Jump to content

List of fallacies

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This is an old revision of this page, as edited by Paradoctor (talk | contribs) at 21:54, 5 August 2017 (top: WP:GENDER; remove one mislink; remove unnecessary link text on another). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

In reasoning to argue a claim[disambiguation needed], a fallacy is reasoning that is evaluated as logically incorrect and that vitiates the logical validity of the argument and permits its recognition as unsound. Regardless of their unsoundness, all registers and manners of speech can demonstrate fallacies.

Because of their variety of structure and application, fallacies are challenging to classify so as to satisfy all practitioners. Fallacies can be classified strictly by either their structure or content, such as classifying them as formal fallacies or informal fallacies, respectively. The classification of informal fallacies may be subdivided into categories such as linguistic, relevance through omission, relevance through intrusion, and relevance through presumption.[1] On the other hand, fallacies may be classified by the process by which they occur, such as material fallacies (content), verbal fallacies (linguistic), and again formal fallacies (error in inference). In turn, material fallacies may be placed into the more general category of informal fallacies as formal fallacies may be clearly placed into the more precise category of logical or deductive fallacies[clarification needed]. Yet, verbal fallacies may be placed in either informal or deductive classifications; compare equivocation which is a word or phrase based ambiguity, e. g. "he is mad", which may refer to either him being angry or clinically insane, to the fallacy of composition which is premise and inference based ambiguity, e. g. "this must be a good basketball team because each of its members is an outstanding player".[2]

Faulty inferences in deductive reasoning are common formal or logical fallacies. As the nature of inductive reasoning is based in probability, a fallacious inductive argument or one that is potentially misleading, is often classified as "weak".

The conscious or habitual use of fallacies as rhetorical devices are prevalent in the desire to persuade, when the focus is more on communication and eliciting common agreement rather than the correctness of the reasoning. One may consider the effective use of a fallacy by an orator as clever but by the same token the reasoning of that orator should be recognized as unsound, and thus the orator's claim, supported by an unsound argument, will be regarded as unfounded and dismissed.[3]

Formal fallacies

A formal fallacy is an error in logic that can be seen in the argument's form.[4] All formal fallacies are specific types of non sequiturs.

Propositional fallacies

A propositional fallacy is an error in logic that concerns compound propositions. For a compound proposition to be true, the truth values of its constituent parts must satisfy the relevant logical connectives that occur in it (most commonly: <and>, <or>, <not>, <only if>, <if and only if>). The following fallacies involve inferences whose correctness is not guaranteed by the behavior of those logical connectives, and hence, which are not logically guaranteed to yield true conclusions.
Types of propositional fallacies:

Quantification fallacies

A quantification fallacy is an error in logic where the quantifiers of the premises are in contradiction to the quantifier of the conclusion.
Types of Quantification fallacies:

Formal syllogistic fallacies

Syllogistic fallacies – logical fallacies that occur in syllogisms.

Informal fallacies

Informal fallacies – arguments that are fallacious for reasons other than structural (formal) flaws and usually require examination of the argument's content.[15]

