Jump to content

Cognitivism (ethics): Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
m Category:Ethics
PrimeBOT (talk | contribs)
m →‎top: Task 44 (trial): clean up shortdesc whitespace issues
 
(104 intermediate revisions by 74 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Meta-ethical theory}}
In [[ethics]], '''cognitivism''' is the view that ethical sentences express propositions. See also [[non-cognitivism]].
{{Other uses|Cognitivism (disambiguation)}}
{{Refimprove|article|date=January 2008}}


'''Cognitivism''' is the [[meta-ethics|meta-ethical]] view that ethical [[Sentence (linguistics)|sentence]]s express [[proposition]]s and can therefore be [[truth value|true or false]] (they are truth-apt), which [[non-cognitivism|noncognitivists]] deny.<ref>{{cite encyclopedia | url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-cognitivism/ | title=Moral Cognitivism vs. Non-Cognitivism | encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy| year=2018 }}</ref> Cognitivism is so broad a thesis that it encompasses (among other views) [[moral realism]] (which claims that ethical sentences express propositions about mind-independent facts of the world), [[ethical subjectivism]] (which claims that ethical sentences express propositions about peoples' attitudes or opinions), and [[error theory]] (which claims that ethical sentences express propositions, but that they are all false, whatever their nature).
[[Proposition]]s are, roughly, what meaningful declarative [[sentence]]s are supposed to ''express'' (but not interrogative or imperative sentences). Different sentences, in different languages, can (it is often thought) express the same proposition: 'snow is white' and 'Schnee ist weiss' both express the proposition that snow is white. A common assumption among philosophers who use this jargon is that propositions, properly speaking, are what are true or false (what bear [[truth value]]s; they are [[correspondence theory of truth|truthbearers]]). So if an ethical sentence does express a proposition, then the sentence expresses something that can be true or false.


==Overview==
To get a better idea of what it means to express a proposition, compare this to something that ''does not'' express a proposition. Suppose someone minding a convenience store sees a thief pick up a candy bar and run. The storekeeper manages to exclaim, "Hey!" In this case, "Hey!" does not express a proposition. Among the things that the ejaculation does not express are, "that's a thief there"; "that thief is getting away"; or "that thief really annoys me." The storekeeper isn't saying anything at all, really, at least nothing that can be true or false. So it is not a ''proposition'' that the storekeeper is expressing. Perhaps it is an ''emotional state'' that is being expressed. The storekeeper is surprised and angered, and expresses those emotions by saying, "Hey!"
Propositions are what meaningful [[declarative sentence]]s (but not interrogative or imperative sentences) are supposed to ''express''. Different sentences, in different languages, can express the same proposition: "snow is white" and "Schnee ist weiß" (in [[German language|German]]) both express the proposition that [[snow]] [[Copula (linguistics)|is]] [[white]]. A common belief among philosophers who use this jargon is that propositions, properly speaking, are what are true or false (what bear [[truth value]]s; they are [[correspondence theory of truth|truthbearers]]).


To get a better idea of what it means to express a proposition, compare this to something that ''does not'' express a proposition. Suppose someone minding a [[convenience store]] sees a thief pick up a [[candy bar]] and run. The storekeeper manages to exclaim, "Hey!" In this case, "Hey!" does not express a proposition. Among the things that the exclamation does not express are, "that's a thief there"; "thieving is wrong"; "please stop that thief"; or "that thief really annoys me." The storekeeper isn't saying anything that can be true or false. So it is not a ''proposition'' that the storekeeper is expressing. Perhaps it is an ''emotional state'' that is being expressed. The storekeeper is surprised and angered, and expresses those feelings by saying, "Hey!"
It is an essential part of [[ethical naturalism]] that ethical sentences ''do'' express propositions. They are not just emotional outbursts, as though we were saying, "Hey!" or "Yay for Mary!" They are actually expressing propositions that can be true or false. Derivatively, the naturalist would say that ethical sentences themselves are either true or false.


Ethical cognitivists hold that ethical sentences ''do'' express propositions: that it can be true or false, for example, that Mary is a good person, or that stealing and lying are always wrong. Cognitivists believe that these sentences do not just express feelings, as though we were saying, "Hey!" or "Yay for Mary!"; they actually express propositions that can be true or false. Derivatively, a cognitivist or a realist would say that ethical sentences themselves are either true or false. Conversely, if one believes that sentences like "Mary is a good person" cannot be either true or false, then one is a [[non-cognitivism|non-cognitivist]].
But cognitivism does also agree with ethical [[irrealism]] or [[anti-realism]]. Ethical naturalism (or ethical realism) and ethical cognitivism are different theories. Several [[meta-ethics|metaethical]] theories accept that ethical sentences can be true or false, even if there are no natural, physical or in any way ''real'' (also called «worldly») entities to make them true or false. In a similar way as there is no real entity to make true the sentence «If it had rained yesterday, the floor would have been wet.» [[John Skorupski]] defends normative cognitivist irrealism distinguishing between receptive awareness, which is not possible in [[norm (philosophy)|normative]] matters, and non-receptive awareness (including dialogical knowledge), which is possible in normative matters.


