Jump to content

Objectivism: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Karbinski (talk | contribs)
Karbinski (talk | contribs)
m Politics: individual rights and capitalism: moved quote box up the page
Line 97: Line 97:
Objectivism's politics derives immediately from its ethics, which provides the principles for "how man should treat other men." These principles of ethics provide the foundation for "the principles of a proper social system."<ref>{{harvnb|Rand|1982|p=4}}</ref> Objectivists hold that ''laissez-faire'' capitalism is "the only ''moral'' social system."<ref>{{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|p=380}}</ref>
Objectivism's politics derives immediately from its ethics, which provides the principles for "how man should treat other men." These principles of ethics provide the foundation for "the principles of a proper social system."<ref>{{harvnb|Rand|1982|p=4}}</ref> Objectivists hold that ''laissez-faire'' capitalism is "the only ''moral'' social system."<ref>{{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|p=380}}</ref>


Rand's defense of individual liberty integrates elements from her entire philosophy.<ref>{{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|p=354}}; {{harvnb|Sciabarra|1995|p=274}}</ref> Since reason is the means of human knowledge, it is therefore each person's most fundamental means of survival and is necessary to the achievement of values.<ref>{{cite book |title=Objectivism in One Lesson: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Ayn Rand |last=Bernstein |first=Andrew |location=Lanham, Maryland |publisher=Hamilton Books |year=2009 |isbn=0-7618-4359-0 |pages=25–31}}</ref> The use or threat of force neutralizes the practical effect of an individual's reason, whether the force originates from the state or from a criminal. According to Rand, "man's mind will not function at the point of a gun."<ref>{{harvnb|Rand|1967|p=141}}</ref> Therefore, the only type of organized human behavior consistent with the operation of reason is that of voluntary cooperation. Persuasion is the method of reason. By its nature, the overtly irrational cannot rely on the use of persuasion and must ultimately resort to force to prevail.<ref>{{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|pp=310–313}}</ref> Thus, Rand saw reason and freedom as correlates, just as she saw mysticism and force as corollaries.<ref>{{harvnb|Rand|1982|p=66}}</ref> Based on this understanding of the role of reason, Objectivists hold that the initiation of physical force against the will of another is immoral,<ref>{{harvnb|Rand|1964|p=36}}; {{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|p=310}}; {{harvnb|Smith|1997|pp=143–147}}</ref> as are indirect initiations of force through threats,<ref>{{harvnb|Smith|1997|pp=150–155}}</ref> fraud,<ref>{{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|pp=319}}</ref> or breach of contract.<ref>{{harvnb|Rand|1964|pp=129–130}}</ref> The use of defensive or retaliatory force, on the other hand, is appropriate.<ref>{{harvnb|Rand|1964|p=126}}; {{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|p=320}}</ref>
{{Quote box
{{Quote box
| quote = In a fully free society, taxation—or, to be exact, payment for governmental services—would be voluntary. Since the proper services of a government—the police, the armed forces, the law courts—are demonstrably needed by individual citizens and affect their interests directly, the citizens would (and should) be willing to pay for such services, as they pay for insurance.
| quote = In a fully free society, taxation—or, to be exact, payment for governmental services—would be voluntary. Since the proper services of a government—the police, the armed forces, the law courts—are demonstrably needed by individual citizens and affect their interests directly, the citizens would (and should) be willing to pay for such services, as they pay for insurance.
Line 104: Line 103:
| align = right
| align = right
}}
}}

