the anchor from [[English auxiliary verbs]]. -->
====''Would rather'', ''would sooner'', and ''would as soon''{{Anchor|would_rather_etc}}==== <!-- There's a link to the anchor from [[English auxiliary verbs]]. -->
''Would rather'', ''would sooner'', or ''would as soon'' can take as its complement either a bare infinitival clause (''She would rather go herself'') or a declarative content clause (''She would rather ''(''that'')'' I went'').<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=108}} They are [[Polarity item|PPIs]]:<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=829}} although ''I would rather not catch the virus'' (with negation of the clause that is subordinate to ''would rather'') is idiomatic, *''I '''wouldn't rather''' catch the virus'' (with negation of the matrix clause) is distinctly strange. Whether its reference is to past, present or future, the declarative content clause complement can use the preterite: ''I{{`}}'''d rather''' you hadn't told her that'' (past counterfactual); ''I{{`}}'''d rather''' you didn't tell her that'' (present/future); ''I{{`}}'''d rather''' you didn't tell her that when you meet her'' (future).<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=1003–1004}}
''Would rather'', ''would sooner'', or ''would as soon'' can take as its complement either a bare infinitival clause (''She would rather go herself'') or a declarative content clause (''She would rather ''(''that'')'' I went'').{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=108}} They are [[Polarity item|PPIs]]:{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=829}} although ''I would rather not catch the virus'' (with negation of the clause that is subordinate to ''would rather'') is idiomatic, *''I '''wouldn't rather''' catch the virus'' (with negation of the matrix clause) is distinctly strange. Whether its reference is to past, present or future, the declarative content clause complement can use the preterite: ''I{{`}}'''d rather''' you hadn't told her that'' (past counterfactual); ''I{{`}}'''d rather''' you didn't tell her that'' (present/future); ''I{{`}}'''d rather''' you didn't tell her that when you meet her'' (future).{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=1003–1004}}


===''Must'' ===
===''Must'' ===
Line 424: Line 424:
When used with ''have'' and a past participle, ''must'' has only an [[epistemic modality|epistemic flavor]]: ''Sue must have left'' means that the speaker concludes that Sue has left. To express obligation or necessity in the past, ''had to'' or some other synonym must be used.
When used with ''have'' and a past participle, ''must'' has only an [[epistemic modality|epistemic flavor]]: ''Sue must have left'' means that the speaker concludes that Sue has left. To express obligation or necessity in the past, ''had to'' or some other synonym must be used.


The negative inflection of ''must'' is ''mustn't''. Negation of ''must'' is "internal", negating the subordinate clause: (''You '''must not'''/'''mustn't''' drive after smoking a joint'' means that not driving is what you must do). But as for any modal auxiliary, a negative interrogative ('''''Mustn't''' we hide the dope?'') negates the matrix clause.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=180, 182, 204, 205}} To express the lack of requirement or obligation, the negative of ''have to'' or ''need'' (see [[#no_need|below]]) can be used: ''You don't have to do this''; ''You needn't do this''.
The negative inflection of ''must'' is ''mustn't''. Negation of ''must'' is "internal", negating the subordinate clause: (''You '''must not'''/'''mustn't''' drive after smoking a joint'' means that not driving is what you must do). But as for any modal auxiliary, a negative interrogative ('''''Mustn't''' we hide the dope?'') negates the matrix clause.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=180, 182, 204, 205}} To express the lack of requirement or obligation, the negative of ''have to'' or ''need'' (see [[#no_need|below]]) can be used: ''You don't have to do this''; ''You needn't do this''.


Negated, ''must'' is not commonly used in an epistemic sense, where it is common to use ''can't'' (''It can't be here''; ''Sue can't have left'') instead.
Negated, ''must'' is not commonly used in an epistemic sense, where it is common to use ''can't'' (''It can't be here''; ''Sue can't have left'') instead.
Line 430: Line 430:
''Mustn't'' can nonetheless be used as a simple negative of ''must'' in [[tag question]]s and other questions expressing doubt: ''We must do it, mustn't we? Mustn't he be in the operating room by this stage?''
''Mustn't'' can nonetheless be used as a simple negative of ''must'' in [[tag question]]s and other questions expressing doubt: ''We must do it, mustn't we? Mustn't he be in the operating room by this stage?''


{{Anchor|needs_must}}''Must'' and ''needs'' can occur in sequence. Hendrik Poutsma writes that "The force of ''must'', notably that of representing the subject under pressure of an overmastering desire [.&nbsp;.&nbsp;.&nbsp;], is often emphasized by ''needs''."<ref name="poutsma_2nd_v1">{{Cite book | first=H. | last=Poutsma | title=A Grammar of Late Modern English | edition=2nd | volume=1 | page=158 | publisher=P. Noordhoff | location=Groningen | oclc=697774306 | url=https://archive.org/details/grammaroflatemod01poutuoft/grammaroflatemod01poutuoft_bw.pdf | via=Internet Archive}}</ref>{{Rp|page=61}} Examples of the pair are:
{{Anchor|needs_must}}''Must'' and ''needs'' can occur in sequence. Hendrik Poutsma writes that "The force of ''must'', notably that of representing the subject under pressure of an overmastering desire [.&nbsp;.&nbsp;.&nbsp;], is often emphasized by ''needs''."{{sfnp|Poutsma|1929|p=61}} Examples of the pair are:
*''The control of the Firm '''needs must''' stay within the Family.''<ref>{{Cite news | url=https://sundayguardianlive.com/opinion/1306-jaipur-shivir-had-one-point-agenda | first=Virendra | last=Kapoor | date=26 January 2013 | work=The Sunday Guardian | title=Jaipur Shivir had one-point agenda | access-date=19 December 2023}}</ref>
*''The control of the Firm '''needs must''' stay within the Family.''{{sfnp|Kapoor|2013}}
*''It '''needs must''' be said that any observation made in this order shall not be taken as observations on merits''<ref>{{cite news | url=https://www.dailyexcelsior.com/hc-rejects-quashing-of-fir-in-multi-crore-fci-scam/ | date=3 August 2018 | title=HC rejects quashing of FIR in multi-crore FCI scam | work=Daily Excelsior | access-date=19 December 2023}}</ref>
*''It '''needs must''' be said that any observation made in this order shall not be taken as observations on merits''{{sfnp|Daily Excelsior|2018}}
*''thinking it through to its ultimate logical consequences '''must needs''' lead to insoluble contradictions''<ref>{{Cite web | first=Ludwig | last=von Mises | author-link=Ludwig von Mises |title=Mises on the Velocity of Circulation | date=7 July 2020 | orig-date=1944 | website=Mises Wire | url=https://mises.org/wire/mises-velocity-circulation | access-date=19 December 2023}}</ref>
*''thinking it through to its ultimate logical consequences '''must needs''' lead to insoluble contradictions''{{sfnp|von Mises|2020}}
*''the Constitution envisions, and by extension the country as a whole '''must needs''' have, a truly high-minded Supreme Court''<ref>{{Cite web | title=How to depoliticize the US Supreme Court | first=Bruce K. | last=Adler | date=15 October 2018 | website=Yahoo News | url=https://sg.news.yahoo.com/depoliticize-u-supreme-court-144623447.html | access-date=19 December 2023}}</ref>
*''the Constitution envisions, and by extension the country as a whole '''must needs''' have, a truly high-minded Supreme Court''{{sfnp|Adler|2018}}


===''Ought''{{Anchor|ought}} ===
===''Ought''{{Anchor|ought}} ===
Line 447: Line 447:
''Had better'' has a similar meaning to ''should'' and ''ought'' for a deontic meaning (expressing recommended or expedient behavior (''You '''ought to''' ''/'' '''should''' ''/'' '''had better''' arrive on time''), but not (other perhaps than jokingly) for an epistemic meaning (''The Sun '''ought to''' ''/'' '''should''' ''/ ?'''''had better''' come out soon'').
''Had better'' has a similar meaning to ''should'' and ''ought'' for a deontic meaning (expressing recommended or expedient behavior (''You '''ought to''' ''/'' '''should''' ''/'' '''had better''' arrive on time''), but not (other perhaps than jokingly) for an epistemic meaning (''The Sun '''ought to''' ''/'' '''should''' ''/ ?'''''had better''' come out soon'').


Negating ''ought'' is "internal": it negates the subordinate clause (''I '''ought not''' to have a third glassful'' means that what I ought to do is decline the glassful). But as for any modal auxiliary, a negative interrogative ('''''Oughtn't''' we to offer cola as well as beer?'') negates the matrix clause.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=187, 205}}
Negating ''ought'' is "internal": it negates the subordinate clause (''I '''ought not''' to have a third glassful'' means that what I ought to do is decline the glassful). But as for any modal auxiliary, a negative interrogative ('''''Oughtn't''' we to offer cola as well as beer?'') negates the matrix clause.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=187, 205}}


The use of ''ought'' as a lexical verb as in ''They didn't ought to go'' is generally thought of as restricted to non-standard dialects<ref name="CompGEL" />{{Rp|page=140}} but has been described as also sometimes found in informal standard usage.<ref>{{Cite book | first=Sidney | last=Greenbaum | author-link=Sidney Greenbaum | title=The Oxford English Grammar | location=Oxford | year=1996 |publisher=Oxford University Press | isbn=978-0-19-861250-6 | page=155}}</ref> "Lexical ''ought'' with the dummy operator ''do'' has been condemned in British usage handbooks.&nbsp;.&nbsp;.&nbsp;. What this censure suggests is that lexical ''ought'' with periphrastic ''do'' is a well-established usage in colloquial [British English]."<ref name="lee_collins">{{cite journal | title=On the usage of ''have'', ''dare'', ''need'', ''ought'' and ''used to'' in Australian English and Hong Kong English | author-first1=Jackie F. K. | author-last1=Lee | author-first2=Peter | author-last2=Collins | journal=World Englishes | volume=23 | number=4 | pages=501–513 | date=2004 | doi=10.1111/j.0083-2919.2004.00374.x}}</ref>{{Rp|page=502}}
The use of ''ought'' as a lexical verb as in ''They didn't ought to go'' is generally thought of as restricted to non-standard dialects{{sfnp|Quirk|Greenbaum|Leech|Svartvik|1985|p=140}} but has been described as also sometimes found in informal standard usage.{{sfnp|Greenbaum|1996|p=155}} "Lexical ''ought'' with the dummy operator ''do'' has been condemned in British usage handbooks.&nbsp;.&nbsp;.&nbsp;. What this censure suggests is that lexical ''ought'' with periphrastic ''do'' is a well-established usage in colloquial [British English]."{{sfnp|Lee|Collins|2004|p=502}}


Data from a corpus of American and British spoken and written English of the 1980s and 1990s show that ''ought not to'', ''oughtn't to'' (both modal auxiliary), and ''didn't ought to'' are rare in both American and British English, whether written or spoken. ''I don't think you ought to'' and similar are commonly used instead.<ref name="LGSWE">{{Cite book | author-first1=Douglas | author-last1=Biber | author-first2=Stig | author-last2=Johansson | author-first3=Geoffrey | author-last3=Leech | author-first4=Susan | author-last4=Conrad | author-first5=Edward | author-last5=Finegan | author-link2=Stig Johansson (linguist) | author-link3=Geoffrey Leech | title=Longman Grammar of Spoken and Written English | location=Harlow, Essex | publisher=Pearson Education | year=1999 | isbn=978-0-582-23725-4 | url=https://archive.org/details/longmangrammarof0000unse/mode/2up?view=theater | via=Internet Archive}}</ref>{{Rp|page=165}} In interrogatives, ''ought'' does not appear in American conversation or fiction or in British conversation; in British fiction, the modal auxiliary is used (''Ought we to .&nbsp;.&nbsp;.&nbsp;?''), not lexical ''ought'' with ''do''-support.<ref name="LGSWE" />{{Rp|page=218}}
Data from a corpus of American and British spoken and written English of the 1980s and 1990s show that ''ought not to'', ''oughtn't to'' (both modal auxiliary), and ''didn't ought to'' are rare in both American and British English, whether written or spoken. ''I don't think you ought to'' and similar are commonly used instead.{{sfnp|Biber|Johansson|Leech|Conrad|1999|p=165}} In interrogatives, ''ought'' does not appear in American conversation or fiction or in British conversation; in British fiction, the modal auxiliary is used (''Ought we to .&nbsp;.&nbsp;.&nbsp;?''), not lexical ''ought'' with ''do''-support.{{sfnp|Biber|Johansson|Leech|Conrad|1999|p=218}}


=== ''Need''{{Anchor|need}} ===
=== ''Need''{{Anchor|need}} ===
Line 463: Line 463:
Although as a modal auxiliary verb ''need'' takes a bare infinitival clause complement (''He needn't overhaul it''), lexical verb ''need'' can take either an object complement (''He needs my help'') or a ''to''-infinitival clause complement (''He needs to overhaul it''), optionally with a subject (''He needs me to overhaul it'').
Although as a modal auxiliary verb ''need'' takes a bare infinitival clause complement (''He needn't overhaul it''), lexical verb ''need'' can take either an object complement (''He needs my help'') or a ''to''-infinitival clause complement (''He needs to overhaul it''), optionally with a subject (''He needs me to overhaul it'').