  • Appeal to the stone (argumentum ad lapidem) – dismissing a claim as absurd without demonstrating proof for its absurdity.[16]
  • Argument from ignorance (appeal to ignorance, argumentum ad ignorantiam) – assuming that a claim is true because it has not been or cannot be proven false, or vice versa.[17]
  • Argument from incredulity (appeal to common sense) – "I cannot imagine how this could be true; therefore, it must be false."[18]
  • Argument from repetition (argumentum ad nauseam, argumentum ad infinitum) – signifies that it has been discussed extensively until nobody cares to discuss it anymore;[19][20] sometimes confused with proof by assertion
  • Argument from silence (argumentum ex silentio) – where the conclusion is based on the absence of evidence, rather than the existence of evidence.[21][22]
  • Argument to moderation (false compromise, middle ground, fallacy of the mean, argumentum ad temperantiam) – assuming that the compromise between two positions is always correct.[23]
  • Begging the question (petitio principii) – providing what is essentially the conclusion of the argument as a premise.[24][25][26][27]
  • Shifting the burden of proof (see – onus probandi) – I need not prove my claim, you must prove it is false.
  • Circular reasoning (circulus in demonstrando) – when the reasoner begins with what he or she is trying to end up with; sometimes called assuming the conclusion.
  • Circular cause and consequence – where the consequence of the phenomenon is claimed to be its root cause.
  • Continuum fallacy (fallacy of the beard, line-drawing fallacy, sorites fallacy, fallacy of the heap, bald man fallacy) – improperly rejecting a claim for being imprecise.[28]
  • Correlative-based fallacies
  • Divine fallacy (argument from incredulity) – arguing that, because something is so incredible/amazing/ununderstandable, it must be the result of superior, divine, alien or paranormal agency.[31]
  • Double counting – counting events or occurrences more than once in probabilistic reasoning, which leads to the sum of the probabilities of all cases exceeding unity.
  • Equivocation – the misleading use of a term with more than one meaning (by glossing over which meaning is intended at a particular time).[32]
    • Ambiguous middle term – a common ambiguity in syllogisms in which the middle term is equivocated.[33]
    • Definitional retreat – changing the meaning of a word to deal with an objection raised against the original wording.[1]
  • Ecological fallacy – inferences about the nature of specific individuals are based solely upon aggregate statistics collected for the group to which those individuals belong.[34]
  • Etymological fallacy – which reasons that the original or historical meaning of a word or phrase is necessarily similar to its actual present-day usage.[35]
  • Fallacy of accent – a specific type of ambiguity that arises when the meaning of a sentence is changed by placing an unusual prosodic stress, or when, in a written passage, it's left unclear which word the emphasis was supposed to fall on.
  • Fallacy of composition – assuming that something true of part of a whole must also be true of the whole.[36]
  • Fallacy of division – assuming that something true of a thing must also be true of all or some of its parts.[37]
  • False attribution – an advocate appeals to an irrelevant, unqualified, unidentified, biased or fabricated source in support of an argument.
    • Fallacy of quoting out of context (contextomy, quote mining) – refers to the selective excerpting of words from their original context in a way that distorts the source's intended meaning.[38]
  • False authority (single authority) – using an expert of dubious credentials or using only one opinion to sell a product or idea. Related to the appeal to authority fallacy.
  • False dilemma (false dichotomy, fallacy of bifurcation, black-or-white fallacy) – two alternative statements are held to be the only possible options, when in reality there are more.[39]
  • False equivalence – describing a situation of logical and apparent equivalence, when in fact there is none.
  • Fallacy of many questions (complex question, fallacy of presupposition, loaded question, plurium interrogationum) – someone asks a question that presupposes something that has not been proven or accepted by all the people involved. This fallacy is often used rhetorically, so that the question limits direct replies to those that serve the questioner's agenda.
  • Fallacy of the single cause (causal oversimplification[40]) – it is assumed that there is one, simple cause of an outcome when in reality it may have been caused by a number of only jointly sufficient causes.
  • Furtive fallacy – outcomes are asserted to have been caused by the malfeasance of decision makers.
  • Gambler's fallacy – the incorrect belief that separate, independent events can affect the likelihood of another random event. If a fair coin lands on heads 10 times in a row, the belief that it is "due to the number of times it had previously landed on tails" is incorrect.[41]
  • Historian's fallacy – occurs when one assumes that decision makers of the past viewed events from the same perspective and having the same information as those subsequently analyzing the decision.[42] (Not to be confused with presentism, which is a mode of historical analysis in which present-day ideas, such as moral standards, are projected into the past.)
  • Historical fallacy – where a set of considerations holds good only because a completed process is read into the content of the process which conditions this completed result.[43]
  • Homunculus fallacy – where a "middle-man" is used for explanation, this sometimes leads to regressive middle-men. Explains without actually explaining the real nature of a function or a process. Instead, it explains the concept in terms of the concept itself, without first defining or explaining the original concept. Explaining thought as something produced by a little thinker, a sort of homunculus inside the head, merely explains it as another kind of thinking (as different but the same).[44]