Rand's defense of individual liberty integrates elements from her entire philosophy.<ref>{{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|p=354}}; {{harvnb|Sciabarra|1995|p=274}}</ref> Since reason is the means of human knowledge, it is therefore each person's most fundamental means of survival and is necessary to the achievement of values.<ref>{{cite book |title=Objectivism in One Lesson: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Ayn Rand |last=Bernstein |first=Andrew |location=Lanham, Maryland |publisher=Hamilton Books |year=2009 |isbn=0-7618-4359-0 |pages=25–31}}</ref> The use or threat of force neutralizes the practical effect of an individual's reason, whether the force originates from the state or from a criminal. According to Rand, "man's mind will not function at the point of a gun."<ref>{{harvnb|Rand|1967|p=141}}</ref> Therefore, the only type of organized human behavior consistent with the operation of reason is that of voluntary cooperation. Persuasion is the method of reason. By its nature, the overtly irrational cannot rely on the use of persuasion and must ultimately resort to force to prevail.<ref>{{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|pp=310–313}}</ref> Thus, Rand saw reason and freedom as correlates, just as she saw mysticism and force as corollaries.<ref>{{harvnb|Rand|1982|p=66}}</ref> Based on this understanding of the role of reason, Objectivists hold that the initiation of physical force against the will of another is immoral,<ref>{{harvnb|Rand|1964|p=36}}; {{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|p=310}}; {{harvnb|Smith|1997|pp=143–147}}</ref> as are indirect initiations of force through threats,<ref>{{harvnb|Smith|1997|pp=150–155}}</ref> fraud,<ref>{{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|pp=319}}</ref> or breach of contract.<ref>{{harvnb|Rand|1964|pp=129–130}}</ref> The use of defensive or retaliatory force, on the other hand, is appropriate.<ref>{{harvnb|Rand|1964|p=126}}; {{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|p=320}}</ref>

Objectivism holds that because the opportunity to use reason without the initiation of force is necessary to achieve moral values, each individual has an inalienable moral [[natural and legal rights|right]] to act as his own judgment directs and to keep the product of his effort. The fundamental right is the right to life, with other rights following from it, including rights to "liberty, property, and the pursuit of happiness."<ref>{{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|pp=351–352}}. The Objectivist understanding of rights is explored at length in {{harvnb|Smith|1997}}.</ref> "A 'right' is a moral principle defining and sanctioning a man's freedom of action in a social context."<ref>{{harvnb|Rand|1964|p=110}}</ref> These rights are specifically understood to be rights to action, not to specific results or objects, and the obligations created by rights are negative in nature: each individual must refrain from violating the rights of others.<ref>{{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|p=355}}</ref> Objectivists reject alternative notions of rights, such as [[positive rights]]<ref>{{harvnb|Smith|1997|pp=165–182}}; ''cf''. {{cite book |title=Then Athena Said: Unilateral Transfers and the Transformation of Objectivist Ethics |last=Touchstone |first=Kathleen |location=Lanham, Maryland |publisher=University Press of America |year=2006 |isbn=0-7618-3519-9 |page=108}}</ref> or rights belonging to anything other than an individual human being, such as collective rights or [[animal rights]].<ref>{{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|pp=356–358}}; {{harvnb|Rand|1964|pp=120}}</ref>
Objectivism holds that because the opportunity to use reason without the initiation of force is necessary to achieve moral values, each individual has an inalienable moral [[natural and legal rights|right]] to act as his own judgment directs and to keep the product of his effort. The fundamental right is the right to life, with other rights following from it, including rights to "liberty, property, and the pursuit of happiness."<ref>{{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|pp=351–352}}. The Objectivist understanding of rights is explored at length in {{harvnb|Smith|1997}}.</ref> "A 'right' is a moral principle defining and sanctioning a man's freedom of action in a social context."<ref>{{harvnb|Rand|1964|p=110}}</ref> These rights are specifically understood to be rights to action, not to specific results or objects, and the obligations created by rights are negative in nature: each individual must refrain from violating the rights of others.<ref>{{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|p=355}}</ref> Objectivists reject alternative notions of rights, such as [[positive rights]]<ref>{{harvnb|Smith|1997|pp=165–182}}; ''cf''. {{cite book |title=Then Athena Said: Unilateral Transfers and the Transformation of Objectivist Ethics |last=Touchstone |first=Kathleen |location=Lanham, Maryland |publisher=University Press of America |year=2006 |isbn=0-7618-3519-9 |page=108}}</ref> or rights belonging to anything other than an individual human being, such as collective rights or [[animal rights]].<ref>{{harvnb|Peikoff|1991|pp=356–358}}; {{harvnb|Rand|1964|pp=120}}</ref>