{{Anchor|no_need}}Negation of ''need'' is external, negating the matrix clause. ''You '''needn't''' apply again'' does not say that there is a need not to apply, merely that there is no need to apply.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=180}} So although the verb ''must'' can usually be substituted for the modal verb ''need'', ''mustn't'' usually cannot be substituted for ''needn't''. (Exceptionally, the pair are synonymous in polar interrogatives: ''Needn't/mustn't we pay now?'')
{{Anchor|no_need}}Negation of ''need'' is external, negating the matrix clause. ''You '''needn't''' apply again'' does not say that there is a need not to apply, merely that there is no need to apply.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=180}} So although the verb ''must'' can usually be substituted for the modal verb ''need'', ''mustn't'' usually cannot be substituted for ''needn't''. (Exceptionally, the pair are synonymous in polar interrogatives: ''Needn't/mustn't we pay now?'')


Modal ''need'' can also be used with ''have'': ''Need I have done that?'' It is most commonly used here in the negative, meaning that an action was (from the present perspective) not in fact necessary: ''You needn't have left that tip''.
Modal ''need'' can also be used with ''have'': ''Need I have done that?'' It is most commonly used here in the negative, meaning that an action was (from the present perspective) not in fact necessary: ''You needn't have left that tip''.


Data from a corpus of American and British spoken and written English of the 1980s and 1990s show that for negative constructions involving ''need'', modal auxiliary ''need'' is commoner in written English (both American and British), but is less common than lexical ''need'' in British English conversation and unused in American English conversation.163 In both American and British English, interrogative constructions that require subject–auxiliary inversion show ''do''-support of lexical ''need'' much more commonly than inversion of auxiliary ''need''; moreover, many of what instances there are of auxiliary ''need'' are of fixed formulas (''Need I say more?'', etc).<ref name="LGSWE" />{{Rp|page=217}}
Data from a corpus of American and British spoken and written English of the 1980s and 1990s show that for negative constructions involving ''need'', modal auxiliary ''need'' is commoner in written English (both American and British), but is less common than lexical ''need'' in British English conversation and unused in American English conversation.163 In both American and British English, interrogative constructions that require subject–auxiliary inversion show ''do''-support of lexical ''need'' much more commonly than inversion of auxiliary ''need''; moreover, many of what instances there are of auxiliary ''need'' are of fixed formulas (''Need I say more?'', etc).{{sfnp|Biber|Johansson|Leech|Conrad|1999|p=217}}


''For "needs must" (and "must needs") see under [[#needs_must|must]]''.
''For "needs must" (and "must needs") see under [[#needs_must|must]]''.
Line 476: Line 476:
''Dare'' is now much commoner as a lexical verb. Lexical verb ''dare'' takes a ''to''-infinitival clause as its complement (''I didn't dare to answer her''), and this may have a subject (''He dared me to dive from a higher board''); modal ''dare'', a bare infinitival clause complement.
''Dare'' is now much commoner as a lexical verb. Lexical verb ''dare'' takes a ''to''-infinitival clause as its complement (''I didn't dare to answer her''), and this may have a subject (''He dared me to dive from a higher board''); modal ''dare'', a bare infinitival clause complement.


Negation of ''dare'' is external: what is negated is the matrix clause. (''She '''dare not''' attempt it'' means "She doesn't dare to attempt it".)<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=196}}
Negation of ''dare'' is external: what is negated is the matrix clause. (''She '''dare not''' attempt it'' means "She doesn't dare to attempt it".){{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=196}}


Examples of the use of modal auxiliary ''dare'', followed by equivalents using lexical ''dare'' where appropriate:
Examples of the use of modal auxiliary ''dare'', followed by equivalents using lexical ''dare'' where appropriate:
Line 492: Line 492:
Although seemingly obsolete in the 21st century, ''daredn't'' was in use in the early 20th. Examples:
Although seemingly obsolete in the 21st century, ''daredn't'' was in use in the early 20th. Examples:


*''"I '''daredn't''' hurry," said Mr Colclough, setting us down at the station. "I was afraid of a skid."''<ref>{{Cite book | chapter=The Death of Simon Fuge | title=The Grim Smile of the Five Towns | first=Arnold | last=Bennett | author-link=Arnold Bennett | orig-date=1907 | location=Harmondsworth, Middlesex | publisher=Penguin | date=1971 | page=186 | url=https://archive.org/details/grimsmileoffiv00benn | via=Internet Archive}}</ref>
*''"I '''daredn't''' hurry," said Mr Colclough, setting us down at the station. "I was afraid of a skid."''{{sfnp|Bennett|1971|p=186}}
*''One's so safe with such a son to con her / Through all the noises and through all the press, / Boys '''daredn't''' squirt tormenters on her dress.''<ref>{{Cite book | first=John | last=Masefield | author-link=John Masefield | title=The Widow in the Bye Street | location=London | publisher=Sidgwick & Jackson | year=1912 | oclc=330395 | url=https://www.gutenberg.org/files/41468/41468-h/41468-h.html | via=Gutenberg Project}}</ref>
*''One's so safe with such a son to con her / Through all the noises and through all the press, / Boys '''daredn't''' squirt tormenters on her dress.''{{sfnp|Masefield|1912|loc={{page needed|date=January 2024}}}}


''Dared'' has supplanted an earlier preterite form, ''durst''.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=110n}} Examples:
''Dared'' has supplanted an earlier preterite form, ''durst''.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=110n}} Examples:
*''The former [.&nbsp;.&nbsp;.] retired with cattle and other booty to their mountains, whither they knew well the Lowlanders durst not follow them.''<ref>{{Cite book | title=An Account of the Danes and Norwegians in England, Scotland, and Ireland | first=J. J. A. | last=Worsaae | author-link=Jens Jacob Asmussen Worsaae | location=London | publisher=John Murray | year=1852 | url=https://www.gutenberg.org/files/55409/55409-h/55409-h.htm | via=Project Gutenberg}}</ref>
*''The former [.&nbsp;.&nbsp;.] retired with cattle and other booty to their mountains, whither they knew well the Lowlanders durst not follow them.''{{sfnp|Worsaae|1852|loc={{page needed|date=January 2024}}}}
*''Other debts I durst not face.''{{sfnp|Yonge|1875|loc={{page needed|date=January 2024}}}}
*''Other debts I durst not face.''<ref>{{Cite book | title=The Pillars of the House; or, Under Wode, under Rode | volume=2 | first=Charlotte M. | last=Yonge | author-link=Charlotte Mary Yonge | location=London | publisher=Macmillan | year=1875 | url=https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/44721/pg44721-images.html | via=Project Gutenberg}}</ref>
*''dizzy church-crowned central peak that time durst not touch''<!-- Lowercase "dizzy" and lack of a period are deliberate --><ref>{{Cite book | title=The Festival | first=H. P. | last=Lovecraft | author-link=H. P. Lovecraft | year=2022 | orig-date=1924 | url=https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/68553/pg68553-images.html | via=Project Gutenberg}}</ref>
*''dizzy church-crowned central peak that time durst not touch''<!-- Lowercase "dizzy" and lack of a period are deliberate -->{{sfnp|Lovecraft|2022|loc={{page needed|date=January 2024}}}}


''Durst'' had a negative inflected form, ''durstn't''. Examples:
''Durst'' had a negative inflected form, ''durstn't''. Examples:
*''I'm under authority, you know, and durstn't overstep''<!-- Lack of a period is deliberate --><ref>{{Cite book | title=Under the Waves: Diving in Deep Waters | first=R. M. | last=Ballantyne | author-link=R. M. Ballantyne | date=2007 | orig-date=1876 | url=https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/23493/pg23493-images.html | via=Project Gutenberg}}</ref>
*''I'm under authority, you know, and durstn't overstep''<!-- Lack of a period is deliberate -->{{sfnp|Ballantyne|2007|loc={{page needed|date=January 2024}}}}
*''the boat, where I durstn't kick for fear of poking my feet through the bottom''<!-- Lowercase "the" and lack of a period are deliberate --><ref>{{Cite book | title=To the West | first=George Manville | last=Fenn | author-link=George Manville Fenn | date=2007 | orig-date=1891 | url=https://www.gutenberg.org/files/21495/21495-h/21495-h.htm | via=Project Gutenberg}}</ref>
*''the boat, where I durstn't kick for fear of poking my feet through the bottom''<!-- Lowercase "the" and lack of a period are deliberate -->{{sfnp|Fenn|2007|loc={{page needed|date=January 2024}}}}
*''I durstn't go home to tell Mother Pring''<!-- Lack of a period is deliberate --><ref>{{Cite book | title=Slain by the Doones | first=R. D. | last=Blackmore | author-link=R. D. Blackmore | date=2021 | orig-date=1895 | url=https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/22315/pg22315-images.html | via=Project Gutenberg}}</ref>
*''I durstn't go home to tell Mother Pring''<!-- Lack of a period is deliberate -->{{sfnp|Blackmore|2021|loc={{page needed|date=January 2024}}}}


Lexical verb ''dare'' is close to an NPI: ''She dared to speak up'' is much less likely than ''She didn't dare to speak up.''<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=110–111}} And the lexical–modal distinction is blurred: "lexical ''dare'' commonly occurs in non-affirmative contexts without ''to''": ''She wouldn't dare ask her father''; and it also can be stranded, as in ''She ought to have asked for a raise, but she didn't dare''.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=110}}
Lexical verb ''dare'' is close to an NPI: ''She dared to speak up'' is much less likely than ''She didn't dare to speak up.''{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=110–111}} And the lexical–modal distinction is blurred: "lexical ''dare'' commonly occurs in non-affirmative contexts without ''to''": ''She wouldn't dare ask her father''; and it also can be stranded, as in ''She ought to have asked for a raise, but she didn't dare''.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=110}}


Data from a corpus of American and British spoken and written English of the 1980s and 1990s show that ''dare'' (modal or lexical) is infrequent and "is found chiefly in fiction and [British English] conversation", but that in negative constructions in American fiction, lexical ''dare'' is commoner; in Britain, modal auxiliary ''dare'' is.<ref name="LGSWE" />{{Rp|page=163}} Further, negation of preterite ''dared'' is rare.<ref name="LGSWE" />{{Rp|page=164}} In both American and British English, interrogative constructions that require subject–auxiliary inversion show inversion of auxiliary ''dare'' much more commonly than ''do''-support of lexical ''dare''; however, many of the instances here of auxiliary ''dare'' are of fixed formulas (''How dare you .&nbsp;.&nbsp;.&nbsp;?'', etc).<ref name="LGSWE" />{{Rp|pages=217–218}}
Data from a corpus of American and British spoken and written English of the 1980s and 1990s show that ''dare'' (modal or lexical) is infrequent and "is found chiefly in fiction and [British English] conversation", but that in negative constructions in American fiction, lexical ''dare'' is commoner; in Britain, modal auxiliary ''dare'' is.{{sfnp|Biber|Johansson|Leech|Conrad|1999|p=163}} Further, negation of preterite ''dared'' is rare.{{sfnp|Biber|Johansson|Leech|Conrad|1999|p=164}} In both American and British English, interrogative constructions that require subject–auxiliary inversion show inversion of auxiliary ''dare'' much more commonly than ''do''-support of lexical ''dare''; however, many of the instances here of auxiliary ''dare'' are of fixed formulas (''How dare you .&nbsp;.&nbsp;.&nbsp;?'', etc).{{sfnp|Biber|Johansson|Leech|Conrad|1999|pp=217–218}}


===''Used''===
===''Used''===
{{See also|English markers of habitual aspect}}
{{See also|English markers of habitual aspect}}


'''Used''' {{IPA|/just/|lang=en}} is far more commonly encountered as a lexical than as an auxiliary verb, particularly for younger or American speakers. The plain form ''use'' (sometimes spelt {{Angbr|used}}) of the lexical verb is seen in ''Did you use to play tennis?''); although rare, its preterite perfect ''had used'' is attested. The first of ''[[The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language]]''{{`}}s five criteria for modal auxiliary verbs is irrelevant to auxiliary verb ''used'', which fails the last three. The auxiliary verb "is also semantically quite distinct from the modal auxiliaries: the meaning it expresses is aspectual, not modal."<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=115}} ''[[The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language|The Cambridge Grammar]]'' does not class auxiliary ''used'' as a modal auxiliary verb.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|page=92}}
'''Used''' {{IPA|/just/|lang=en}} is far more commonly encountered as a lexical than as an auxiliary verb, particularly for younger or American speakers. The plain form ''use'' (sometimes spelt {{Angbr|used}}) of the lexical verb is seen in ''Did you use to play tennis?''); although rare, its preterite perfect ''had used'' is attested. The first of ''[[The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language]]''{{`}}s five criteria for modal auxiliary verbs is irrelevant to auxiliary verb ''used'', which fails the last three. The auxiliary verb "is also semantically quite distinct from the modal auxiliaries: the meaning it expresses is aspectual, not modal."{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=115}} ''[[The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language|The Cambridge Grammar]]'' does not class auxiliary ''used'' as a modal auxiliary verb.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|p=92}}


For more about ''use'', see [[English auxiliary verbs#Use|English auxiliary verbs]].
For more about ''use'', see [[English auxiliary verbs#Use|English auxiliary verbs]].