  • Inflation of conflict – The experts of a field of knowledge disagree on a certain point, so the scholars must know nothing, and therefore the legitimacy of their entire field is put to question.[45]
  • If-by-whiskey – an argument that supports both sides of an issue by using terms that are selectively emotionally sensitive.
  • Incomplete comparison – in which insufficient information is provided to make a complete comparison.
  • Inconsistent comparison – where different methods of comparison are used, leaving one with a false impression of the whole comparison.
  • Intentionality fallacy – the insistence that the ultimate meaning of an expression must be consistent with the intention of the person from whom the communication originated (e.g. a work of fiction that is widely received as a blatant allegory must necessarily not be regarded as such if the author intended it not to be so.)[46]
  • Ignoratio elenchi (irrelevant conclusion, missing the point) – an argument that may in itself be valid, but does not address the issue in question.[47]
  • Kettle logic – using multiple, jointly inconsistent arguments to defend a position.[dubiousdiscuss]
  • Ludic fallacy – the belief that the outcomes of non-regulated random occurrences can be encapsulated by a statistic; a failure to take into account unknown unknowns in determining the probability of events taking place.[48]
  • McNamara fallacy (quantitative fallacy) – making a decision based only on quantitative observations, discounting all other considerations.
  • Moralistic fallacy – inferring factual conclusions from purely evaluative premises in violation of fact–value distinction. For instance, inferring is from ought is an instance of moralistic fallacy. Moralistic fallacy is the inverse of naturalistic fallacy defined below.
  • Moving the goalposts (raising the bar) – argument in which evidence presented in response to a specific claim is dismissed and some other (often greater) evidence is demanded.
  • Naturalistic fallacy – inferring evaluative conclusions from purely factual premises[49] in violation of fact–value distinction. For instance, inferring ought from is (sometimes referred to as the is-ought fallacy) is an instance of naturalistic fallacy. Also naturalistic fallacy in a stricter sense as defined in the section "Conditional or questionable fallacies" below is an instance of naturalistic fallacy. Naturalistic fallacy is the inverse of moralistic fallacy.
  • Naturalistic fallacy fallacy[50] (anti-naturalistic fallacy)[51] – inferring an impossibility to infer any instance of ought from is from the general invalidity of is-ought fallacy, mentioned above. For instance, is does imply ought for any proposition , although the naturalistic fallacy fallacy would falsely declare such an inference invalid. Naturalistic fallacy fallacy is an instance of argument from fallacy.
  • Nirvana fallacy (perfect solution fallacy) – when solutions to problems are rejected because they are not perfect.
  • Onus probandi – from Latin "onus probandi incumbit ei qui dicit, non ei qui negat" the burden of proof is on the person who makes the claim, not on the person who denies (or questions the claim). It is a particular case of the argumentum ad ignorantiam fallacy, here the burden is shifted on the person defending against the assertion.
  • Post hoc ergo propter hoc Latin for "after this, therefore because of this" (faulty cause/effect, coincidental correlation, correlation without causation) – X happened, then Y happened; therefore X caused Y. The Loch Ness Monster has been seen in this loch. Something tipped our boat over; it's obviously the Loch Ness Monster.[52]
  • Proof by assertion – a proposition is repeatedly restated regardless of contradiction; sometimes confused with argument from repetition (argumentum ad infinitum, argumentum ad nauseam)
  • Prosecutor's fallacy – a low probability of false matches does not mean a low probability of some false match being found.
  • Proving too much – using a form of argument that, if it were valid, could be used to reach an additional, undesirable conclusion.
  • Psychologist's fallacy – an observer presupposes the objectivity of his own perspective when analyzing a behavioral event.
  • Red herring – a speaker attempts to distract an audience by deviating from the topic at hand by introducing a separate argument the speaker believes is easier to speak to.[53]
  • Referential fallacy[54] – assuming all words refer to existing things and that the meaning of words reside within the things they refer to, as opposed to words possibly referring to no real object or that the meaning of words often comes from how we use them.
  • Regression fallacy – ascribes cause where none exists. The flaw is failing to account for natural fluctuations. It is frequently a special kind of post hoc fallacy.
  • Reification (concretism, hypostatization, or the fallacy of misplaced concreteness) – a fallacy of ambiguity, when an abstraction (abstract belief or hypothetical construct) is treated as if it were a concrete, real event or physical entity. In other words, it is the error of treating as a "real thing" something that is not a real thing, but merely an idea.
  • Retrospective determinism – the argument that because an event has occurred under some circumstance, the circumstance must have made its occurrence inevitable.
  • Shotgun argumentation – the arguer offers such a large number of arguments for a position that the opponent can't possibly respond to all of them. (See "Argument by verbosity" and "Gish Gallop", above.)
  • Special pleading – where a proponent of a position attempts to cite something as an exemption to a generally accepted rule or principle without justifying the exemption.
  • Wrong direction – cause and effect are reversed. The cause is said to be the effect and vice versa.[55]

