Individualist anarchism: Difference between revisions
revert to rjii. too weird. learn to speak english or go to another language encyclopedia. |
|||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{Anarchism}} |
{{Anarchism}} |
||
'''Individualist anarchism''' is a philosophical tradition that opposes [[collectivism]] and has a particularly strong emphasis on the supremacy and autonomy of the [[individualism|individual]]. The tradition appears most often in the [[United States]], most notably in regard to its advocacy of private property. Individualist anarchism's roots includes Europeans such as [[William Godwin]], [[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]], |
'''Individualist anarchism''' is a philosophical tradition that opposes [[collectivism]] and has a particularly strong emphasis on the supremacy and autonomy of the [[individualism|individual]]. The tradition appears most often in the [[United States]], most notably in regard to its advocacy of private property. Individualist anarchism's roots includes Europeans such as [[William Godwin]], [[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]], and [[Max Stirner]] (who is also connected to the [[existentialism|existentialist]] philosophy), though the individualist anarchist tradition draws heavily on American independent thinkers, including [[Josiah Warren]], [[Benjamin Tucker]], [[Lysander Spooner]], [[Ezra Heywood]], [[Stephen Pearl Andrews]], and [[Henry David Thoreau]]. Noteworthy anarchist writer and poet [[John Henry Mackay]] is also considered an individualist anarchist. Contemporary individualist anarchists title include [[Robert Anton Wilson]], Joe Peacott, Daniel Burton and Keith Preston. Though some individualists have engaged in practical endeavors, individualist anarchism is mostly "philosophical anarchism" as its focus has mainly been on philosophical argumentation to effect change. Individualist anarchism is sometimes seen as a form of [[liberalism]], and hence, has been called "liberal anarchism" [http://www.weisbord.org/conquest8.htm]. |
||
Individualists anarchists have received influences from both Illustrated Liberalism and [[Utopian Socialism]]. |
|||
== Origins == |
== Origins == |
||
Line 17: | Line 16: | ||
After Dejacque and others split from Proudhon due to the latter's support of individual property and an exchange economy, the relationship between the individualists, who continued in relative alignment with the philosophy of Proudhon, and the anarcho-communists was characterised by various degrees of antagonism and harmony. For example, individualists like Tucker on the one hand translating and reprinted the works of collectivists like [[Mikhail Bakunin]], while on the other hand rejecting the economic aspects of collectivism and communism as incompatible with anarchist ideals. |
After Dejacque and others split from Proudhon due to the latter's support of individual property and an exchange economy, the relationship between the individualists, who continued in relative alignment with the philosophy of Proudhon, and the anarcho-communists was characterised by various degrees of antagonism and harmony. For example, individualists like Tucker on the one hand translating and reprinted the works of collectivists like [[Mikhail Bakunin]], while on the other hand rejecting the economic aspects of collectivism and communism as incompatible with anarchist ideals. |
||
While individualist anarchism is often seen as including William Godwin and Max Stirner, it is most often associated with the ''market anarchism'' found in the native American tradition, which advocates individual ownership of the produce of labor and a [[market economy]] where this property may be bought and sold. However, this form of individualist anarchism is not exclusive to the Americans. It is also found in the philosophy of other radical individalists, such as those in England and France though almost all were influenced by the early American individualists. Individualist anarchism of this type is in contrast to "social anarchism" (e.g. communist anarchism) which holds that productive property should be in the control of the society at large in various forms of worker collectives and that the produce of labor should be collectivized |
While individualist anarchism is often seen as including William Godwin and Max Stirner, it is most often associated with the ''market anarchism'' found in the native American tradition, which advocates individual ownership of the produce of labor and a [[market economy]] where this property may be bought and sold. However, this form of individualist anarchism is not exclusive to the Americans. It is also found in the philosophy of other radical individalists, such as those in England and France though almost all were influenced by the early American individualists. Individualist anarchism of this type is in contrast to "social anarchism" (e.g. communist anarchism) which holds that productive property should be in the control of the society at large in various forms of worker collectives and that the produce of labor should be collectivized. |
||
== The American tradition == |
== The American tradition == |
||
Line 28: | Line 27: | ||