Revision as of 13:50, 8 July 2011

Objectivism is a philosophy defined by the Russian-American philosopher and novelist Ayn Rand (1905–1982). Objectivism holds that reality exists independent of consciousness, that human beings have direct contact with reality through sense perception, that one can attain objective knowledge from perception through the process of concept formation and inductive and deductive logic, that the proper moral purpose of one's life is the pursuit of one's own happiness or rational self-interest, that the only social system consistent with this morality is full respect for individual rights, embodied in laissez faire capitalism, and that the role of art in human life is to transform man's widest metaphysical ideas, by selective reproduction of reality, into a physical form—a work of art—that he can comprehend and to which he can respond emotionally.

Rand originally expressed her philosophical ideas in her novels The Fountainhead and Atlas Shrugged, and other works. She further elaborated on them in her periodicals The Objectivist Newsletter, The Objectivist, and The Ayn Rand Letter, and in non-fiction books such as Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology and The Virtue of Selfishness.[1]

The name "Objectivism" derives from the idea that human knowledge and values are objective: they are not created by the thoughts one has, but are determined by the nature of reality, to be discovered by one's mind.[2] Rand stated that she chose the name because her preferred term for a philosophy based on the primacy of existence—"existentialism"—had already been taken.[3]

Philosophy

Ayn Rand characterized Objectivism as "a philosophy for living on earth," grounded in reality, and aimed at defining man's nature and the nature of the world in which he lives.[1]

My philosophy, in essence, is the concept of man as a heroic being, with his own happiness as the moral purpose of his life, with productive achievement as his noblest activity, and reason as his only absolute.

— Ayn Rand, Atlas Shrugged[4]

Metaphysics: objective reality

Rand's philosophy begins with three axioms: existence, identity, and consciousness.[5] Rand defined an axiom as "a statement that identifies the base of knowledge and of any further statement pertaining to that knowledge, a statement necessarily contained in all others whether any particular speaker chooses to identify it or not. An axiom is a proposition that defeats its opponents by the fact that they have to accept it and use it in the process of any attempt to deny it."[6] As Leonard Peikoff noted, Rand's argument for axioms "is not a proof that the axioms of existence, consciousness, and identity are true. It is proof that they are axioms, that they are at the base of knowledge and thus inescapable."[7]

Rand held that existence is the perceptually self-evident fact at the base of all other knowledge, i.e., that "existence exists." She further held that to be is to be something, that "existence is identity." That is, to be is to be "an entity of a specific nature made of specific attributes." That which has no nature or attributes does not and cannot exist. The axiom of existence is grasped in differentiating something from nothing, while the law of identity is grasped in differentiating one thing from another, i.e., one's first awareness of the law of non-contradiction, another crucial base for the rest of knowledge. As Rand wrote, "A leaf ... cannot be all red and green at the same time, it cannot freeze and burn at the same time... A is A."[8]

Rand argues that consciousness, "the faculty of perceiving that which exists," is an inherently relational phenomenon. As she puts it, "to be conscious is to be conscious of something," that is consciousness itself cannot be distinguished or grasped except in relation to an independent reality.[9] "It cannot be aware only of itself—there is no 'itself' until it is aware of something."[10] Thus, Objectivism holds that the mind does not create reality, but rather, it is a means of discovering reality.[11] Expressed differently, existence has "primacy" over consciousness which must conform to it. Any other approach Rand termed "the primacy of consciousness," including any variant of metaphysical subjectivism or theism.[12]

Objectivist philosophy derives its explanations of action and causation from the axiom of identity, calling causation "the law of identity applied to action."[13] According to Rand, it is entities that act, and every action is the action of an entity. The way entities act is caused by the specific nature (or "identity") of those entities; if they were different they would act differently. As with the other axioms, an implicit understanding of causation is derived from one's primary observations of causal connections among entities even before it is verbally identified, and serves as the basis of further knowledge.[14]