Faulty generalizations

Faulty generalizations – reach a conclusion from weak premises. Unlike fallacies of relevance, in fallacies of defective induction, the premises are related to the conclusions yet only weakly buttress the conclusions. A faulty generalization is thus produced.

  • Accident – an exception to a generalization is ignored.[56]
    • No true Scotsman – makes a generalization true by changing the generalization to exclude a counterexample.[57]
  • Cherry picking (suppressed evidence, incomplete evidence) – act of pointing at individual cases or data that seem to confirm a particular position, while ignoring a significant portion of related cases or data that may contradict that position.[58]
    • Survivorship bias – when a small number of survivors of a given process are actively promoted while completely ignoring a large number of failures
  • False analogy – an argument by analogy in which the analogy is poorly suited.[59]
  • Hasty generalization (fallacy of insufficient statistics, fallacy of insufficient sample, fallacy of the lonely fact, leaping to a conclusion, hasty induction, secundum quid, converse accident) – basing a broad conclusion on a small sample.[60]
  • Inductive fallacy – A more general name to some fallacies, such as hasty generalization. It happens when a conclusion is made of premises that lightly support it.
  • Misleading vividness – involves describing an occurrence in vivid detail, even if it is an exceptional occurrence, to convince someone that it is a problem.
  • Overwhelming exception – an accurate generalization that comes with qualifications that eliminate so many cases that what remains is much less impressive than the initial statement might have led one to assume.[61]
  • Thought-terminating cliché – a commonly used phrase, sometimes passing as folk wisdom, used to quell cognitive dissonance, conceal lack of thought-entertainment, move on to other topics etc. but in any case, end the debate with a cliché—not a point.

Red herring fallacies

A red herring fallacy, one of the main subtypes of fallacies of relevance, is an error in logic where a proposition is, or is intended to be, misleading in order to make irrelevant or false inferences. In the general case any logical inference based on fake arguments, intended to replace the lack of real arguments or to replace implicitly the subject of the discussion.[62][63][64]

Red herring – argument given in response to another argument, which is irrelevant and draws attention away from the subject of argument. See also irrelevant conclusion.