==Cognitivism and subjectivism==
Cognitivism points to the [[semantics|semantic]] difference between imperative [[sentence]]s and declarative sentences in normative subjects. Or to the different meanings and purposes of some superficially declarative sentences. For instance, if a teacher allows one of her students to go out by saying «You may go out, this sentence is neither true or false. It ''gives'' a permission. But, in most situations, if one of the students asks one of his classmates whether she thinks that he may go out and she answers «Of course you may go out, this sentence is either true or false. It does not ''give'' a permission, it states that ''there is'' a permission.


[[Ethical subjectivism]] is the [[meta-ethics|meta-ethical]] view which claims that:
Another argument for ethical cognitivism stands on the close resemblance between ethics and other normative matters, such as [[game]]s. As much as [[morality]], games consist of norms (or [[rule]]s), but it would be hard to accept that it be not true that the [[chess]]player who checkmates the other one wins the game. If statements about game rules can be true or false, why not ethical statements?
# Ethical [[Sentence (linguistics)|sentence]]s express [[proposition]]s.
# Some such propositions are true.
# Those propositions are about the attitudes of people.<ref>{{Harvnb|Brandt|1959|p=153}}: "[Objectivism and subjectivism] have been used more vaguely, confusedly, and in more different senses than the others we are considering. We suggest as a convenient usage, however, that a theory be called subjectivist [[if and only if]], according to it, any ethical assertion implies that somebody does, or somebody of a certain sort under certain conditions would, take ''some specified attitude'' toward something."</ref>


This makes ethical subjectivism a form of cognitivism. Ethical subjectivism stands in opposition to [[moral realism]], which claims that moral propositions refer to objective facts, independent of human opinion; to [[error theory]], which denies that any moral propositions are true in any sense; and to [[non-cognitivism]], which denies that moral sentences express propositions at all.
An ethical naturalist and other ethical cognitivists might hold that it can be true or false that Mary is a good person; it can be true or false that stealing and lying are always wrong. On the other hand, if one believes the sentence, "Mary is a good person," cannot be either true or false, then one is not a cognitivist.


The most common forms of ethical subjectivism are also forms of [[moral relativism]], with moral standards held to be relative to each culture or society (c.f. [[cultural relativism]]), or even to every individual. The latter view, as put forward by [[Protagoras]], holds that there are as many distinct scales of good and evil as there are subjects in the world.<ref>"moral subjectivism is that species of moral relativism that relativizes moral value to the individual subject". [http://www.iep.utm.edu/r/relativi.htm Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]</ref> However, there are also [[moral universalism|universalist]] forms of subjectivism such as [[ideal observer theory]] (which claims that moral propositions are about what attitudes a hypothetical ideal observer would hold) and [[divine command theory]] (which claims that moral propositions are about what attitudes God holds).
Notice, too, that if we say that ethical sentences ''merely'' express emotions (they "do" no more than that: see [[speech act]]), as though they were just exclamations like "Hey!" and "Yay for Mary!", then we cannot also think that ethical sentences are true or false. It would be nonsense to say, "It's true that 'Hey!'" or "It's false that 'Yay for Mary!'" Mere expressions of emotion might be appropriate ("apt" is the jargon bandied here) or inappropriate, but not true or false. This is the claim of [[emotivism]].


==Cognitivism and objectivism==
[[Category:Ethics]]

Cognitivism encompasses all forms of [[moral realism]], but cognitivism can also agree with ethical [[irrealism (philosophy)|irrealism]] or [[anti-realism]]. Aside from the [[subjectivist]] branch of cognitivism, some cognitive irrealist theories accept that ethical sentences can be objectively true or false, even if there [[existence|exist]] no natural, physical or in any way [[reality|real]] (or "[[world]]ly") [[wikt:entity|entities]] or [[object (philosophy)|object]]s to make them true or false.

There are a number of ways of construing how a proposition can be objectively true without corresponding to the world:
* By the [[coherence theory of truth|coherence]] rather than the [[correspondence theory of truth]]
* In a figurative sense: it can be true that I have a cold, but that doesn't mean that the word "cold" corresponds to a distinct entity.
* In the way that mathematical statements are true for [[Mathematical anti-realism|mathematical anti-realists]]. This would typically be the idea that a proposition can be true if it is an entailment of some intuitively appealing [[axiom]]—in other words, ''[[a priori knowledge|a priori]]'' analytical reasoning.