===Modal idioms with ''have''===
===Modal idioms with ''have''===
The verb ''had'' in the expression '''''had better''''' lacks any untensed form (*''Tomorrow you will have better concentrate''; *''I've had better work hard since I started''; *''We're having better concentrate''), and hence is sometimes classed as a modal idiom,<ref name="CompGEL" />{{Rp|pages=141–143}}<ref name="aarts" />{{Rp|pages=303–304}}<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=108, 113}} a semi-modal,<ref name="collins_mqm" />{{Rp|page=16}}<ref>{{Cite book | author-link1=Geoffrey Leech | author-first1=Geoffrey | author-last1=Leech | author-first2=Marianne | author-last2=Hundt | author-first3=Christian | author-last3=Mair | author-first4=Nicholas | author-last4=Smith | title=Change in Contemporary English: A Grammatical Study | year=2009 | location=Cambridge | publisher=Cambridge University Press | isbn=978-0-521-86722-1 | pages=105, 106}}</ref> or an emerging or quasi-modal verb.<ref name="krug">{{Cite book | chapter=Modality and the history of English adhortatives | first=Manfred | last=Krug | pages=315–347 | title=Modality in English: Theory and Description | editor-first1=Raphael | editor-last1=Salkie | editor-first2=Pierre | editor-last2=Busuttil | editor-first3=Johan | editor-last3=van der Auwera | series=Topics in English Linguistics 58 | location=Berlin | publisher=Mouton de Gruyter | year=2009 | isbn=978-3-11-019634-4 }}</ref>{{Rp|page=332}}<!-- Krug writes "a modal (or, in the case of ''had better'', an emerging or quasi-modal) verb" -->
The verb ''had'' in the expression '''''had better''''' lacks any untensed form (*''Tomorrow you will have better concentrate''; *''I've had better work hard since I started''; *''We're having better concentrate''), and hence is sometimes classed as a modal idiom,{{sfnp|Quirk|Greenbaum|Leech|Svartvik|1985|pp=141–143}}{{sfnp|Aarts|2011|pp=303–304}}{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=108, 113}} a semi-modal,{{sfnp|Collins|2009|p=16}}{{sfnp|Leech|Hundt|Mair|Smith|2009|pp=105–106}} or an emerging or quasi-modal verb.{{sfnp|Krug|2009|p=332}}<!-- Krug writes "a modal (or, in the case of ''had better'', an emerging or quasi-modal) verb" -->


Negating ''had better'', whether by ''had better not'' or by ''hadn't better'', normally negates the subordinate clause: it is internal (''You{{`}}'''d better not''' stick around''). But as for any modal auxiliary, a negative interrogative ('''''Hadn't''' we better scarper before the police come?'') negates the matrix clause.<ref name="CamGEL" />{{Rp|pages=196, 205}}
Negating ''had better'', whether by ''had better not'' or by ''hadn't better'', normally negates the subordinate clause: it is internal (''You{{`}}'''d better not''' stick around''). But as for any modal auxiliary, a negative interrogative ('''''Hadn't''' we better scarper before the police come?'') negates the matrix clause.{{sfnp|Huddleston|Pullum|2002|pp=196, 205}}


'''Had best''' and '''had rather''' similarly lack any untensed form. ''Had best'' is much less common than ''had better''.<ref name="Auwera2013">{{Cite book | author-last1=Van der Auwera | author-first1=Johan | author-first2=Dirk | author-last2=Noël | author-first3=An | author-last3=Van linden | year=2013 | chapter=''Had better'', ''{{`}}d better'' and ''better'': Diachronic and transatlantic variation | title=English Modality: Core, Periphery and Evidentiality | series=Topics in English Linguistics 81 | editor-first1=Juana I. | editor-last1=Marín‐Arrese | editor-first2=Marta | editor-last2=Carretero | editor-first3=Jorge | editor-last3=Arús | editor-last4=Van der Auwera | editor-first4=Johan | pages=119–154| location=Berlin | publisher=De Gruyter Mouton | isbn=978-3-11-028632-8 | chapter-url=https://orbi.uliege.be/bitstream/2268/211212/1/JVA_DN_AVL_2013TiEL_hadbetter_final.pdf | via=University of Liège | access-date=29 November 2023}}</ref>{{Rp|page=6}} As ''had rather'' and ''would rather'' are both likely to be realized as ''{{`}}d rather'', it is rarely easy to decide which of the pair is being used.
'''Had best''' and '''had rather''' similarly lack any untensed form. ''Had best'' is much less common than ''had better''.{{sfnp|Van der Auwera|Noël|Van linden|2013|p=6}} As ''had rather'' and ''would rather'' are both likely to be realized as ''{{`}}d rather'', it is rarely easy to decide which of the pair is being used.


Hendrik Poutsma adds:
Hendrik Poutsma adds:


<blockquote>''I '''had as lief''''' (or ''lieve''), although now antiquated and mostly replaced by ''I had as soon'', has never fallen completely into disuse.&nbsp;.&nbsp;.&nbsp;. The shortening of ''had'' to ''{{`}}d'' has given rise to ''would'' being sometimes substituted for it.<ref name="poutsma_2nd_v1" />{{Rp|page=158}}</blockquote>
<blockquote>''I '''had as lief''''' (or ''lieve''), although now antiquated and mostly replaced by ''I had as soon'', has never fallen completely into disuse.&nbsp;.&nbsp;.&nbsp;. The shortening of ''had'' to ''{{`}}d'' has given rise to ''would'' being sometimes substituted for it.{{sfnp|Poutsma|1929|p=158}}</blockquote>


==Frequency of use==
==Frequency of use==
During the second half of the 20th century, the frequencies of use of both the modal auxiliary verbs and of alternatives to these showed considerable change. A comparison<ref name="collins_mqm" />{{Rp|page=7}}<ref>{{Cite book | author-last1=Mair | author-first1=Christian | author-first2=Geoffrey N. | author-last2=Leech | author-link2=Geoffrey Leech | year=2006 | chapter=Current changes in English syntax | editor-first1=Basil | editor-last1=Aarts | editor-first2=April | editor-last2=McMahon | editor-link2=April McMahon | title=Handbook of English Linguistics | location=Oxford | publisher=Blackwell | pages=318&ndash;342 | isbn=978-1-4051-1382-3}}</ref>{{Rp|pages=327, 328}} of the frequencies in the British corpora [[Lancaster-Oslo-Bergen Corpus|LOB]] and FLOB (with material from 1961 and 1991 respectively), and of those in the US corpora [[Brown Corpus|Brown]] and Frown (1961 and 1992 material respectively) shows:
During the second half of the 20th century, the frequencies of use of both the modal auxiliary verbs and of alternatives to these showed considerable change. A comparison{{sfnp|Collins|2009|p=7}}{{sfnp|Mair|Leech|2006|pp=327–328}} of the frequencies in the British corpora [[Lancaster-Oslo-Bergen Corpus|LOB]] and FLOB (with material from 1961 and 1991 respectively), and of those in the US corpora [[Brown Corpus|Brown]] and Frown (1961 and 1992 material respectively) shows:


{| class="wikitable" | style="margin-left: auto; margin-right: auto; border: none;"
{| class="wikitable" | style="margin-left: auto; margin-right: auto; border: none;"
Line 616: Line 616:
(Percentage changes shown in parentheses come with [[Chi-squared test|{{math|χ<sup>2</sup>}}]] values of greater than 0.05; they are of less [[statistical significance]].)
(Percentage changes shown in parentheses come with [[Chi-squared test|{{math|χ<sup>2</sup>}}]] values of greater than 0.05; they are of less [[statistical significance]].)


A study of modal auxiliary verbs and quasi-modals in American, British and Australian examples (given equal weight) of a variety of genres of written and spoken English in the 1990s found<ref name="collins_mqm" />{{Rp|page=5}} that the totals were:
A study of modal auxiliary verbs and quasi-modals in American, British and Australian examples (given equal weight) of a variety of genres of written and spoken English in the 1990s found{{sfnp|Collins|2009|p=5}} that the totals were:


{| class="wikitable" | style="margin-left: auto; margin-right: auto; border: none;"
{| class="wikitable" | style="margin-left: auto; margin-right: auto; border: none;"
Line 650: Line 650:
Commenting on a different but similar set of figures, ''[[Longman Grammar of Spoken and Written English]]'' observes of ''ought'', ''need'', ''dare'', and also ''use'' {{IPA|/jus/|lang=en}} that:
Commenting on a different but similar set of figures, ''[[Longman Grammar of Spoken and Written English]]'' observes of ''ought'', ''need'', ''dare'', and also ''use'' {{IPA|/jus/|lang=en}} that:


<blockquote>In view of the considerable attention given to these marginal auxiliaries in grammatical descriptions of English and English language teaching materials, it is worth noting how rare they are, particularly in negative and interrogative auxiliary constructions.<ref name="LGSWE" />{{Rp|page=219}}</blockquote>
<blockquote>In view of the considerable attention given to these marginal auxiliaries in grammatical descriptions of English and English language teaching materials, it is worth noting how rare they are, particularly in negative and interrogative auxiliary constructions.{{sfnp|Biber|Johansson|Leech|Conrad|1999|p=219}}</blockquote>


== Deduction ==
== Deduction ==
{{main|Epistemic modality}}
{{main|Epistemic modality}}
In English, modal verbs as ''must, have, got'' and ''could/can'' are used to express deduction and contention. These modal verbs state how sure the speaker is about something.<ref>[https://learnenglish.britishcouncil.org/en/grammar-reference/modals-deduction-present Modals – deduction (present)] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141215072628/https://learnenglish.britishcouncil.org/en/grammar-reference/modals-deduction-present |date=2014-12-15 }} ''learnenglish.britishcouncil.org''</ref><ref>[[George Yule (linguist)|George Yule]], ''Oxford Practice Grammar (Advanced)'', Oxford University Press {{ISBN|978-0-19-432754-1}} page 40</ref><ref>[http://www.ecenglish.com/learnenglish/lessons/modals-deduction-past Modals Deduction Past] ''ecenglish.com''</ref>
In English, modal verbs as ''must, have, got'' and ''could/can'' are used to express deduction and contention. These modal verbs state how sure the speaker is about something.{{sfnp|British Council|n.d.}}{{sfnp|Murphy|2013}}{{sfnp|Yule|2006|p=40}}


*You're shivering – you must be cold.
*You're shivering – you must be cold.
Line 669: Line 669:
In Standard English, since a modal auxiliary verb is followed by a verb in its plain form (which modals lack), it cannot be followed by a second modal auxiliary verb. ''Might have'' is grammatical (''have'' is here the plain form of a non-modal verb), but *''might must'' is not.
In Standard English, since a modal auxiliary verb is followed by a verb in its plain form (which modals lack), it cannot be followed by a second modal auxiliary verb. ''Might have'' is grammatical (''have'' is here the plain form of a non-modal verb), but *''might must'' is not.