  • Ad hominem – attacking the arguer instead of the argument.
    • Poisoning the well – a subtype of ad hominem presenting adverse information about a target person with the intention of discrediting everything that the target person says.[65]
    • Abusive fallacy – a subtype of ad hominem that verbally abuses the opponent rather than arguing about the originally proposed argument.[66]
    • Appeal to motive – a subtype of ad hominem that dismisses an idea by questioning the motives of its proposer.
    • Tone policing – a subtype of ad hominem focusing on emotion behind a message rather than the message itself as a discrediting tactic.
    • Traitorous critic fallacy (ergo decedo) – a subtype of ad hominem where a critic's perceived affiliation is seen as the underlying reason for the criticism and the critic is asked to stay away from the issue altogether.
  • Appeal to authority (argumentum ad verecundiam) – where an assertion is deemed true because of the position or authority of the person asserting it.[67][68]
  • Appeal to consequences (argumentum ad consequentiam) – the conclusion is supported by a premise that asserts positive or negative consequences from some course of action in an attempt to distract from the initial discussion.[70]
  • Appeal to emotion – where an argument is made due to the manipulation of emotions, rather than the use of valid reasoning.[71]
    • Appeal to fear – a specific type of appeal to emotion where an argument is made by increasing fear and prejudice towards the opposing side[72][73]
    • Appeal to flattery – a specific type of appeal to emotion where an argument is made due to the use of flattery to gather support.[74]
    • Appeal to pity (argumentum ad misericordiam) – an argument attempts to induce pity to sway opponents.[75]
    • Appeal to ridicule – an argument is made by presenting the opponent's argument in a way that makes it appear ridiculous.[76][77]
    • Appeal to spite – a specific type of appeal to emotion where an argument is made through exploiting people's bitterness or spite towards an opposing party.[78]
    • Wishful thinking – a specific type of appeal to emotion where a decision is made according to what might be pleasing to imagine, rather than according to evidence or reason.[79]
  • Appeal to nature – wherein judgment is based solely on whether the subject of judgment is 'natural' or 'unnatural'.[80] (Sometimes also called the "naturalistic fallacy", but is not to be confused with the other fallacies by that name)
  • Appeal to novelty (argumentum novitatis, argumentum ad antiquitatis) – where a proposal is claimed to be superior or better solely because it is new or modern.[81]
  • Appeal to poverty (argumentum ad Lazarum) – supporting a conclusion because the arguer is poor (or refuting because the arguer is wealthy). (Opposite of appeal to wealth.)[82]
  • Appeal to tradition (argumentum ad antiquitatem) – a conclusion supported solely because it has long been held to be true.[83]
  • Appeal to wealth (argumentum ad crumenam) – supporting a conclusion because the arguer is wealthy (or refuting because the arguer is poor).[84] (Sometimes taken together with the appeal to poverty as a general appeal to the arguer's financial situation.)
  • Argumentum ad baculum (appeal to the stick, appeal to force, appeal to threat) – an argument made through coercion or threats of force to support position.[85]
  • Argumentum ad populum (appeal to widespread belief, bandwagon argument, appeal to the majority, appeal to the people) – where a proposition is claimed to be true or good solely because many people believe it to be so.[86]
  • Association fallacy (guilt by association and honor by association) – arguing that because two things share (or are implied to share) some property, they are the same.[87]
  • Bulverism (psychogenetic fallacy) – inferring why an argument is being used, associating it to some psychological reason, then assuming it is invalid as a result. It is wrong to assume that if the origin of an idea comes from a biased mind, then the idea itself must also be a falsehood.[45]
  • Chronological snobbery – where a thesis is deemed incorrect because it was commonly held when something else, clearly false, was also commonly held.[88][89]
  • Fallacy of relative privation ("not as bad as") – dismissing an argument or complaint due to the existence of more important problems in the world, regardless of whether those problems bear relevance to the initial argument. For example, First World problem.
  • Genetic fallacy – where a conclusion is suggested based solely on something or someone's origin rather than its current meaning or context.[90]
  • Judgmental language – insulting or pejorative language to influence the recipient's judgment.
  • Moralistic fallacy (the inverse of naturalistic fallacy) – statements about what is on the basis of claims about what ought to be.
  • Motte-and-bailey fallacy: The arguer conflates two similar positions, one modest and easy to defend (the "motte") and one much more controversial (the "bailey"). The arguer advances the controversial position, but when challenged, they insist that they are only advancing the more modest position.[91]
  • Naturalistic fallacy (is–ought fallacy,[92] naturalistic fallacy[93]) – claims about what ought to be on the basis of statements about what is.
  • Pooh-pooh – dismissing an argument perceived unworthy of serious consideration.[94]
  • Straw man fallacy – an argument based on misrepresentation of an opponent's position.[95]
  • Texas sharpshooter fallacy – improperly asserting a cause to explain a cluster of data.[96]
  • Tu quoque ("you too", appeal to hypocrisy, I'm rubber and you're glue) – the argument states that a certain position is false or wrong or should be disregarded because its proponent fails to act consistently in accordance with that position.[97]
  • Two wrongs make a right – occurs when it is assumed that if one wrong is committed, an "equal but opposite" wrong will cancel it out.[98]
  • Vacuous truth – A claim that is technically true but meaningless, in the form of claiming that no A in B has C, when there are no A in B. For example, claiming that no mobile phones in the room are on when there are no mobile phones in the room at all.
  • Appeal to self-evident truth – A claim that a proposition is self-evidently true, so needs no further supporting evidence. If self-evidence is actually the basis for the claim, it is arbitrary and the opposite (a contradictory or contrary statement) is equally true. In many cases, however, the basis is really some kind of unstated and unexamined observation or assumption.