[[Crispin Wright]], [[John Skorupski]] and some others defend normative cognitivist irrealism. Wright asserts the extreme implausibility of both [[J. L. Mackie]]'s error-theory and [[non-cognitivism]] (including [[Simon Blackburn|S. Blackburn]]'s [[quasi-realism]]) in view of both everyday and sophisticated moral speech and argument. The same point is often expressed as the [[Expressivism#The Embedding Problem (or, the Frege–Geach objection)|Frege-Geach Objection]]. Skorupski distinguishes between receptive awareness, which is not possible in [[norm (philosophy)|normative]] matters, and non-receptive awareness (including dialogical knowledge), which is possible in normative matters.

[[Hilary Putnam]]'s book ''Ethics without Ontology'' ([[Harvard University Press|Harvard]], 2004) argues for a similar view, that ethical (and for that matter [[mathematics|mathematical]]) sentences can be true and [[Objectivity (philosophy)|objective]] without [[ontology|there being]] any objects to make them so.

Cognitivism points to the [[semantics|semantic]] difference between [[Imperative mood|imperative]] [[Sentence (linguistics)|sentence]]s and [[declarative sentence]]s in normative subjects. Or to the different meanings and purposes of some superficially declarative sentences. For instance, if a teacher allows one of her students to go out by saying "You may go out", this sentence is neither true nor false. It ''gives'' a permission. But, in most situations, if one of the students asks one of his classmates whether she thinks that he may go out and she answers "Of course you may go out", this sentence is either true or false. It does not ''give'' a permission, it states that ''there is'' a permission.

Another argument for ethical cognitivism stands on the close resemblance between ethics and other normative matters, such as [[game]]s. As much as [[morality]], games consist of norms (or [[wiktionary:rule|rule]]s), but it would be hard to accept that it be not true that the [[chess]]player who checkmates the other one wins the game. If statements about game rules can be true or false, why not ethical statements? One answer is that we may want ethical statements to be [[categorical syllogism|categorically]] true, while we only need statements about right action to be [[Contingency (philosophy)|contingent]] on the acceptance of the rules of a particular game—that is, the choice to play the game according to a given set of rules.

== See also ==
* [[Glossary of philosophical isms]]
* [[Non-cognitivism]]
* [[Transcognition]]

==Notes==
<references />

==Bibliography==
* {{Cite book |last=Brandt |first=Richard |title=Ethical Theory |publisher=Prentice Hall |year=1959 |location=Englewood Cliffs |language=en |chapter=Ethical Naturalism |lccn=59010075 |author-link=Richard Brandt}}

==Further reading==
* {{Cite book |title=Truth in Ethics |publisher=Blackwell |year=1996 |isbn=978-0-631-19701-0 |editor-last=Hooker |editor-first=Brad |editor-link=Brad Hooker |location=Oxford}}

== External links ==
* ''[[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]'' entry on [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-cognitivism/ Moral Cognitivism and Non-Cognitivism]
{{Ethics}}
[[Category:Ethical theories]]
[[Category:Metaethics]]
[[Category:Cognition]]

[[de:Metaethik#Kognitivismus]]
[[sv:Kognitivism]]

Latest revision as of 11:53, 4 April 2024

Cognitivism is the meta-ethical view that ethical sentences express propositions and can therefore be true or false (they are truth-apt), which noncognitivists deny.[1] Cognitivism is so broad a thesis that it encompasses (among other views) moral realism (which claims that ethical sentences express propositions about mind-independent facts of the world), ethical subjectivism (which claims that ethical sentences express propositions about peoples' attitudes or opinions), and error theory (which claims that ethical sentences express propositions, but that they are all false, whatever their nature).

Overview

[edit]

Propositions are what meaningful declarative sentences (but not interrogative or imperative sentences) are supposed to express. Different sentences, in different languages, can express the same proposition: "snow is white" and "Schnee ist weiß" (in German) both express the proposition that snow is white. A common belief among philosophers who use this jargon is that propositions, properly speaking, are what are true or false (what bear truth values; they are truthbearers).

To get a better idea of what it means to express a proposition, compare this to something that does not express a proposition. Suppose someone minding a convenience store sees a thief pick up a candy bar and run. The storekeeper manages to exclaim, "Hey!" In this case, "Hey!" does not express a proposition. Among the things that the exclamation does not express are, "that's a thief there"; "thieving is wrong"; "please stop that thief"; or "that thief really annoys me." The storekeeper isn't saying anything that can be true or false. So it is not a proposition that the storekeeper is expressing. Perhaps it is an emotional state that is being expressed. The storekeeper is surprised and angered, and expresses those feelings by saying, "Hey!"