Yet what appear to be sequences of modal auxiliary verbs do occur. ''Might could'', ''must can'', ''might oughta'', ''might would'', ''must could'', ''could oughta'', ''might should'', ''may can'', ''should oughta'', ''might can'', ''may could'', ''would oughta'', ''might will'', ''may will'', ''may should'' are all attested in [[Southern American English]]. Those with ''might'' as the first modal are easily the commonest, and ''might could'' is the commonest of all. Longer sequences such as ''might should oughta'' are also attested.<ref name="hasty2012">{{Cite journal | last=Hasty | first=J. Daniel | date=2012 | title=We might should oughta take a second look at this: A syntactic re-analysis of double modals in Southern United States English | journal=Lingua | volume=122 | pages=1716–1738 | doi=10.1016/j.lingua.2012.09.005}}</ref>{{Rp|pages=1717–1718}} In Britain, by contrast, the commonest is ''would might'';<ref name="coats2023">{{Cite journal | first=Steven | last=Coats | title=Double modals in contemporary British and Irish speech | journal=English Language and Linguistics | date=December 2023 | doi=10.1017/S1360674323000126 | pages=693–718 | volume=27 | number=4| doi-access=free }}</ref>{{Rp|pages=11, 17}} although commonness is relative: double modal auxiliary verbs "occur only rarely in spontaneous speech, even in varieties in which they are known to be used".<ref name="coats2023" />{{Rp|page=2}}
Yet what appear to be sequences of modal auxiliary verbs do occur. ''Might could'', ''must can'', ''might oughta'', ''might would'', ''must could'', ''could oughta'', ''might should'', ''may can'', ''should oughta'', ''might can'', ''may could'', ''would oughta'', ''might will'', ''may will'', ''may should'' are all attested in [[Southern American English]]. Those with ''might'' as the first modal are easily the commonest, and ''might could'' is the commonest of all. Longer sequences such as ''might should oughta'' are also attested.{{sfnp|Hasty|2012|pp=1717–1718}} In Britain, by contrast, the commonest is ''would might'';{{sfnp|Coats|2023|pp=11, 17}} although commonness is relative: double modal auxiliary verbs "occur only rarely in spontaneous speech, even in varieties in which they are known to be used".{{sfnp|Coats|2023|p=2}}


The syntactic status of sequences such as ''might could'' and ''would might'' is unclear. One possibility is that ''might'' has been [[Lexicalization|reanalysed]] by the speaker as an [[English adverbs|adverb]] and thus be functioning as an [[Adjunct (grammar)|adjunct]].<ref>{{Cite journal | author-last1=Lebedeva | author-first1=Irina S. | author-last2=Orlova | author-first2=Svetlana N. | year=2019 | title=Semantics and pragmatics of the double modal 'might could' | journal=Training, Language and Culture | volume=3 | number=2 | pages=71–84 | doi=10.29366/2019tlc.3.2.5 | url=https://cyberleninka.ru/article/n/semantics-and-pragmatics-of-the-double-modal-might-could | via=Cyberleninka| doi-access=free }}</ref>
The syntactic status of sequences such as ''might could'' and ''would might'' is unclear. One possibility is that ''might'' has been [[Lexicalization|reanalysed]] by the speaker as an [[English adverbs|adverb]] and thus be functioning as an [[Adjunct (grammar)|adjunct]].{{sfnp|Lebedeva|Orlova|2019|pp=71–84}}


Two rules from different grammatical models supposedly disallow the construction. [[Phrase structure grammar]] sees the surface clause as allowing only one modal verb, while main verb analysis dictates that modal verbs occur in [[Finite verb|finite forms]].<ref name=paolo>{{cite journal |title=Double modals as single lexical items |first=Marianna |last=Di Paolo |journal=[[American Speech]] |volume=64 |issue=3 |year=1989 |pages=195–224 |doi=10.2307/455589 |jstor=455589 |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/455589}}</ref>{{Rp|page=195}}
Two rules from different grammatical models supposedly disallow the construction. [[Phrase structure grammar]] sees the surface clause as allowing only one modal verb, while main verb analysis dictates that modal verbs occur in [[Finite verb|finite forms]].{{sfnp|Di Paolo|1989|p=195}}


==Comparison with other Germanic languages==
==Comparison with other Germanic languages==
Line 696: Line 696:
==References==
==References==
{{Reflist}}
{{Reflist}}

===Works cited===
{{refbegin|2}}
<!-- A -->
* {{Cite book | last=Aarts | first=Bas | title=Oxford Modern English Grammar | location=Oxford | publisher=Oxford University Press | date=2011 | isbn=978-0-19-953319-0}}
* {{Cite web | last=Adler | first=Bruce K. | title=How to depoliticize the US Supreme Court | date=15 October 2018 | website=Hippo Reads | url=https://hipporeads.com/how-to-depoliticize-the-u-s-supreme-court/ | access-date=19 December 2023}}
<!-- B -->
* {{Cite book | last=Ballantyne| first=R. M. | author-link=R. M. Ballantyne | title=Under the Waves: Diving in Deep Waters | date=2007 | orig-date=1876 | url=https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/23493/pg23493-images.html | via=Project Gutenberg}}
* {{Cite book | last=Bennett | first=Arnold | chapter=The Death of Simon Fuge | title=The Grim Smile of the Five Towns | author-link=Arnold Bennett | orig-date=1907 | location=Harmondsworth, Middlesex | publisher=Penguin | date=1971 | url=https://archive.org/details/grimsmileoffiv00benn | via=Internet Archive}}
* {{Cite book | author-last1=Biber | author-first1=Douglas | author-last2=Johansson | author-first2=Stig | author-last3=Leech | author-first3=Geoffrey | author-last4=Conrad | author-first4=Susan | author-last5=Finegan | author-first5=Edward | author-link2=Stig Johansson (linguist) | author-link3=Geoffrey Leech | title=Longman Grammar of Spoken and Written English | location=Harlow, Essex | publisher=Pearson Education | date=1999 | isbn=978-0-582-23725-4 | url=https://archive.org/details/longmangrammarof0000unse/mode/2up?view=theater | via=Internet Archive}}
* {{Cite book | last=Blackmore| first=R. D. | author-link=R. D. Blackmore | title=Slain by the Doones | date=2021 | orig-date=1895 | url=https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/22315/pg22315-images.html | via=Project Gutenberg}}
* {{cite web | ref={{harvid|British Council|n.d.}} | title=Modals – deduction (present) | date=n.d. | url=https://learnenglish.britishcouncil.org/en/grammar-reference/modals-deduction-present | url-status=dead | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141215072628/https://learnenglish.britishcouncil.org/en/grammar-reference/modals-deduction-present | archive-date=2014-12-15 | website=learnenglish.britishcouncil.org}}
<!-- C -->
* {{Cite journal | first=Steven | last=Coats | title=Double modals in contemporary British and Irish speech | journal=English Language and Linguistics | date=December 2023 | doi=10.1017/S1360674323000126 | pages=693–718 | volume=27 | number=4| doi-access=free }}
* {{Cite book | last=Collins | first=Peter | title=Modals and Quasi-modals in English | series=Language and Computers: Studies in Practical Linguistics 67 | location=Amsterdam | publisher=Rodopi | date=2009 | isbn=978-90-420-2532-5}}
* {{cite book | last1=Comrie | first1=Bernard | title=Tense | date=1985 | publisher=Cambridge University Press | isbn=978-0-521-28138-6 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=KmFMW40zyFcC | language=en}}
<!-- D -->
* {{cite news | ref={{harvid|Daily Excelsior|2018}} | url=https://www.dailyexcelsior.com/hc-rejects-quashing-of-fir-in-multi-crore-fci-scam/ | date=3 August 2018 | title=HC rejects quashing of FIR in multi-crore FCI scam | work=Daily Excelsior | access-date=19 December 2023}}
* {{cite journal | last=Di Paolo | first=Marianna | title=Double modals as single lexical items | journal=[[American Speech]] | volume=64 | issue=3 | date=1989 | pages=195–224 | doi=10.2307/455589 | jstor=455589}}
<!-- E -->
<!-- F -->
* {{Cite book | last=Fenn | first=George Manville | author-link=George Manville Fenn | title=To the West | date=2007 | orig-date=1891 | url=https://www.gutenberg.org/files/21495/21495-h/21495-h.htm | via=Project Gutenberg}}
* {{cite book | last1=Fleischman | first1=Suzanne | title=The Future in Thought and Language: Diachronic Evidence from Romance | date=1982 | publisher=Cambridge University Press | isbn=978-0-521-24389-6 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ltyLYpq0RNUC | language=en}}
<!-- G -->
* {{Cite book | last=Greenbaum | first=Sidney | author-link=Sidney Greenbaum | title=The Oxford English Grammar | location=Oxford | date=1996 |publisher=Oxford University Press | isbn=978-0-19-861250-6 }}
<!-- H -->
* {{Cite journal | last=Hasty | first=J. Daniel | date=2012 | title=We might should oughta take a second look at this: A syntactic re-analysis of double modals in Southern United States English | journal=Lingua | volume=122 | pages=1716–1738 | doi=10.1016/j.lingua.2012.09.005}}
* {{Cite book | last1=Huddleston | first1=Rodney | last2=Pullum | first2=Geoffrey K. | title=The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language | authorlink1=Rodney Huddleston | authorlink2=Geoffrey K. Pullum | publisher=Cambridge University Press | date=2002 | location=Cambridge | isbn=978-0-521-43146-0}}
<!-- I -->
<!-- J -->
<!-- K -->
* {{Cite news | last=Kapoor | first=Virendra | url=https://sundayguardianlive.com/opinion/1306-jaipur-shivir-had-one-point-agenda | date=26 January 2013 | work=The Sunday Guardian | title=Jaipur Shivir had one-point agenda | access-date=19 December 2023}}
* {{Cite web | last=Koltai | first=Anastasia | title=English Grammar: Usage of Shall vs Should with Examples | url=https://www.myenglishteacher.eu/blog/english-grammar-shall-vs-should-with-examples/ | website=My English Teacher | date=February 21, 2013}}
* {{Cite book | last=Krug | first=Manfred | chapter=Modality and the history of English adhortatives | pages=315–347 | title=Modality in English: Theory and Description | editor-first1=Raphael | editor-last1=Salkie | editor-first2=Pierre | editor-last2=Busuttil | editor-first3=Johan | editor-last3=van der Auwera | series=Topics in English Linguistics 58 | location=Berlin | publisher=Mouton de Gruyter | date=2009 | isbn=978-3-11-019634-4 }}
<!-- L -->
* {{Cite journal | author-last1=Lebedeva | author-first1=Irina S. | author-last2=Orlova | author-first2=Svetlana N. | date=2019 | title=Semantics and pragmatics of the double modal 'might could' | journal=Training, Language and Culture | volume=3 | number=2 | pages=71–84 | doi=10.29366/2019tlc.3.2.5 | url=https://cyberleninka.ru/article/n/semantics-and-pragmatics-of-the-double-modal-might-could | via=Cyberleninka | doi-access=free }}
* {{cite journal | author-last1=Lee | author-first1=Jackie F. K. | author-last2=Collins | author-first2=Peter | title=On the usage of ''have'', ''dare'', ''need'', ''ought'' and ''used to'' in Australian English and Hong Kong English | journal=World Englishes | volume=23 | number=4 | pages=501–513 | date=2004 | doi=10.1111/j.0083-2919.2004.00374.x}}
* {{Cite book | author-link1=Geoffrey Leech | author-last1=Leech | author-first1=Geoffrey | author-last2=Hundt | author-first2=Marianne | author-last3=Mair | author-first3=Christian | author-last4=Smith | author-first4=Nicholas | title=Change in Contemporary English: A Grammatical Study | date=2009 | location=Cambridge | publisher=Cambridge University Press | isbn=978-0-521-86722-1 }}
* {{Cite journal | last=Levine | first=Robert D. | date=2012 | title=Auxiliaries: ''To''{{`}}s company | journal=Journal of Linguistics | language=en | volume=48 | issue=1 | pages=187–203 | doi=10.1017/S002222671100034X | issn=0022-2267}}
* {{Cite book | last=Lovecraft | first=H. P. | author-link=H. P. Lovecraft | title=The Festival | date=2022 | orig-date=1924 | url=https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/68553/pg68553-images.html | via=Project Gutenberg}}
* {{Cite web | first=Ludwig | last=von Mises | author-link=Ludwig von Mises |title=Mises on the Velocity of Circulation | date=7 July 2020 | orig-date=1944 | website=Mises Wire | url=https://mises.org/wire/mises-velocity-circulation | access-date=19 December 2023}}
<!-- M -->
* {{Cite book | author-last1=Mair | author-first1=Christian | author-first2=Geoffrey N. | author-last2=Leech | author-link2=Geoffrey Leech | date=2006 | chapter=Current changes in English syntax | editor-first1=Basil | editor-last1=Aarts | editor-first2=April | editor-last2=McMahon | editor-link2=April McMahon | title=Handbook of English Linguistics | location=Oxford | publisher=Blackwell | pages=318–342 | isbn=978-1-4051-1382-3}}
* {{Cite book | last=Masefield | first=John | author-link=John Masefield | title=The Widow in the Bye Street | location=London | publisher=Sidgwick & Jackson | date=1912 | oclc=330395 | url=https://www.gutenberg.org/files/41468/41468-h/41468-h.html | via=Gutenberg Project}}
* {{cite web | last=Murphy | first=Chris | title=Modals Deduction Past | date=18 June 2013 | url=http://www.ecenglish.com/learnenglish/lessons/modals-deduction-past | website=ecenglish.com}}
<!-- N -->
<!-- O -->
* {{cite encyclopedia | ref={{harvid|OED|1989}} | encyclopedia=[[Oxford English Dictionary]] | edition=Second | title=need | date=1989}}
<!-- P -->
* {{cite book | last1=Palmer | first1=Frank Robert | title=Mood and Modality | date=2001 | publisher=Cambridge University Press | location=Cambridge | isbn=978-0-521-80479-0 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=xKUvDFTARR8C | language=en}}
* {{Cite book | last=Palmer | first=F. R. | author-link=Frank R. Palmer | title=The English Verb | location=London | publisher=Longman | date=1988 | isbn=978-0-582-01470-1 | edition=2nd}}
* {{cite book | last1=Palmer | first1=Frank Robert | title=A Linguistic Study of the English Verb | date=1965 | publisher=Longmans | location=London | url=https://books.google.co.uk/books?id=LSuSzgEACAAJ | language=en}}
* {{Cite book | last=Poutsma | first=H. | title=A Grammar of Late Modern English | edition=2nd | volume=1 | page=158 | publisher=P. Noordhoff | location=Groningen | oclc=697774306 | date=1929 | url=https://archive.org/details/grammaroflatemod01poutuoft/grammaroflatemod01poutuoft_bw.pdf | via=Internet Archive}}
<!-- Q -->
* {{Cite book | author-last1=Quirk | author-first1=Randolph | author-first2=Sidney | author-last2=Greenbaum | author-first3=Geoffrey | author-last3=Leech | author-first4=Jan | author-last4=Svartvik | authorlink1=Randolph Quirk | authorlink2=Sidney Greenbaum | authorlink3=Geoffrey Leech | authorlink4=Jan Svartvik | date=1985 | title=A Comprehensive Grammar of the English Language | location=London | publisher=Longman | isbn=978-0-582-51734-9}}
<!-- R -->
<!-- S -->
* {{Cite web | ref={{harvid|StudySpanish|n.d.}} | url=https://studyspanish.com/verbs/lessons/conditional.htm | website=Study Spanish | title=The Conditional Tense}}
<!-- T -->
<!-- U -->
* {{Cite web | ref={{harvid|Ultralingua|n.d.}} |url=http://ultralingua.com/onlinedictionary/references/spanish/conditional.htm | website=UltraLingua Online Dictionary & Grammar | title=Conditional tense | date=n.d. | url-status=dead | archive-url=http://arquivo.pt/wayback/20091011013417/http://ultralingua.com/onlinedictionary/references/spanish/conditional.htm | archive-date=2009-10-11}}
<!-- V -->
* {{Cite book | author-last1=Van der Auwera | author-first1=Johan | author-last2=Noël | author-first2=Dirk | author-last3=Van linden | author-first3=An | date=2013 | chapter=''Had better'', ''{{`}}d better'' and ''better'': Diachronic and transatlantic variation | title=English Modality: Core, Periphery and Evidentiality | series=Topics in English Linguistics 81 | editor-first1=Juana I. | editor-last1=Marín‐Arrese | editor-first2=Marta | editor-last2=Carretero | editor-first3=Jorge | editor-last3=Arús | editor-last4=Van der Auwera | editor-first4=Johan | pages=119–154| location=Berlin | publisher=De Gruyter Mouton | isbn=978-3-11-028632-8 | chapter-url=https://orbi.uliege.be/bitstream/2268/211212/1/JVA_DN_AVL_2013TiEL_hadbetter_final.pdf | via=University of Liège | access-date=29 November 2023}}
<!-- W -->
* {{Cite book | last=Warner | first=Anthony R. | title=English Auxiliaries: Structure and History | series=Cambridge Studies in Linguistics 66 | location=Cambridge | publisher=Cambridge University Press | date=1993 | isbn=978-0-521-30284-5}}
* {{Cite book | last=Worsaae | first=J. J. A. | author-link=Jens Jacob Asmussen Worsaae | title=An Account of the Danes and Norwegians in England, Scotland, and Ireland | location=London | publisher=John Murray | date=1852 | url=https://www.gutenberg.org/files/55409/55409-h/55409-h.htm | via=Project Gutenberg}}
<!-- X -->
<!-- Y -->
* {{Cite book | last=Yonge | first=Charlotte M. | author-link=Charlotte Mary Yonge | title=The Pillars of the House; or, Under Wode, under Rode | volume=2 | location=London | publisher=Macmillan | date=1875 | url=https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/44721/pg44721-images.html | via=Project Gutenberg}}
* {{cite book | last1=Yule | first1=George | author-link1=George Yule (linguist) | title=Oxford Practice Grammar (Advanced) | date=2006 | publisher=Oxford University Press | isbn=978-0-19-432754-1}}
<!-- Z -->
* {{Cite book | first=R. W. | last=Zandvoort | title=A Handbook of English Grammar | edition=7th | location=London | publisher=Longman | date=1975 | isbn=978-0-582-55339-2}}
{{refend}}