Conditional or questionable fallacies

  • Broken window fallacy – an argument that disregards lost opportunity costs (typically non-obvious, difficult to determine or otherwise hidden) associated with destroying property of others, or other ways of externalizing costs onto others. For example, an argument that states breaking a window generates income for a window fitter, but disregards the fact that the money spent on the new window cannot now be spent on new shoes.
  • Definist fallacy – involves the confusion between two notions by defining one in terms of the other.[99]
  • Naturalistic fallacy – attempts to prove a claim about ethics by appealing to a definition of the term "good" in terms of either one or more claims about natural properties (sometimes also taken to mean the appeal to nature) or God's will.[80]
  • Slippery slope (thin edge of the wedge, camel's nose) – asserting that a relatively small first step inevitably leads to a chain of related events culminating in some significant impact/event that should not happen, thus the first step should not happen. It is, in its essence, an appeal to probability fallacy. (e.g. if person x does y then z would [probably] occur, leading to q, leading to w, leading to e.)[100] This is also related to the reductio ad absurdum.

See also

References

Notes
  1. ^ a b Pirie, Madsen (2006). How to Win Every Argument: The Use and Abuse of Logic. A&C Black. p. 46. ISBN 978-0-8264-9006-3. Retrieved 10 September 2015.
  2. ^ "fallacy". Encyclopedia Brittanica. Encyclopedia Brittanica. Retrieved 13 June 2017.
  3. ^ Hornby, A.S. (2010). Oxford advanced learner's dictionary of current English (8th ed. ed.). Oxford [England]: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0194799003. sophist {{cite book}}: |access-date= requires |url= (help); |edition= has extra text (help)
  4. ^ Bunnin & Yu 2004, "formal fallacy".
  5. ^ Leon, Joseph (23 April 2011). "Appeal to Probability". Logical & Critical Thinking. Archived from the original on 27 September 2013. {{cite web}}: Unknown parameter |dead-url= ignored (|url-status= suggested) (help)
  6. ^ McDonald, Simon (2009). "Appeal to probability". Toolkit For Thinking. Archived from the original on 19 February 2015. {{cite web}}: Unknown parameter |dead-url= ignored (|url-status= suggested) (help)
  7. ^ Curtis, "Fallacy Fallacy".
  8. ^ "Base Rate Fallacy". Psychology Glossary. AlleyDog.com. Retrieved 2011-02-01.
  9. ^ Straker, David. "Conjunction Fallacy". ChangingMinds.org. Retrieved 2011-02-01.
  10. ^ Curtis, "The Masked Man Fallacy".
  11. ^ a b c Wilson 1999, p. 316.
  12. ^ a b c d e f Wilson 1999, p. 317.
  13. ^ Pirie 2006, pp. 133–36. sfn error: multiple targets (2×): CITEREFPirie2006 (help)
  14. ^ Wilson 1999, pp. 316–17.
  15. ^ Bunnin & Yu 2004, "informal fallacy".
  16. ^ "Johnson's Refutation of Berkeley: Kicking the Stone Again". JSTOR 2709600. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  17. ^ Damer 2009, p. 165.
  18. ^ "Toolkit for Thinking".
  19. ^ "Repetition". changingminds.org. Retrieved 2016-02-24.