The individualists' economic theory (''[[mutualism (economic theory)|mutualism]]'') is based on the [[labor theory of value]]. Accepting that the value of a good is the amount of labor undertaking in producing it, they conclude that it is unethical to charge a higher price for a commodity than the cost of producing or acquiring and bringing it to market (''[[Cost the limit of price]]''). To ensure that labor receives its "full produce" they advocate that a commodity should be purchased with an amount of labor that is equivalent to the amount of labor undertaken in producing that commodity. As a result, equal amounts of labor would receive equal pay; those that did not labor would not be paid. In the area of employment, this would obviate the possibility of an employer profiting from the labor of an employee, which they opposed as being exploitative, since the employee must receive the "full produce" of his labor. With the exception of Warren, this led to their position that private ownership of land should be supported only if the possessor of that land is using it, otherwise, the possessor would be able to charge rent to others without laboring to produce anything (Warren does not oppose ownership of land but does advocate that it be sold at cost). Profiting from lending money for interest is generally seen as usurious as an income is seen as being derived without labor. To the individualists, profit from interest, profit from wages, and rental of land is only made possible by government-backed "monopoly" and "privilege" that restricts competition in the marketplace and concentrates wealth in the hands of a few. |
The individualists' economic theory (''[[mutualism (economic theory)|mutualism]]'') is based on the [[labor theory of value]]. Accepting that the value of a good is the amount of labor undertaking in producing it, they conclude that it is unethical to charge a higher price for a commodity than the cost of producing or acquiring and bringing it to market (''[[Cost the limit of price]]''). To ensure that labor receives its "full produce" they advocate that a commodity should be purchased with an amount of labor that is equivalent to the amount of labor undertaken in producing that commodity. As a result, equal amounts of labor would receive equal pay; those that did not labor would not be paid. In the area of employment, this would obviate the possibility of an employer profiting from the labor of an employee, which they opposed as being exploitative, since the employee must receive the "full produce" of his labor. With the exception of Warren, this led to their position that private ownership of land should be supported only if the possessor of that land is using it, otherwise, the possessor would be able to charge rent to others without laboring to produce anything (Warren does not oppose ownership of land but does advocate that it be sold at cost). Profiting from lending money for interest is generally seen as usurious as an income is seen as being derived without labor. To the individualists, profit from interest, profit from wages, and rental of land is only made possible by government-backed "monopoly" and "privilege" that restricts competition in the marketplace and concentrates wealth in the hands of a few. |
||
=== |
=== Anarcho-capitalism === |
||
{{main|anarcho-capitalism}} |
{{main|anarcho-capitalism}} |
||
⚫ | Unlike the early American individualist anarchists, anarcho-capitalists do not regard value as being matter of labor exerted but a matter of individual subjective judgements (see [[subjective theory of value]]) and therefore have no opposition to profit. While anarcho-capitalism is an individualist philosophy, there is much controversy in the claim that anarcho-capitalism is a form of individualist ''anarchism''. The relationship between [[individualist anarchism and anarcho-capitalism]] is explored further in that article. |
||
Anarcho-capitalism is not a form of anarchism in the strict sense of the word. |
|||
⚫ | Unlike the early American |
||
==See also== |
==See also== |
Revision as of 01:02, 8 December 2005
Individualist anarchism is a philosophical tradition that opposes collectivism and has a particularly strong emphasis on the supremacy and autonomy of the individual. The tradition appears most often in the United States, most notably in regard to its advocacy of private property. Individualist anarchism's roots includes Europeans such as William Godwin, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, and Max Stirner (who is also connected to the existentialist philosophy), though the individualist anarchist tradition draws heavily on American independent thinkers, including Josiah Warren, Benjamin Tucker, Lysander Spooner, Ezra Heywood, Stephen Pearl Andrews, and Henry David Thoreau. Noteworthy anarchist writer and poet John Henry Mackay is also considered an individualist anarchist. Contemporary individualist anarchists title include Robert Anton Wilson, Joe Peacott, Daniel Burton and Keith Preston. Though some individualists have engaged in practical endeavors, individualist anarchism is mostly "philosophical anarchism" as its focus has mainly been on philosophical argumentation to effect change. Individualist anarchism is sometimes seen as a form of liberalism, and hence, has been called "liberal anarchism" [1].