{{wikt|Appendix:English modal verbs}}
{{wikt|Appendix:English modal verbs}}

Revision as of 16:48, 2 January 2024

The English modal auxiliary verbs are a subset of the English auxiliary verbs used mostly to express modality (properties such as possibility and obligation).[a] They can most easily be distinguished from other verbs by their defectiveness (they do not have participles or plain forms[b]) and by their lack of the ending ‑(e)s for the third-person singular.[3]

The central English modal auxiliary verbs are can (with could), may (with might), shall (with should), will (with would), and must. A few other verbs are sometimes classed as modals: ought, and (in certain uses) dare, need and use /jus/. Other expressions, notably had better, share some of their characteristics.

A list of what tend to be regarded as modal auxiliary verbs in Modern English, along with their inflected forms, is shown in the following table.

Contractions are only shown if their orthography is distinctive. There are also unstressed versions that are typically, although not necessarily, written in the standard way.[4] Where there is a blank, the modal auxiliary verb lacks this form. (A corresponding lexical verb may have the form. For example, although the lexical verb need has a preterite form, the modal auxiliary verb need does not.)

English modal auxiliary verb paradigm
Citation
form
Plain present Preterite Confusible
lexical
homonym?[c]
Neutral Contr. Negative Neutral Contr. Negative
will will 'll won't would 'd wouldn't none
may[d] may might mightn't none
can can can't, cannot could couldn't none
shall shall 'll shan't should shouldn't none
must must mustn't none
ought ought oughtn't marginal
need[e] need needn't exists
dare[e] dare daren't dared exists
had
better
had better 'd better, better hadn't better none
used[f] used usedn't exists

Criteria for modal auxiliary verbs

Descriptive grammars of English differ slightly on the criteria they set for modal auxiliary verbs. For The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language, the criteria are as follows.

Auxiliary verbs

Modal auxiliary verbs are a subset of auxiliary verbs, and thus meet the criteria for these. For lists of these criteria, see the article English auxiliary verbs; but among them are that the verbs: (i) can invert with their subjects (notably in questions, Must I go?), (ii) can be negated with not (I must not go; Must I not go?),[8] and (iii) have negative inflected forms (won't, wouldn't).[9]

No untensed forms

To illustrate untensed forms, those of the irregular lexical verb take and the non-modal auxiliary verb be are the plain take and be (as in Take it!, I didn't take it, and Don't be silly), the gerund-participles taking and being, and the past participles taken and been.[10]

Modal auxiliary verbs lack untensed forms. Attempting to use them brings ungrammatical results:

  • *I will can drive if I take ten lessons.[g]
  • *Canning drive would be helpful.
  • *I have could/canned drive since I was 18.

Compare the grammaticality of non-modal auxiliary verb be in I will be able to drive, being able to drive, and I have been able to drive.

No subject–verb agreement

This refers to agreement of a verb (in present tense) with its third-person singular subject:

  • She can/*cans try.

Compare lexical verb try in She tries/*try, and non-modal auxiliary verb do in She does/*do try.

Had better and used lack present tense forms. Other than in present tense, even lexical verbs lack subject agreement, so this test is inapplicable to either had better or used.

Only a bare infinitival clause as complement

Whereas the lexical verb seem takes a to-infinitival clause (It seemed to happen), and the non-modal auxiliary verb have takes a past participial clause complement (It has happened), a modal auxiliary verb can (in principle) only take a bare infinitival clause (a subordinate clause with the plain form of the verb, and without to) as its complement:

  • It can be a surprise.
  • *It can to be a surprise.
  • *It can being a surprise.

If they are modal auxiliary verbs, then ought and used are exceptions to this (although ought is increasingly used with a bare infinitival clause complement).[11]

Bare infinitival clause complements are not unique to modal auxiliary verbs. Do is a non-modal auxiliary verb that takes one (Did you move the piano?); help is a lexical verb that can do so (I helped move the piano).

Ability to occur in remote apodosis

An apodosis is the "then" half of a conditional statement. (A protasis is the "if" half.) Remote here means "thought by the speaker to be unlikely" or "known by the speaker to be untrue".

  • If I were an elephant, I would eat more apples.

Compare lexical verb eat in *If I were an elephant, I ate more apples, and non-modal auxiliary verb be in *If I were an elephant, I was able to eat more apples.

Must satisfies this only for a minority of speakers, and it is questionable whether had better does so.[12]

The Cambridge Grammar comments on may that:

here there is evidence that for some speakers may and might have diverged to the extent that they are no longer inflectional forms of a single lexeme, but belong to distinct lexemes, may and might, each of which – like must – lacks a preterite....[5]

Used does not satisfy this.[7]

Preterite usable in the main clause for modal remoteness

  • I could drive there, I suppose.

If similarly intended (as a doubtful or reluctant contemplation of an option for the future), attempts at this with a lexical or non-modal auxiliary verb are ungrammatical: *I drove there, I suppose; *I was going to drive there, I suppose.

Other than when used for backshift, should has diverged in meaning so far from shall as to be usable here only with difficulty. As they lack preterite forms, must, ought and need cannot be used in this way, and so this criterion does not apply to them.[13] And used describes the past, not the present or future.

Comments

The following verbs, shown in present–preterite pairs, satisfy or come close to satisfying all of the above criteria, and can be classed as the central modal verbs of English:

  • can (with could)
  • will (with would)
  • may (with might) – although the lack in today's Standard English of a negative present inflection (*mayn't) means that it fails one of the criteria for auxiliary verbs
  • shall (with should) – although the semantic divergence of shall and should means that its success with one criterion is debatable
  • must – although its lack of a preterite (see its etymology below) means that it neither passes nor fails one of the criteria

Even for lexical verbs, preterite forms have uses besides referring to the past; but for modal auxiliary verbs such uses are particularly important: (Could you pass me the sauce?; Without my phone I might easily be lost; You should work harder; I would avoid that street).

Ought, dare, need, and used satisfy some of the criteria above, and are more (ought, dare, need) or less (used) often categorized as modal verbs.[14][15] Had better is sometimes called a modal idiom.

Other English auxiliary verbs appear in a variety of different forms and are not regarded as modal verbs. These are:

Lists of modal auxiliary verbs

Five recent scholarly descriptions of verbs disagree among themselves on the extension of modal auxiliary verb: on which verbs are modal auxiliary verbs.

They agree that can (with could), may (with might), must, shall (with should) and will with (would) are, or are among, the "central modal auxiliaries" (A Comprehensive Grammar of the English Language, 1985),[17] "secondary or modal auxiliaries" (F. R. Palmer, 1988),[18] "modal auxiliaries" (Anthony R. Warner, 1993),[19] "central members of the modal auxiliary class" (The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language, 2002),[20] or "core modal verbs" (Bas Aarts, 2011).[21]

Among these five verbs, The Cambridge Grammar selects the pair can and will (with could and would) as "the most straightforward of the modal auxiliaries"[22] (and Peter Collins agrees[23]).

All five accord ought, need and dare a less clear or merely a marginal membership.[24][18][19][25][26]

A Comprehensive Grammar and Warner do likewise for use;[27][19] the other three deny that it is a modal auxiliary verb.[28][7][29] For this reason it is primarily discussed not in this article but in the article English auxiliary verbs.)

As for would in would rather, would sooner and would as soon, and have in had better, had best and had rather, only The Cambridge Grammar notes all six, but each of the other four discussions of auxiliary verbs notes three or more. Of the three to six idioms that each discussion does note, there is no variation in the status that it accords to them. Warner calls the three that he notes – would rather, had better, had rather – modal auxiliaries.[19] Palmer says that the same three are not modal auxiliaries.[30] Both A Comprehensive Grammar and Aarts use the term modal idiom for a choice of five.[31][32] The Cambridge Grammar sees modal characteristics in all six uses of these two auxiliary verbs.[33]

A Comprehensive Grammar calls both have got (I've got to go now) and be to (You are to hand over the cash) modal idioms.[31] None of the other discussions agrees.[34][35][36][37]

Palmer calls be bound/able/going/willing to and have (got) to semi-modals.[38] A Comprehensive Grammar calls be able/about/apt/​​bound/due/going/​​likely/meant/obliged/​​supposed/willing to and have to semi-auxiliaries, adding that "The boundaries of this category are not clear".[39]

Etymology

The modals can and could are from Old English can(n) and cuþ, which were respectively present and preterite forms of the verb cunnan ("be able"). The silent l in the spelling of could results from analogy with would and should.

Similarly, may and might are from Old English mæg and meahte, respectively present and preterite forms of magan ("may, to be able"); shall and should are from sceal and sceolde, respectively present and preterite forms of sculan ("owe, be obliged"); and will and would are from wille and wolde, respectively present and preterite forms of willan ("wish, want").

The aforementioned Old English verbs cunnan, magan, sculan, and willan followed the preterite-present paradigm (or, in the case of willan, a similar but irregular paradigm), which explains the absence of the ending -s in the third person on the present forms can, may, shall, and will. (The original Old English forms given above were first and third person singular forms; their descendant forms became generalized to all persons and numbers.)