  20. ^ "Ad nauseam – Toolkit For Thinking". toolkitforthinking.com. Retrieved 2016-02-24.
  21. ^ "Argument from silence – Toolkit For Thinking". toolkitforthinking.com. Retrieved 2016-02-24.
  22. ^ Bo Bennett. "Argument from Silence". logicallyfallacious.com. Retrieved 2016-02-24.
  23. ^ Damer 2009, p. 150.
  24. ^ "Your logical fallacy is begging the question". Thou shalt not commit logical fallacies. Retrieved 2016-02-24.
  25. ^ "Fallacy: Begging the Question". nizkor.org. Retrieved 2016-02-24.
  26. ^ Bo Bennett. "Begging the Question". logicallyfallacious.com. Retrieved 2016-02-24.
  27. ^ "Begging the Question". txstate.edu. Retrieved 2016-02-24.
  28. ^ Dowden 2010, "Line-Drawing".
  29. ^ Pirie 2006, p. 41. sfn error: multiple targets (2×): CITEREFPirie2006 (help)
  30. ^ Feinberg, Joel (2007). "Psychological Egoism". In Shafer-Landau, Russ (ed.). Ethical Theory: An Anthology. Blackwell Philosophy Anthologies. Wiley-Blackwell. p. 193. ISBN 978-1-4051-3320-3.
  31. ^ Carroll, Robert T. "divine fallacy (argument from incredulity)". The Skeptic's Dictionary. Retrieved 5 April 2013.
  32. ^ Damer 2009, p. 121.
  33. ^ Copi & Cohen 1990, p. 206.
  34. ^ Fischer 1970, p. 119.
  35. ^ Gula 2002, p. 70.
  36. ^ Pirie 2006, p. 31. sfn error: multiple targets (2×): CITEREFPirie2006 (help)
  37. ^ Pirie 2006, p. 53. sfn error: multiple targets (2×): CITEREFPirie2006 (help)
  38. ^ Gula 2002, p. 97.
  39. ^ "Fallacy – False Dilemma". Nizkor. The Nizkor Project. Retrieved 2011-02-01.
  40. ^ Damer 2009, p. 178.
  41. ^ Damer 2009, p. 186.
  42. ^ Fischer 1970, p. 209.
  43. ^ "The Reflex Arc Concept in Psychology", John Dewey, The Psychological Review, Vol. III. No. 4. July 1896. p. 367
  44. ^ Bunnin & Yu 2004, "Homunculus".
  45. ^ a b "A List Of Fallacious Arguments". Retrieved 6 October 2012.
  46. ^ Wimsatt, William K. and Monroe C. Beardsley. "The Intentional Fallacy." Sewanee Review, vol. 54 (1946): 468–88. Revised and republished in The Verbal Icon: Studies in the Meaning of Poetry, U of Kentucky P, 1954: 3–18.
  47. ^ Copi & Cohen 1990, p. 105.
  48. ^ Taleb, Nassim (2007). The Black Swan. Random House. p. 309. ISBN 1-4000-6351-5. Retrieved 2016-02-24.
  49. ^ "TheFreeDictionary". Naturalistic fallacyTemplate:Inconsistent citations{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: postscript (link).
  50. ^ John Searle, "How to Derive 'Ought' from 'Is'", The Philosophical Review, 73:1 (January 1964), 43–58
  51. ^ Alex Walter, "The Anti-naturalistic Fallacy: Evolutionary Moral Psychology and the Insistence of Brute Facts", Evolutionary Psychology, 4 (2006), 33–48
  52. ^ Damer 2009, p. 180.
  53. ^ Damer 2009, p. 208.
  54. ^ Semiotics Glossary R, Referential fallacy or illusion
  55. ^ Gula 2002, p. 135.
  56. ^ Pirie 2006, p. 5. sfn error: multiple targets (2×): CITEREFPirie2006 (help)
  57. ^ Flew 1984, "No-true-Scotsman move".
  58. ^ Hurley 2007, p. 155.
  59. ^ Damer 2009, p. 151.
  60. ^ Hurley 2007, p. 134.
  61. ^ Fischer 1970, p. 127.
  62. ^ Gary Curtis. "Logical Fallacy: Red Herring". fallacyfiles.org. Retrieved 2016-02-24.
  63. ^ joseph (April 17, 2011). "Red Herring Fallacy". Archived from the original on 2014-12-03.