Origins
There is significant variance between the philosophies of different individualist anarchists. Almost all, following Proudhon, support individual ownership of the particular form of private property he refered to as "possession". Stirner supports private property but rejects the notion of a right to property. Godwin is an altruist, Stirner an egoist. Warren espouses natural law as a basis for individual liberty, while Tuckers premises it upon egoism. Tucker opposes intellectual property while Spooner advocates it. However, what these philosophers all have in common is a rejection of both capitalist economics and collectivist notions of society and a pronounced focus on individuality.
William Godwin, of England, wrote essays advocating a society without government that are considered some of the first, if not the first, anarchist treatises. As such, some consider the liberal British writer to be the "father of philosophical anarchism." There is a lack of consensus as to whether Godwin was an individualist or a communist. He is regarded by some as one of the first individualist anarchists, although his philosophy has some communist-like characteristics. He advocates an extreme form of individualism, proposing that all sorts of cooperation in labor should be eliminated; he says: "everything understood by the term co-operation is in some sense an evil." Godwin's individualism is to such a radical degree that he even opposes individuals performing together in orchestras. The only apparent exception to this opposition to cooperation is the spontaneous assocation that may arise when a society is threatened by violent force. One reason he opposes cooperation is he believes it to interfere with an individual's ability to be benevolent for the greater good. Godwin opposes the existence of government and expressly opposes democracy, fearing oppression of the individual by the majority (though he believes democracy to be preferable to dictatorship). Godwin supports individual ownership of property, defining it as as "the empire to which every man is entitled over the produce of his own industry." However, he does advocate that individuals give to each other their surplus property on the occasion that others have a need for it, without involving trade (see gift economy). This was to be based on utilitarian principles; he says: "Every man has a right to that, the exclusive possession of which being awarded to him, a greater sum of benefit or pleasure will result than could have arisen from its being otherwise appropriated." However, benevolence was not to be enforced but a matter of free individual "private judgement." He does not advocate a community of goods or assert collective ownership as is embraced in communism, but his belief that individuals ought to share with those in need was influential on anarchist communism later. Some consider Godwin both an individualist and a communist rather than than a strict individualist for this reason. [2] Some, such as Murray Rothbard, do not regard Godwin as being in the individualist camp at all [3] (Some restrict "individualist anarchism" to the market anarchists). Others consider him an individualist anarchist without reservation. [4] Some writers see a conflict between Godwin's advocacy of "private judgement" and utilitarianism, as he says that ethics requires that individuals give their surplus property to each other resulting in an egalitarian society, but, at the same time, he insists that all things be left to individual choice. [5] Communist-anarchist Peter Kropotkin says in the 1911 Encyclopedia Britannica that Godwin "entirely rewrote later on his chapter on property and mitigated his communist views in the second edition of Political Justice." Godwin's basis in utilitarianism and ethical altruism contrasts with later individualists, such as Max Stirner and Benjamin Tucker, who ground their philosophy on egoism or self-interest (though not all are egoists). Also, Godwin's aversion to cooperation and a market economy is not typical among the individualists.