The verb must comes from Old English moste, part of the verb motan ("be able/obliged (to do something)"). This was another preterite-present verb, of which moste was in fact the preterite (the present form mot gave rise to mote, which was used as a modal verb in Early Modern English; but must has now lost its past connotations and has replaced mote). Similarly, ought was originally a past form—it derives from ahte, preterite of agan ("own"), another Old English preterite-present verb, whose present tense form ah has also given the modern (regular) verb owe (and ought was formerly used as a past tense of owe).

The verb dare also originates from a preterite-present verb, durran ("dare"), specifically its present tense dear(r), although in its non-modal uses in Modern English it is conjugated regularly. However, need comes from the regular Old English verb neodian (meaning "be necessary")—the alternative third person form need (in place of needs), which has become the norm in modal uses, became common in the 16th century.[40]

Preterite forms

The preterite forms given above (could, might, should, and would, corresponding to can, may, shall, and will, respectively) do not always simply modify the meaning of the modal to give it past time reference. The only one regularly used as an ordinary past tense is could, when referring to ability: I could swim may serve as a past form of I can swim.

All the preterites are used as past equivalents for the corresponding present modals in indirect speech and similar clauses requiring the rules of sequence of tenses to be applied. For example, if it were said in 1960 that People think that we will all be driving hovercars by the year 2000, it might now be reported that In 1960, people thought we would all be driving hovercars by the year 2000.

This "future-in-the-past" (also known as the past prospective, see: prospective) usage of would can also occur in independent sentences: I moved to Green Gables in 1930; I would live there for the next ten years.

In many cases, in order to give modals past reference, they are used together with the auxiliary have and a past participle, as in I should have asked her; You may have seen me. Sometimes these expressions are limited in meaning; for example, must have can refer only to certainty, whereas past obligation is expressed by an alternative phrase such as had to (see § Replacements for defective forms below).

Conditional sentences

The preterite forms of modals are used in the apodosis (then-clause) of counterfactual conditional sentences. The modal would (or should as a first-person alternative) is used to produce the conditional construction typically used in clauses of this type: If you loved me, you would support me. It can be replaced by could (meaning "would be able (to do something)") and might (meaning "would possibly") as appropriate.

When the clause has past time reference, the construction with the modal plus have (see above) is used: If they (had) wanted to do it, they would (could/might) have done it by now. (The would have done construction is called the conditional perfect.)

The protasis (if-clause) of such a sentence typically contains the past tense of a verb (or the past perfect construction, for past time reference), without any modal. The modal could may be used here in its role of the past tense of can (if I could speak French). However, all the modal preterites can be used in such clauses with certain types of hypothetical future reference: if I should lose or should I lose (equivalent to if I lose); if you would/might/could stop doing that (usually used as a form of request).

Sentences with the verb wish (and expressions of wish using if only...) follow similar patterns to the if-clauses referred to above, when they have counterfactual present or past reference. When they express a desired event in the near future, the modal would is used: I wish you would visit me; If only he would give me a sign.

For more information see English conditional sentences.

Second-person singular forms

Early Modern English could and often did distinguish between second-person plural you (or ye) and second-person singular thou. Rather as English verbs other than modal auxiliaries agree with third-person singular subjects in today's English, in Early Modern English, verbs in general (modal auxiliaries included) agreed with a second person subject that was distinctively singular. (There was no such agreement with instances of you or ye that happened to have singular reference.) Examples from Shakespeare are shown below.

Second-person singular (thou) forms
Plain present Preterite
can canst[α] couldst[β]
dare darest[γ] durst[δ]
may mayst, mayest[ε] mightst[ζ]
must must[η]
need needest[θ]
ought oughtest[ι]
shall shalt[θ] shouldst[κ]
will wilt[λ] wouldst[μ]
  1. ^ Thou canst not then be false to any man. (Hamlet, I.3)
  2. ^ Couldst thou save nothing? (King Lear, III.4)
  3. ^ Arrest me, foolish fellow, if thou darest. (Comedy of Errors, IV.1)
  4. ^ Durst thou have look'd upon him being awake, / And hast thou kill'd him sleeping? (Midsummer Night's Dream, III.2)
  5. ^ Safe mayst thou wander, safe return again! (Cymbeline, III.5); If thou mayest discern by that which is left of him what he is, fetch me to the sight of him. (Winter's Tale, III.3)
  6. ^ Then mightst thou speak, then mightst thou tear thy hair (Romeo and Juliet, III.3)
  7. ^ thou must know the king is full of grief (Winter's Tale, IV.4)
  8. ^ a b thy horse stands behind the hedge: when thou needest him, there thou shalt find him (Henry IV, Part 1, II.2)
  9. ^ thou oughtest not to let thy horse wear a cloak (Henry VI, Part 2, IV.7)
  10. ^ Wherefore shouldst thou pity her? (Two Gentlemen of Verona, IV.4)
  11. ^ Wilt thou be lord of all the world? (Antony and Cleopatra, II.7)
  12. ^ Why, whither, Adam, wouldst thou have me go? (As You Like It, II.3)

Replacements for defective forms

As noted above, English modal verbs are defective in that they do not have any untensed form, or, for some, preterite forms. However in many cases there exist expressions that carry the same meaning as the modal, and can be used to supply the missing forms. In particular:

  • The modals can and could, expressing ability, can be replaced by be able to, with the appropriate inflection of be.
  • The modals may and might, expressing permission, can be replaced by be allowed to, again with the appropriate inflection of be.
  • The modal must in most meanings can be replaced by have to, with the appropriate inflection of have.
  • When used for futurity, will can be replaced by be going to, with the appropriate inflection of be.
  • The modals should and ought to might be replaced by be supposed to, again with the appropriate inflection of be.

Weak forms

Most of the modals have negative inflected forms: can't, won't, etc. Although these started as weak forms (contractions), they are so no longer.[9] Genuine contractions are:[41]

  • can /ˈkæn//kən/
  • could /ˈkʊd//kəd/
  • shall /ˈʃæl//ʃəl/
  • should /ˈʃʊd//ʃəd/
  • will /ˈwɪl//wəl/, /l/
  • would /ˈwʊd//wəd/, /d/
  • had better /ˈhæd ˈbɛtəɹ//həd ˈbɛtəɹ/, /d ˈbɛtəɹ/, /ˈbɛtəɹ/

When shall and should are first-person replacements for will and would, they too may take the weak forms ‑ll and ‑d.[citation needed]

A combination like should have is normally reduced to /ʃʊd(h)əv/ or just /ʃʊdə/ shoulda. Also, ought to can become /ɔːtə/ oughta.[42] See weak and strong forms in English.

Effect of negation

Either or both of two kinds of negation can apply to a construction using a modal auxiliary verb. What is called internal negation is limited to the subordinate clause. The difference between He might have overheard you and He might not have overheard you (with internal negation) is that between "It is possible that he overheard you" and "It is possible that he did not overhear you".[43]

By contrast, what is called external negation applies to the matrix clause. The difference between He could have overheard you and He couldn't have overheard you (with external negation) is that between "It is possible that he overheard you" and "It is not possible that he overheard you".[43]

Not can be moved into the subordinate clause. He might have not overheard you has the same meaning as He might not have overheard you; but He could have not overheard you means "It is possible that he did not overhear you".[44]

The two kinds of negation can be combined. He can't have not overheard you means "It is not possible that he did not overhear you".[44]

Likewise, the difference between You mustn't apologize and You needn't apologize is that the former shows internal negation, inverting the necessity; the latter external negation, negating the necessity.[45]

Whether negating a modal auxiliary verb brings negation of the subordinate or the matrix clause (internal or external negation respectively) thus depends on the particular verb (and this in turn partly depends on the strength of the modality that the verb expresses), and there may be other determining factors as well. However: "Negative interrogatives, used as questions biased towards a positive answer, have external negation irrespective of the strength of the modality [. . .] A special case of this is in tags: We must stop soon, mustn't we?"[46]

Usage of specific verbs

Can and could

The modal verb can expresses possibility in a dynamic, deontic, or epistemic sense, that is, in terms of innate ability, permissibility, or probability. For example:

  • Dynamic
    • Ability:[47] You needn't struggle with your Tamil when talking to me: I can speak English ("I am capable of speaking English"; "I know how to speak English")
    • Existential:[48] Most siblings get along at least tolerably well, but there can be strong rivalry between them (such rivalry does sometimes occur)
    • The reasonable/acceptable:[48] You can be a few minutes late; nobody will mind
    • The circumstantially possible:[48] Petrol left for months in an unused car can wreck its fuel line (This is the result of a predictable chemical process that is not being prevented.)
  • Deontic:[49] Smoking is forbidden anywhere in this building, but you can smoke behind the bicycle shed ("You are permitted to smoke here")
  • Epistemic:[50] He did the "Ironman" in under seven hours? That can't be true. ("It is impossible for that to be true.")

The preterite form could is used as the past tense or remote conditional form of can in the above meanings (see § Preterite forms above). It is also used to express likelihood: We could be in trouble here. It is preferable to use could, may or might rather than can when expressing likelihood in a particular situation[citation needed] (as opposed to the general case, as in the "rivalry" example above, where can or may is used).

Both can and could can be used to make requests:[51] Can/could you pass me the cheese? means "Please pass me the cheese" (where could is more polite[52]). Either can be used with possibly: Can/could you possibly pass me the cheese?[53] Requests with can't may sound impatient (Can't you be quiet?)[52]

It is common to use can with verbs of perception such as see, hear, etc., as in I can see a tree.[47] Aspectual distinctions can be made, such as I could see it (ongoing state) vs. I saw it (event).[citation needed]

Could have expresses past ability or possibility, either in some counterfactual circumstance: I could have told him if I had seen him; I could have told him yesterday (but I didn't).

Can have... is less common than may have....[citation needed]

Can may be negated by the addition of not /kən ˈnɒt/, analogously to the addition of not to could, may, will and so forth. It can also be negated by inflection; its commoner inflected form is can't /ˈkɑnt/, /ˈkɑnt/, or /kant/ (in RP, General American and General Australian respectively). However, it has an alternative inflected form, cannot /ˈkænɒt/. Can not and cannot thus differ in placement of the single stress. Can not is more formal than can't, and does not invert with its subject (Can't/*Cannot we leave now?).[54]

Negated, could has the inflected form couldn't.

Negating can or could is external: it negates the matrix clause, expressing inability, impermissibility or impossibility (I can't wear jeans). This differs from may or might used to express possibility: It can't be true does not mean It may not be true. Thus can't (or cannot) is often used to express disbelief even in possibility, as must expresses belief in the certainty. When the reference is to the past, have is used: He can't/cannot have done it means "It is not possible that he did it" (compare He must have done it).

With special stress, internal negation is possible: I can NOT wear a suit, if I wish means "I am not compelled to wear a suit if I don't want to".[55]

May and might

The verb may expresses possibility in either an epistemic or deontic sense, that is, in terms of probability or permissibility. For example:

  • The mouse may be dead means that it is possible that the mouse (perhaps audible until the day before) is now dead.
  • Trevor may leave if he'd prefer to play with his friends means that Trevor is permitted to leave.

May can have future as well as present reference (He may arrive means that it is possible that he will arrive; I may go to the mall means that I am considering going to the mall).

The preterite form might is used as a synonym of may when expressing possible circumstance (as can could – see above). It is sometimes said[according to whom?] that might and could express more doubt than may. For uses of might in conditional sentences, and as a past equivalent to may in such contexts as indirect speech, see § Preterite forms above.

May (or might) can also express concession of a minor point: He may be taller than me, but he's certainly not stronger could mean "While I'd agree that he is taller than me, that is unimportant, as he's certainly not stronger."

May can indicate permission for present or future actions, or be a polite directive: You may go now. Might used in this way is milder: You might go now if you feel like it. Similarly, May I use your phone? is a request for permission; Might I use your phone? would be more hesitant or polite.

A less common use of may is optative (to express a wish), as in May you live long and happy[56] (see also English subjunctive).

May have indicates uncertainty about a past circumstance, whereas might have can have that meaning, but it can also refer to possibilities that did not occur but could have (see also conditional sentences above).

  • She may have eaten the cake. (The speaker does not know whether she did.)
  • She might have eaten the cake. (The speaker either does not know whether she did, or knows that she did not eat cake but that her eating it would have been possible.)

May have is used for possibility, not permission (although the second sense of might have might sometimes imply permission).

The inflected form mayn't is obsolete. The inflected form mightn't mostly appears in the tags of tag questions (It might snow tonight, mightn't it?) and in other questions expressing doubt (Mightn't I come in if I took my boots off?).

The result of negating may or might depends on whether the interpretation is epistemic (about likelihood) or deontic (about permission). In epistemic senses, the negation is "internal", of the subordinate clause (There may not be a vote on it this week). In deontic senses, the negation is normally external (You may not go to the party unless you finish your homework), but with special stress, internal negation is possible: (I may NOT attend church, if I wish, meaning "I have permission not to attend church").[57]

Shall and should

The verb shall is used in some varieties of English in place of will when the subject is first person (I shall, we shall).