Objectivism rejects belief in "every 'spiritual' dimension, force, Form, Idea, entity, power, or whatnot alleged to transcend existence."[15]

Epistemology: reason

Objectivist epistemology begins with the principle that "Consciousness is Identification". This is understood to be a direct consequence of the metaphysical principle that "Existence is Identity."[16] Rand defined "reason" as "the faculty that identifies and integrates the material provided by man's senses."[17]

Objectivist epistemology maintains that all knowledge is ultimately based on perception. "Percepts, not sensations, are the given, the self-evident."[18] Rand considered the validity of the senses to be axiomatic, and claimed that purported arguments to the contrary all commit the fallacy of the "stolen concept"[19] by presupposing the validity of concepts that, in turn, presuppose the validity of the senses.[20] She held that perception, being physiologically determined, is incapable of error. So optical illusions, for example, are errors in the conceptual identification of what is seen, not errors in sight itself.[21]

The Objectivist theory of perception distinguishes between the form and object. The form in which an organism perceives is determined by the physiology of its sensory systems. Whatever form the organism perceives it in, what it perceives—the object of perception—is reality.[22] Rand consequently rejected the Kantian dichotomy between "things as we perceive them" and "things as they are in themselves." The epistemologies of representationalism and indirect realism that accept a "veil of perception", as put forward by Descartes or John Locke, are thus inconsistent with Objectivism. Rand rejected epistemological skepticism as the skeptics claim knowledge "undistorted" by the form or the means of perception is impossible.[21]

According to Rand, attaining knowledge beyond what is given in perception requires both volition (or the exercise of free will) and adherence to a specific method of validation through observation, concept-formation, and the application of inductive and deductive logic. A belief in, say, dragons, however sincere, does not oblige reality to contain any dragons. For anything that cannot be directly observed, a process of "proof" identifying the basis in reality of the claimed item of knowledge is necessary to establish its truth.[23]

Objectivism rejects both faith and "feeling" as sources of knowledge. Rand acknowledged the importance of emotion for human beings, but she maintained that emotions are a consequence of the conscious or subconscious ideas that a person already accepts, not a means of achieving awareness of reality. "Emotions are not tools of cognition."[24]

The fundamental concept of method, the one on which all the others depend, is logic. The distinguishing characteristic of logic (the art of non-contradictory identification) indicates the nature of the actions (actions of consciousness required to achieve a correct identification) and their goal (knowledge)—while omitting the length, complexity or specific steps of the process of logical inference, as well as the nature of the particular cognitive problem involved in any given instance of using logic.

 Ayn Rand, Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology [25]

Rand rejected all forms of faith or mysticism, terms that she used synonymously. She defined faith as "the acceptance of allegations without evidence or proof, either apart from or against the evidence of one's senses and reason... Mysticism is the claim to some non-sensory, non-rational, non-definable, non-identifiable means of knowledge, such as 'instinct,' 'intuition,' 'revelation,' or any form of 'just knowing.'"[26] Reliance on revelation is like reliance on a Ouija board; it bypasses the need to show how it connects its results to reality. Faith, for Rand, is not a "short-cut" to knowledge, but a "short-circuit" destroying it.[27]

According to Rand, consciousness possesses a specific, finite identity, just like everything else that exists; therefore, it must operate by a specific method of validation. An item of knowledge cannot be "disqualified" by being arrived at by a specific process in a particular form. Thus, for Rand, the fact that consciousness must itself possess identity implies the rejection of both universal skepticism based on the "limits" of consciousness and any claim to revelation, emotion or faith based belief.