Ethical cognitivists hold that ethical sentences do express propositions: that it can be true or false, for example, that Mary is a good person, or that stealing and lying are always wrong. Cognitivists believe that these sentences do not just express feelings, as though we were saying, "Hey!" or "Yay for Mary!"; they actually express propositions that can be true or false. Derivatively, a cognitivist or a realist would say that ethical sentences themselves are either true or false. Conversely, if one believes that sentences like "Mary is a good person" cannot be either true or false, then one is a non-cognitivist.

Cognitivism and subjectivism

[edit]

Ethical subjectivism is the meta-ethical view which claims that:

  1. Ethical sentences express propositions.
  2. Some such propositions are true.
  3. Those propositions are about the attitudes of people.[2]

This makes ethical subjectivism a form of cognitivism. Ethical subjectivism stands in opposition to moral realism, which claims that moral propositions refer to objective facts, independent of human opinion; to error theory, which denies that any moral propositions are true in any sense; and to non-cognitivism, which denies that moral sentences express propositions at all.

The most common forms of ethical subjectivism are also forms of moral relativism, with moral standards held to be relative to each culture or society (c.f. cultural relativism), or even to every individual. The latter view, as put forward by Protagoras, holds that there are as many distinct scales of good and evil as there are subjects in the world.[3] However, there are also universalist forms of subjectivism such as ideal observer theory (which claims that moral propositions are about what attitudes a hypothetical ideal observer would hold) and divine command theory (which claims that moral propositions are about what attitudes God holds).

Cognitivism and objectivism

[edit]

Cognitivism encompasses all forms of moral realism, but cognitivism can also agree with ethical irrealism or anti-realism. Aside from the subjectivist branch of cognitivism, some cognitive irrealist theories accept that ethical sentences can be objectively true or false, even if there exist no natural, physical or in any way real (or "worldly") entities or objects to make them true or false.

There are a number of ways of construing how a proposition can be objectively true without corresponding to the world:

  • By the coherence rather than the correspondence theory of truth
  • In a figurative sense: it can be true that I have a cold, but that doesn't mean that the word "cold" corresponds to a distinct entity.
  • In the way that mathematical statements are true for mathematical anti-realists. This would typically be the idea that a proposition can be true if it is an entailment of some intuitively appealing axiom—in other words, a priori analytical reasoning.

Crispin Wright, John Skorupski and some others defend normative cognitivist irrealism. Wright asserts the extreme implausibility of both J. L. Mackie's error-theory and non-cognitivism (including S. Blackburn's quasi-realism) in view of both everyday and sophisticated moral speech and argument. The same point is often expressed as the Frege-Geach Objection. Skorupski distinguishes between receptive awareness, which is not possible in normative matters, and non-receptive awareness (including dialogical knowledge), which is possible in normative matters.

Hilary Putnam's book Ethics without Ontology (Harvard, 2004) argues for a similar view, that ethical (and for that matter mathematical) sentences can be true and objective without there being any objects to make them so.

Cognitivism points to the semantic difference between imperative sentences and declarative sentences in normative subjects. Or to the different meanings and purposes of some superficially declarative sentences. For instance, if a teacher allows one of her students to go out by saying "You may go out", this sentence is neither true nor false. It gives a permission. But, in most situations, if one of the students asks one of his classmates whether she thinks that he may go out and she answers "Of course you may go out", this sentence is either true or false. It does not give a permission, it states that there is a permission.

Another argument for ethical cognitivism stands on the close resemblance between ethics and other normative matters, such as games. As much as morality, games consist of norms (or rules), but it would be hard to accept that it be not true that the chessplayer who checkmates the other one wins the game. If statements about game rules can be true or false, why not ethical statements? One answer is that we may want ethical statements to be categorically true, while we only need statements about right action to be contingent on the acceptance of the rules of a particular game—that is, the choice to play the game according to a given set of rules.

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ "Moral Cognitivism vs. Non-Cognitivism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2018.
  2. ^ Brandt 1959, p. 153: "[Objectivism and subjectivism] have been used more vaguely, confusedly, and in more different senses than the others we are considering. We suggest as a convenient usage, however, that a theory be called subjectivist if and only if, according to it, any ethical assertion implies that somebody does, or somebody of a certain sort under certain conditions would, take some specified attitude toward something."
  3. ^ "moral subjectivism is that species of moral relativism that relativizes moral value to the individual subject". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Bibliography

[edit]

Further reading

[edit]
[edit]