With second- and third-person subjects, shall indicates a directive or prophecy: Cinderella, you shall go to the ball! It is often used in writing laws and specifications: Those convicted of violating this law shall be imprisoned for a term of not less than three years; The device shall be able to operate within a normal temperature range.

Shall is sometimes used in requests for advice or confirmation of a suggestion: Shall I read now?; What shall we wear?[58]

Should is sometimes used as a first-person equivalent to would (in its conditional and "future-in-the-past" uses), in the same way that shall can replace will. Should is also used for a protasis with future reference: either with the preposition if (If you should meet her, please give her this) or with subject–auxiliary inversion (Should you meet her, please give her this).

Should is often used to describe an expected or recommended act or state. It can be used to give advice or to describe normative behavior, though without such strong obligatory force as must or have to. Thus You should never lie describes a social or ethical norm. It can also express what is expected: This should work. In these uses it is equivalent to ought.

Both shall and should can be used with have (shall/should have (done)) in their role as first-person equivalents of will and would (thus to form future perfect or conditional perfect structures). Also shall have may express an order with perfective aspect (You shall have finished your duties by nine o'clock). When should is used in this way it usually expresses something which would have been expected at some time in the past, but which did not in fact happen (or is not known to have happened): I should have done that yesterday ("It would have been expedient, or expected of me, to do that yesterday").

The negative inflections are shan't and shouldn't.

Negating should negates the subordinate clause: the negation is internal (You shouldn't use botox).[59] (To negate the meaning of I should, one may useI ought not to or I am not supposed to.)

As for any modal auxiliary, a negative interrogative (Shouldn't you check your credit card statement?) instead negates the matrix clause.[46]

Will and would

  • Will often expresses futurity (The next meeting will be held on Thursday). Since this is an expression of time rather than modality, constructions with will (or sometimes shall; see "Shall and should" above) are often called the future tense. For those speakers who for first-person subjects (I, we) use shall to express futurity, the use of will for these indicates particular resolve. (Future events are also sometimes described with the present tense (see Uses of English verb forms), or using the going to construction.)
  • Will can express habitual aspect or dynamic modality; for example, He will make mistakes (in which will is usually stressed somewhat) may mean that he seems often to make them.

Will also has these uses as a modal:[60][61]

  • It can express strong probability with present time reference, as in That will be John at the door.
  • It can be used to give an indirect order, as in You will do it right now.

Modal uses of the preterite form would include:

  • Would is used in some conditional sentences.[vague]
  • Expression of politeness, as in I would like to... (to politely state a preference) and Would you (be so kind as to) do this? (for "Please do this").

As a tense marker, would is used for

  • Future of the past, as in I knew I would graduate two years later. Would is the past form of future will as described above under § Preterite forms. (It is sometimes replaced by should in the first person in the same way that will is replaced by shall.)

As an aspect marker, would is used for

  • Expression of habitual aspect in past time, as in Back then, I would eat early and would walk to school.[62][63]

Both will and would can be used with have (will have, would have), either to form the future perfect and conditional perfect forms already referred to, or to express perfective aspect in their other meanings (e.g. there will have been an arrest order, expressing strong probability).

The negative inflections are won't and wouldn't. For contracted forms of will and would themselves, see "Weak forms", above.

Negating will or would is "internal": it negates the subordinate clause. (I won't be surprised if it rains means I will be unsurprised if it rains.) But as for any modal auxiliary, a negative interrogative (Won't/Wouldn't we submit them in person?) negates the matrix clause.[64]

Would rather, would sooner, and would as soon

Would rather, would sooner, or would as soon can take as its complement either a bare infinitival clause (She would rather go herself) or a declarative content clause (She would rather (that) I went).[22] They are PPIs:[65] although I would rather not catch the virus (with negation of the clause that is subordinate to would rather) is idiomatic, *I wouldn't rather catch the virus (with negation of the matrix clause) is distinctly strange. Whether its reference is to past, present or future, the declarative content clause complement can use the preterite: I'd rather you hadn't told her that (past counterfactual); I'd rather you didn't tell her that (present/future); I'd rather you didn't tell her that when you meet her (future).[66]

Must

Must differs from the central modal auxiliary verbs in lacking a preterite. It expresses obligation or necessity: You must use this form; We must try to escape. It can also express a conclusion reached by indirect evidence (e.g. Sue must be at home).

When used with have and a past participle, must has only an epistemic flavor: Sue must have left means that the speaker concludes that Sue has left. To express obligation or necessity in the past, had to or some other synonym must be used.

The negative inflection of must is mustn't. Negation of must is "internal", negating the subordinate clause: (You must not/mustn't drive after smoking a joint means that not driving is what you must do). But as for any modal auxiliary, a negative interrogative (Mustn't we hide the dope?) negates the matrix clause.[67] To express the lack of requirement or obligation, the negative of have to or need (see below) can be used: You don't have to do this; You needn't do this.

Negated, must is not commonly used in an epistemic sense, where it is common to use can't (It can't be here; Sue can't have left) instead.

Mustn't can nonetheless be used as a simple negative of must in tag questions and other questions expressing doubt: We must do it, mustn't we? Mustn't he be in the operating room by this stage?

Must and needs can occur in sequence. Hendrik Poutsma writes that "The force of must, notably that of representing the subject under pressure of an overmastering desire [. . . ], is often emphasized by needs."[68] Examples of the pair are:

  • The control of the Firm needs must stay within the Family.[69]
  • It needs must be said that any observation made in this order shall not be taken as observations on merits[70]
  • thinking it through to its ultimate logical consequences must needs lead to insoluble contradictions[71]
  • the Constitution envisions, and by extension the country as a whole must needs have, a truly high-minded Supreme Court[72]

Ought

Ought differs from the central modal auxiliary verbs both in taking as its complement a to-infinitival rather than a bare infinitival clause (compare He should go with He ought to go) and in lacking a preterite.

Ought is used with meanings similar to those of should, expressing expectation or requirement.

The reduced pronunciation of ought to (see "Weak forms" above) is sometimes spelt oughtta.

Ought can be used with have in the same way as should (plus intervening to): You ought to have done that earlier. Ought not to or oughtn't to can be substituted for shouldn't.

Had better has a similar meaning to should and ought for a deontic meaning (expressing recommended or expedient behavior (You ought to / should / had better arrive on time), but not (other perhaps than jokingly) for an epistemic meaning (The Sun ought to / should / ?had better come out soon).

Negating ought is "internal": it negates the subordinate clause (I ought not to have a third glassful means that what I ought to do is decline the glassful). But as for any modal auxiliary, a negative interrogative (Oughtn't we to offer cola as well as beer?) negates the matrix clause.[73]

The use of ought as a lexical verb as in They didn't ought to go is generally thought of as restricted to non-standard dialects[74] but has been described as also sometimes found in informal standard usage.[75] "Lexical ought with the dummy operator do has been condemned in British usage handbooks. . . . What this censure suggests is that lexical ought with periphrastic do is a well-established usage in colloquial [British English]."[76]

Data from a corpus of American and British spoken and written English of the 1980s and 1990s show that ought not to, oughtn't to (both modal auxiliary), and didn't ought to are rare in both American and British English, whether written or spoken. I don't think you ought to and similar are commonly used instead.[77] In interrogatives, ought does not appear in American conversation or fiction or in British conversation; in British fiction, the modal auxiliary is used (Ought we to . . . ?), not lexical ought with do-support.[78]

Need

As a modal auxiliary verb, need is a negative polarity item, appearing in negative contexts and other contexts that do not affirm. Thus:

  • We need not remain silent.
  • Need we remain silent?
  • *We need remain silent.

Like must, modal need has no preterite form.

Although as a modal auxiliary verb need takes a bare infinitival clause complement (He needn't overhaul it), lexical verb need can take either an object complement (He needs my help) or a to-infinitival clause complement (He needs to overhaul it), optionally with a subject (He needs me to overhaul it).

Negation of need is external, negating the matrix clause. You needn't apply again does not say that there is a need not to apply, merely that there is no need to apply.[79] So although the verb must can usually be substituted for the modal verb need, mustn't usually cannot be substituted for needn't. (Exceptionally, the pair are synonymous in polar interrogatives: Needn't/mustn't we pay now?)

Modal need can also be used with have: Need I have done that? It is most commonly used here in the negative, meaning that an action was (from the present perspective) not in fact necessary: You needn't have left that tip.

Data from a corpus of American and British spoken and written English of the 1980s and 1990s show that for negative constructions involving need, modal auxiliary need is commoner in written English (both American and British), but is less common than lexical need in British English conversation and unused in American English conversation.163 In both American and British English, interrogative constructions that require subject–auxiliary inversion show do-support of lexical need much more commonly than inversion of auxiliary need; moreover, many of what instances there are of auxiliary need are of fixed formulas (Need I say more?, etc).[80]

For "needs must" (and "must needs") see under must.

Dare

As a modal auxiliary verb, dare too is a negative polarity item, appearing in negative contexts and other contexts that do not affirm.

Dare is now much commoner as a lexical verb. Lexical verb dare takes a to-infinitival clause as its complement (I didn't dare to answer her), and this may have a subject (He dared me to dive from a higher board); modal dare, a bare infinitival clause complement.

Negation of dare is external: what is negated is the matrix clause. (She dare not attempt it means "She doesn't dare to attempt it".)[81]

Examples of the use of modal auxiliary dare, followed by equivalents using lexical dare where appropriate:

  • If he dare try it, he may succeed. ("If he dares to try it, he may succeed.")
  • If he dared try it, he might succeed. ("If he dared to try it, he might succeed.")
  • Dare he do it? ("Does he dare to do it?")
  • Dared he do it? ("Did he dare to do it?")
  • I daren't (or dare not) try. ("I don't dare to try.")
  • I dared not try. ("I didn't dare to try.")
  • How dare you! (formulaic expression of outrage)
  • I dare say (or daresay) it's true. (Another formulaic expression, here exceptionally in an affirmative context, unexpected for an NPI)

However, thanks to its affirmative context, *He dared speak up is ungrammatical.

Although seemingly obsolete in the 21st century, daredn't was in use in the early 20th. Examples:

  • "I daredn't hurry," said Mr Colclough, setting us down at the station. "I was afraid of a skid."[82]
  • One's so safe with such a son to con her / Through all the noises and through all the press, / Boys daredn't squirt tormenters on her dress.[83]

Dared has supplanted an earlier preterite form, durst.[84] Examples:

  • The former [. . .] retired with cattle and other booty to their mountains, whither they knew well the Lowlanders durst not follow them.[85]
  • Other debts I durst not face.[86]
  • dizzy church-crowned central peak that time durst not touch[87]

Durst had a negative inflected form, durstn't. Examples:

  • I'm under authority, you know, and durstn't overstep[88]
  • the boat, where I durstn't kick for fear of poking my feet through the bottom[89]
  • I durstn't go home to tell Mother Pring[90]

Lexical verb dare is close to an NPI: She dared to speak up is much less likely than She didn't dare to speak up.[91] And the lexical–modal distinction is blurred: "lexical dare commonly occurs in non-affirmative contexts without to": She wouldn't dare ask her father; and it also can be stranded, as in She ought to have asked for a raise, but she didn't dare.[92]

Data from a corpus of American and British spoken and written English of the 1980s and 1990s show that dare (modal or lexical) is infrequent and "is found chiefly in fiction and [British English] conversation", but that in negative constructions in American fiction, lexical dare is commoner; in Britain, modal auxiliary dare is.[93] Further, negation of preterite dared is rare.[94] In both American and British English, interrogative constructions that require subject–auxiliary inversion show inversion of auxiliary dare much more commonly than do-support of lexical dare; however, many of the instances here of auxiliary dare are of fixed formulas (How dare you . . . ?, etc).[95]

Used

Used /just/ is far more commonly encountered as a lexical than as an auxiliary verb, particularly for younger or American speakers. The plain form use (sometimes spelt ⟨used⟩) of the lexical verb is seen in Did you use to play tennis?); although rare, its preterite perfect had used is attested. The first of The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language's five criteria for modal auxiliary verbs is irrelevant to auxiliary verb used, which fails the last three. The auxiliary verb "is also semantically quite distinct from the modal auxiliaries: the meaning it expresses is aspectual, not modal."[7] The Cambridge Grammar does not class auxiliary used as a modal auxiliary verb.[96]

For more about use, see English auxiliary verbs.

The verb had in the expression had better lacks any untensed form (*Tomorrow you will have better concentrate; *I've had better work hard since I started; *We're having better concentrate), and hence is sometimes classed as a modal idiom,[31][32][33] a semi-modal,[97][98] or an emerging or quasi-modal verb.[99]

Negating had better, whether by had better not or by hadn't better, normally negates the subordinate clause: it is internal (You'd better not stick around). But as for any modal auxiliary, a negative interrogative (Hadn't we better scarper before the police come?) negates the matrix clause.[100]

Had best and had rather similarly lack any untensed form. Had best is much less common than had better.[101] As had rather and would rather are both likely to be realized as 'd rather, it is rarely easy to decide which of the pair is being used.