While individualists typically assert property as a right, Germany's Max Stirner that a "right" to property is an illusion, or "ghost"; property is only a matter of control --it is not based in any moral right but solely in the right of might: "Whoever knows how to take, to defend, the thing, to him belongs property.". Stirner considers the world and everything in it, including other persons, available to one's taking or use without moral constraint --that rights do not exist in regard to objects at all. He sees no rationality in taking the interests of others into account unless doing so furthers one's self-interest, which he believes is the only legitimate reason for acting. His embrace of egoism is in stark contrast to Godwin's altruism. He denies society as being an actual entity, calling society a "spook" and that "the individuals are its reality" (The Ego and Its Own). Whether individualist anarchism is properly justified by self-interest (egoism) or natural law has been a subject of debate among the individualists. For example, Lysander Spooner holds that there are natural property rights, but egoists such as Benjamin Tucker agree with Stirner that there are no natural property rights but hold that property can come only about by contract between individuals.
France's Pierre-Joseph Proudhon was the first philosopher to label himself an "anarchist." He was particularly influential among the American individualists, mainly by way of Benjamin Tucker who had translated and studied his works. Proudhon opposes government privilege that protects banking and land interests, and any form of coercion that led to the accumulation or acquisition of property, which he believes hampers competition and keeps wealth in the hands of the few. Proudhon favors a right of individuals to retain the product of their labor as their own property, but believed that any property beyond that which an individual produced and could possess was illegitimate. Thus, he saw private property as both essential to liberty and a road to tyranny, the former when it resulted from labor and the later when it resulted from extortion (interest, tax, etc). He says: "Where shall we find a power capable of counter-balancing the... State? There is none other than property... The absolute right of the State is in conflict with the absolute right of the property owner. Property is the greatest revolutionary force which exists." Proudhon maintains that those who labor should retain the entirety of what they produce, and that monopolies on credit and land are the forces that prohibiting such. He advocated an economic system that included private property as possession and exchange market but without profit, which he called mutualism. It is Proudhon's philosophy that was explictly amended by Joseph Dejacque in the inception of anarchist-communism, with the latter asserting directly to Proudhon in a letter that "it is not the product of his or her labor that the worker has a right to, but to the satisfaction of his or her needs, whatever may be their nature." Proudhon said that "communism...is the very denial of society in its foundation..." (Philosophy of Poverty) and was famous for declaring that "property is theft" in referance to the capitalist practices of his time.
After Dejacque and others split from Proudhon due to the latter's support of individual property and an exchange economy, the relationship between the individualists, who continued in relative alignment with the philosophy of Proudhon, and the anarcho-communists was characterised by various degrees of antagonism and harmony. For example, individualists like Tucker on the one hand translating and reprinted the works of collectivists like Mikhail Bakunin, while on the other hand rejecting the economic aspects of collectivism and communism as incompatible with anarchist ideals.
While individualist anarchism is often seen as including William Godwin and Max Stirner, it is most often associated with the market anarchism found in the native American tradition, which advocates individual ownership of the produce of labor and a market economy where this property may be bought and sold. However, this form of individualist anarchism is not exclusive to the Americans. It is also found in the philosophy of other radical individalists, such as those in England and France though almost all were influenced by the early American individualists. Individualist anarchism of this type is in contrast to "social anarchism" (e.g. communist anarchism) which holds that productive property should be in the control of the society at large in various forms of worker collectives and that the produce of labor should be collectivized.
The American tradition
Individualist anarchism in American is noted for its strong advocacy of the type of private property championed by Proudhon, and a competitive free market economy. Josiah Warren, who is the first individualist anarchist in the American tradition, had participated in a failed collectivist experiment headed by Robert Owen called "New Harmony" and came to the conclusion that such a system is inferior to one where individualism and private property is respected. In Practical Details, where he discusses his conclusions in regard to the experiment. In a much cited quote from that text, he makes a vehement assertion of individual negative liberty: "Society must be so converted as to preserve the SOVEREIGNTY OF EVERY INDIVIDUAL inviolate. That it must avoid all combinations and connections of persons and interests, and all other arrangements which will not leave every individual at all times at liberty to dispose of his or her person, and time, and property in any manner in which his or her feelings or judgment may dictate WITHOUT INVOLVING THE PERSONS OR INTERESTS OF OTHERS" (Warren's capitalization). Though Warren and Proudhon did not associate with each other, working on separate continents they both came to like conclusions in regard to labor theory of value and property. However, according to Benjamin Tucker, that profiting by violating the labor theory of value is exploitative "was Proudhon's position before it was Marx's, and Josiah Warren's before it was Proudhon's" (Liberty or Authority).