  64. ^ "Logical Fallacies". logicalfallacies.info. Retrieved 2016-02-24.
  65. ^ Walton 2008, p. 187.
  66. ^ Bo Bennett. "Ad Hominem (Abusive)". logicallyfallacious.com. Retrieved 2016-02-24.
  67. ^ Clark & Clark 2005, pp. 13–16.
  68. ^ Walton 1997, p. 28.
  69. ^ Bo Bennett. "Appeal to Accomplishment". logicallyfallacious.com. Retrieved 2016-02-24.
  70. ^ Walton 2008, p. 27.
  71. ^ Damer 2009, p. 111.
  72. ^ Bo Bennett. "Appeal to Fear". logicallyfallacious.com.
  73. ^ "Appeal to Fear". changingminds.org.
  74. ^ Gula 2002, p. 12.
  75. ^ Walton 2008, p. 128.
  76. ^ "Appeal to Ridicule". changingminds.org.
  77. ^ Bo Bennett. "Appeal to Ridicule". logicallyfallacious.com.
  78. ^ "Appeal to Spite". changingminds.org.
  79. ^ Damer 2009, p. 146.
  80. ^ a b Gary Curtis. "Logical Fallacy: Appeal to Nature". fallacyfiles.org.
  81. ^ Pirie 2006, p. 116. sfn error: multiple targets (2×): CITEREFPirie2006 (help)
  82. ^ Pirie 2006, p. 104. sfn error: multiple targets (2×): CITEREFPirie2006 (help)
  83. ^ Pirie 2006, p. 14. sfn error: multiple targets (2×): CITEREFPirie2006 (help)
  84. ^ Pirie 2006, p. 39. sfn error: multiple targets (2×): CITEREFPirie2006 (help)
  85. ^ Damer 2009, p. 106.
  86. ^ "Appeal to Widespread Belief". Retrieved 6 October 2012.
  87. ^ Gary Curtis. "Logical Fallacy: Guilt by Association". fallacyfiles.org.
  88. ^ "Encyclopedia Barfieldiana". davidlavery.net.
  89. ^ "Archived copy". Archived from the original on February 5, 2012. Retrieved February 11, 2014. {{cite web}}: Unknown parameter |deadurl= ignored (|url-status= suggested) (help)CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link)
  90. ^ Damer 2009, p. 93.
  91. ^ Shackel, Nicholas (2005). "The Vacuity of Postmodernist Methodology". Metaphilosophy. 36 (3). For my purposes the desirable but only lightly defensible territory of the Motte and Bailey castle, that is to say, the Bailey, represents a philosophical doctrine or position with similar properties: desirable to its proponent but only lightly defensible. The Motte is the defensible but undesired position to which one retreats when hard pressed…
  92. ^ Dowden 2010, "Is-Ought".
  93. ^ Dowden 2010, "Naturalistic".
  94. ^ Munson, Ronald; Black, Andrew (2016). The Elements of Reasoning. Cengage Learning. p. 257. ISBN 1305886836.
  95. ^ Walton 2008, p. 22.
  96. ^ Curtis, "The Texas Sharpshooter Fallacy".
  97. ^ Pirie 2006, p. 164. sfn error: multiple targets (2×): CITEREFPirie2006 (help)
  98. ^ Johnson & Blair 1994, p. 122.
  99. ^ Frankena, W. K. (October 1939). "The Naturalistic Fallacy". Mind. 48 (192). Oxford University Press: 464–77. JSTOR 2250706.
  100. ^ Walton 2008, p. 315.
Works

Further reading

The following is a sample of books for further reading, selected for a combination of content, ease of access via the internet, and to provide an indication of published sources that interested readers may review. The titles of some books are self-explanatory. Good books on critical thinking commonly contain sections on fallacies, and some may be listed below.