Hendrik Poutsma adds:

I had as lief (or lieve), although now antiquated and mostly replaced by I had as soon, has never fallen completely into disuse. . . . The shortening of had to 'd has given rise to would being sometimes substituted for it.[102]

Frequency of use

During the second half of the 20th century, the frequencies of use of both the modal auxiliary verbs and of alternatives to these showed considerable change. A comparison[103][104] of the frequencies in the British corpora LOB and FLOB (with material from 1961 and 1991 respectively), and of those in the US corpora Brown and Frown (1961 and 1992 material respectively) shows:

Changes in frequencies of use of English modals and quasi-modals
Modals Quasi-modals
BrE AmE BrE AmE
can (+2.2%) (–1.5%) be going to (–1.2%) +51.6%
could (+2.4%) –6.8% be to –17.2% –40.1%
may –17.4% –32.4% had better (–26.0%) (–17.1%)
might –15.1% (–4.5%) have got to (–34.1%) (+15.6%)
must –29.0% –34.4% have to (+9.0%) (+1.1%)
need –40.2% (–12.5%) need to +249.1% +123.2%
ought to –44.2% (–30.0%) be supposed to +113.6% (+6.3%)
shall –43.7% –43.8% want to +18.5% +70.9%
should –11.8% –13.5%
will (–2.7%) –11.1%
would –11.0% –6.1%

(Percentage changes shown in parentheses come with χ2 values of greater than 0.05; they are of less statistical significance.)

A study of modal auxiliary verbs and quasi-modals in American, British and Australian examples (given equal weight) of a variety of genres of written and spoken English in the 1990s found[105] that the totals were:

Frequencies of use of English modals and quasi-modals
Modals Quasi-modals
can 7663 be able to 889
could 3557 be about to 124
may 2261 be bound to 27
might 1499 be going to 2721
must 1367 be supposed to 171
need 56 be to 371
ought to 126 had better 89
shall 343 have got to 705
should 2432 have to 2827
will 8505 need to 716
would 7775 want to 1897
Total 35584 Total 10537

Commenting on a different but similar set of figures, Longman Grammar of Spoken and Written English observes of ought, need, dare, and also use /jus/ that:

In view of the considerable attention given to these marginal auxiliaries in grammatical descriptions of English and English language teaching materials, it is worth noting how rare they are, particularly in negative and interrogative auxiliary constructions.[106]

Deduction

In English, modal verbs as must, have, got and could/can are used to express deduction and contention. These modal verbs state how sure the speaker is about something.[107][108][109]

  • You're shivering – you must be cold.
  • Someone must have taken the key: it is not here.
  • I didn't order ten books. This has to be a mistake.
  • These aren't mine – they've got to be yours.
  • It can't be a burglar. All the doors and windows are locked.

Modals at the head of chains

The verb governed by the modal may be another auxiliary (necessarily one that can appear in plain form—this includes be and have, but not another modal, except in the non-standard cases described below under § Double modals). Hence a modal may introduce a chain (technically a catena) of verb forms, in which the other auxiliaries express properties such as aspect and voice, as in He must have been given a new job. If infinitival to is regarded as an auxiliary verb, then longer chains are possible, as in He must have been encouraged to try to serve tea.

Double modals

In Standard English, since a modal auxiliary verb is followed by a verb in its plain form (which modals lack), it cannot be followed by a second modal auxiliary verb. Might have is grammatical (have is here the plain form of a non-modal verb), but *might must is not.

Yet what appear to be sequences of modal auxiliary verbs do occur. Might could, must can, might oughta, might would, must could, could oughta, might should, may can, should oughta, might can, may could, would oughta, might will, may will, may should are all attested in Southern American English. Those with might as the first modal are easily the commonest, and might could is the commonest of all. Longer sequences such as might should oughta are also attested.[110] In Britain, by contrast, the commonest is would might;[111] although commonness is relative: double modal auxiliary verbs "occur only rarely in spontaneous speech, even in varieties in which they are known to be used".[112]

The syntactic status of sequences such as might could and would might is unclear. One possibility is that might has been reanalysed by the speaker as an adverb and thus be functioning as an adjunct.[113]

Two rules from different grammatical models supposedly disallow the construction. Phrase structure grammar sees the surface clause as allowing only one modal verb, while main verb analysis dictates that modal verbs occur in finite forms.[114]

Comparison with other Germanic languages

Many English modals have cognates in other Germanic languages, if often with different meanings. Unlike the English modals, however, these verbs are not generally defective. Examples of such cognates include:

  • In German: mögen, müssen, können, sollen, wollen; cognates of may, must, can, shall, and will. Although German shares five modal verbs with English, their meanings are often quite different. Mögen does not mean "be allowed" but "may" as epistemic modal and "like" as a normal verb followed by a noun phrase. It can be followed by an infinitive with the meaning of "have a desire (to do something)". Wollen means "will" only in the sense of "want (to do something)" and is not used for future reference, for which werden is used instead. Müssen, können, and sollen are used similarly to English "must", "can", and "shall". The negation of müssen is a literal one in German, not an inverse one as in English": German ich muss ("I must") means "I need (to do something)", and ich muss nicht (literally "I must not") accordingly means "I don't need (to do something)". In English, "have (to do something)" behaves the same way, whereas English "must" expresses an interdiction when negated. brauchen (need) is sometimes used like a modal verb, especially negated (Er braucht nicht kommen. "He need not come.").
  • In Dutch: mogen, moeten, kunnen, zullen, willen; cognates of may, must, can, shall, and will.
  • In Danish: måtte, kunne, ville, skulle, cognates of may/must, can, will, shall. They generally have the same meanings as in English, with the exception of ville, which usually means "want (to do something)" (but which can also mean "will").
  • In Swedish: (past tense: måtte), måsta, kunna, vilja, ska(ll), cognates of may/might, must, can, will, shall. Their meanings generally correspond to those in English, with the exception of vilja, which means "want (to do something)".

Since modal verbs in other Germanic languages are not defective, the problem of double modals (see above) does not arise: the second modal verb in such a construction simply takes the infinitive form, as would any verb in the same position. Compare the following translations of English "I want to be able to dance", all of which translate literally as "I want can dance" (except the German, as "I want dance can"):

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Although there are non-auxiliary modal verbs in English, such as "require" and "oblige", with the aim of brevity this article often uses "modal" or "modal verb" to mean "modal auxiliary verb".
  2. ^ The plain form of a verb is exemplified by beware and by the form be of the verb be: You should beware of the dog; You should be careful. It is distinguished from the plain present form of the verb, exemplified by am, are, and were. For any verb aside from be that is not defective, the plain and plain present forms have identical pronunciation and spelling.[1][2]
  3. ^ More precisely: Does there exist a lexical verb with the same spelling and pronunciation that is synonymous or could be said to have an auxiliary (or copular) function? (Ignored here is any lexical verb – will meaning "exert one's will in an attempt to compel", can meaning "insert into cans", etc – that is unlikely to be mistaken for the auxiliary verb.)
  4. ^ "[T]here is evidence that for some speakers [of Standard English] may and might have diverged to the extent that they are no longer inflectional forms of a single lexeme, but belong to distinct lexemes, may and might, each of which – like must – lacks a preterite. . . ."[5]
  5. ^ a b An NPI, rare for speakers of Standard American English.[5]
  6. ^ Pronounced /just/ (rhyming with "roost"). Auxiliary verb form used should be distinguished from the homonymous adjective used, as in I've got (very) used to it.[6] (The homographic verb form used /juzd/, rhyming with "refused", is lexical only.) "For many speakers [of Standard English], especially younger ones", use /jus/ is exclusively a lexical verb.[7]
  7. ^ This article uses asterisks ⟨*⟩ to indicate ungrammatical expressions. As an example, "She can/*cans try" means that although She can try is grammatical, *She cans try is not.

References

  1. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 104.
  2. ^ Aarts (2011), pp. 83–85.
  3. ^ Quirk et al. (1985), [page needed].
  4. ^ Palmer (1988), pp. 242–248.
  5. ^ a b c Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 109.
  6. ^ Zandvoort (1975), p. 85.
  7. ^ a b c d Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 115.
  8. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 94–107.
  9. ^ a b Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 91.
  10. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 74–75.
  11. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 109, 115.
  12. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 109, 113.
  13. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 108–110.
  14. ^ Palmer (2001), p. 33.
  15. ^ Palmer (1965), [page needed].
  16. ^ Levine (2012), pp. 187–204.
  17. ^ Quirk et al. (1985), pp. 135–136.
  18. ^ a b Palmer (1988), p. 26.
  19. ^ a b c d Warner (1993), p. 11.
  20. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 108–109.
  21. ^ Aarts (2011), pp. 280–298.
  22. ^ a b Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 108.
  23. ^ Collins (2009), p. 14.
  24. ^ Quirk et al. (1985), pp. 138–140.
  25. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 109–111.
  26. ^ Aarts (2011), pp. 298–301.
  27. ^ Quirk et al. (1985), pp. 138, 140.
  28. ^ Palmer (1988), p. 170.
  29. ^ Aarts (2011), pp. 273–274.
  30. ^ Palmer (1988), pp. 170–171.
  31. ^ a b c Quirk et al. (1985), pp. 141–143.
  32. ^ a b Aarts (2011), pp. 303–304.
  33. ^ a b Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 108, 113.
  34. ^ Palmer (1988), pp. 128–131, 141–143.
  35. ^ Warner (1993), p. 46.
  36. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 111–114.
  37. ^ Aarts (2011), pp. 301–302, 304–305.
  38. ^ Palmer (1988), p. 106.
  39. ^ Quirk et al. (1985), pp. 143–146.
  40. ^ OED (1989).
  41. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 1613.
  42. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 1615.
  43. ^ a b Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 175.
  44. ^ a b Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 175, 1216.
  45. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 176.
  46. ^ a b Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 205.
  47. ^ a b Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 185.
  48. ^ a b c Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 184.
  49. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 183.
  50. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 181.
  51. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 865.
  52. ^ a b Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 940.
  53. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 768, 770.
  54. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 1611.
  55. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 180, 184, 204, 804–805.
  56. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 856, 944.
  57. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 180, 182, 184, 204.
  58. ^ Koltai (2013).
  59. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 187, 204.
  60. ^ Fleischman (1982), pp. 86–97.
  61. ^ Comrie (1985), pp. 21, 47–48.
  62. ^ Ultralingua (n.d.).
  63. ^ StudySpanish (n.d.).
  64. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 193, 205.
  65. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 829.
  66. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 1003–1004.
  67. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 180, 182, 204, 205.
  68. ^ Poutsma (1929), p. 61.
  69. ^ Kapoor (2013).
  70. ^ Daily Excelsior (2018).
  71. ^ von Mises (2020).
  72. ^ Adler (2018).
  73. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 187, 205.
  74. ^ Quirk et al. (1985), p. 140.
  75. ^ Greenbaum (1996), p. 155.
  76. ^ Lee & Collins (2004), p. 502.
  77. ^ Biber et al. (1999), p. 165.
  78. ^ Biber et al. (1999), p. 218.
  79. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 180.
  80. ^ Biber et al. (1999), p. 217.
  81. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 196.
  82. ^ Bennett (1971), p. 186.
  83. ^ Masefield (1912), [page needed].
  84. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 110n.
  85. ^ Worsaae (1852), [page needed].
  86. ^ Yonge (1875), [page needed].
  87. ^ Lovecraft (2022), [page needed].
  88. ^ Ballantyne (2007), [page needed].
  89. ^ Fenn (2007), [page needed].
  90. ^ Blackmore (2021), [page needed].
  91. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 110–111.
  92. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 110.
  93. ^ Biber et al. (1999), p. 163.
  94. ^ Biber et al. (1999), p. 164.
  95. ^ Biber et al. (1999), pp. 217–218.
  96. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), p. 92.
  97. ^ Collins (2009), p. 16.
  98. ^ Leech et al. (2009), pp. 105–106.
  99. ^ Krug (2009), p. 332.
  100. ^ Huddleston & Pullum (2002), pp. 196, 205.
  101. ^ Van der Auwera, Noël & Van linden (2013), p. 6.
  102. ^ Poutsma (1929), p. 158.
  103. ^ Collins (2009), p. 7.
  104. ^ Mair & Leech (2006), pp. 327–328.
  105. ^ Collins (2009), p. 5.
  106. ^ Biber et al. (1999), p. 219.
  107. ^ British Council (n.d.).
  108. ^ Murphy (2013).
  109. ^ Yule (2006), p. 40.
  110. ^ Hasty (2012), pp. 1717–1718.
  111. ^ Coats (2023), pp. 11, 17.
  112. ^ Coats (2023), p. 2.
  113. ^ Lebedeva & Orlova (2019), pp. 71–84.
  114. ^ Di Paolo (1989), p. 195.

Works cited