While Warren based his philosophy on natural law, Benjamin Tucker eventually switched his allegiance to egoism as a result of his reading of Max Stirner. Many individualists followed in his footsteps in this respect. Tucker maintained that there were two rights, "the right of might" and "the right of contract" and that moral rights do not exist until they are devised by contract initiated out of the self-interest of the contracting parties.
The individualists' economic theory (mutualism) is based on the labor theory of value. Accepting that the value of a good is the amount of labor undertaking in producing it, they conclude that it is unethical to charge a higher price for a commodity than the cost of producing or acquiring and bringing it to market (Cost the limit of price). To ensure that labor receives its "full produce" they advocate that a commodity should be purchased with an amount of labor that is equivalent to the amount of labor undertaken in producing that commodity. As a result, equal amounts of labor would receive equal pay; those that did not labor would not be paid. In the area of employment, this would obviate the possibility of an employer profiting from the labor of an employee, which they opposed as being exploitative, since the employee must receive the "full produce" of his labor. With the exception of Warren, this led to their position that private ownership of land should be supported only if the possessor of that land is using it, otherwise, the possessor would be able to charge rent to others without laboring to produce anything (Warren does not oppose ownership of land but does advocate that it be sold at cost). Profiting from lending money for interest is generally seen as usurious as an income is seen as being derived without labor. To the individualists, profit from interest, profit from wages, and rental of land is only made possible by government-backed "monopoly" and "privilege" that restricts competition in the marketplace and concentrates wealth in the hands of a few.
Anarcho-capitalism
Unlike the early American individualist anarchists, anarcho-capitalists do not regard value as being matter of labor exerted but a matter of individual subjective judgements (see subjective theory of value) and therefore have no opposition to profit. While anarcho-capitalism is an individualist philosophy, there is much controversy in the claim that anarcho-capitalism is a form of individualist anarchism. The relationship between individualist anarchism and anarcho-capitalism is explored further in that article.
See also
External links
- Individualist Anarchist Resources
- A Vindication of Natural Society: or, a View of the Miseries and Evils arising to Mankind from every Species of Artifical Society by Edmund Burke - some regard this liberal essay to be the first to advocate anarchy
- Enquiry Concerning Political Justice by William Godwin
- The Ego and his Own by Max Stirner, translated by Christian individualist anarchist Steven T. Byington
- Manifesto by Josiah Warren
- Equitable Commerce by Josiah Warren
- State Socialism and Anarchism: How far they agree, and wherein they differ. by Benjamin Tucker (1886)
- Anarchist Individualism as Life and Activity by E. Armand (1907)
- Anarchist FAQ: Section on Individualist Anarchism (Mirrored at: [6] and [7])
- Anarchist FAQ: Are individualist anarchists anti-capitalist? (Mirrored at: [8] and [9])
- Anarchist FAQ: Why do social anarchists reject individualist anarchism? (Mirrored at: [10] and [11])
- I. Liberal-Anarchism VIII. Libertarianism from The Conquest of Power, by Albert Weisbord[12] discusses individualism of Godwin and Stirner
- American Liberal-Anarchism from The Conquest of Power, by Albert Weisbord[13]
- American Anarchism by Wendy McElroy 19th Century Individualist Anarchism in America
- Bad Press Contemporary Individualist Anarchist Publications
- Individualist-Anarchist.Net
- The Schism Between Individualist and Communist Anarchism
- Proudhon and Anarchism by Larry Gambone
- Individualist Anarchist Society at UC Berkeley