The attack on man's consciousness and particularly on his conceptual faculty has rested on the unchallenged premise that any knowledge acquired by a process of consciousness is necessarily subjective and cannot correspond to the facts of reality, since it is "processed knowledge... . [But] All knowledge is processed knowledge—whether on the sensory, perceptual or conceptual level. An "unprocessed" knowledge would be a knowledge acquired without means of cognition.[28]

Immanuel Kant's contrary arguments, according to Rand, amount to saying: "man is limited to a consciousness of a specific nature, which perceives by specific means and no others; therefore, his consciousness is not valid; man is blind because he has eyes—deaf because he has ears—deluded because he has a mind—and the things he perceives do not exist because he perceives them."[29]

The aspect of epistemology given the most elaboration by Rand is the theory of concept-formation, which she presented in Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology. She argued that concepts are formed by a process of measurement omission. Peikoff described her view as follows:

To form a concept, one mentally isolates a group of concretes (of distinct perceptual units), on the basis of observed similarities which distinguish them from all other known concretes (similarity is 'the relationship between two or more existents which possess the same characteristic(s), but in different measure or degree'); then, by a process of omitting the particular measurements of these concretes, one integrates them into a single new mental unit: the concept, which subsumes all concretes of this kind (a potentially unlimited number). The integration is completed and retained by the selection of a perceptual symbol (a word) to designate it. 'A concept is a mental integration of two or more units possessing the same distinguishing characteristic(s), with their particular measurements omitted.'"[30]

According to Rand, "[T]he term 'measurements omitted' does not mean, in this context, that measurements are regarded as non-existent; it means that measurements exist, but are not specified. That measurements must exist is an essential part of the process. The principle is: the relevant measurements must exist in some quantity, but may exist in any quantity."[31]

Rand argued that concepts are hierarchically organized. Concepts such as 'dog,' which bring together "concretes" available in perception, can be differentiated (into the concepts of 'dachshund,' 'poodle,' etc.) or integrated (along with 'cat,' etc., into the concept of 'animal'). Abstract concepts such as 'animal' can be further integrated, via "abstraction from abstractions", into such concepts as 'living thing.' Concepts are formed in the context of knowledge available. A young child differentiates dogs from cats and chickens, but need not explicitly differentiate them from deep-sea tube worms, or from other types of animals not yet known to him, to form a concept 'dog.'[32]

Because of its view of concepts as "open-ended" classifications that go well beyond the characteristics included in their past or current definitions, Objectivist epistemology rejects the analytic-synthetic distinction as a false dichotomy[33] and denies the possibility of a priori knowledge.[34]

Objectivist epistemology acknowledges the facts that human beings have limited knowledge, are vulnerable to error, and do not instantly understand all of the implications of their knowledge.[35] According to Peikoff, one can be certain of a proposition if all of the available evidence supports it, i.e., it can be logically integrated with the rest of one's knowledge; one is then certain within the context of the evidence.[36]

Objectivist epistemology attributes a special status to propositions put forward without any supporting evidence whatever, calling them "arbitrary assertions," which can be legitimately treated as though "nothing has been said."[37]

Some commentators have asserted that the Objectivist epistemology is incomplete.[38] According to psychology professor Robert L. Campbell, the notion of proof for propositions remains sketchy.[39] Campbell also says the relationship between Objectivist epistemology and cognitive science remains unclear because Rand, Peikoff, and Kelley have all made extensive claims about human cognition and its development which appear to belong to psychology, yet Rand asserted that philosophy is logically prior to psychology and in no way dependent on it.[40][41]

Ethics: rational self-interest

Rand defines morality as "a code of values to guide man's choices and actions—the choices and actions that determine the purpose and the course of his life."[42] Rand maintained that the first question isn't what should the code of values be, the first question is "Does man need values at all—and why?"

According to Rand, "it is only the concept of 'Life' that makes the concept of 'Value' possible," and, "the fact that a living entity is, determines what it ought to do.".[43] Rand writes: "there is only one fundamental alternative in the universe: existence or non-existence—and it pertains to a single class of entities: to living organisms. The existence of inanimate matter is unconditional, the existence of life is not: it depends on a specific course of action... It is only a living organism that faces a constant alternative: the issue of life or death..." The survival of the organism is the ultimate value to which all of the organism's activities are aimed, the end served by all of its lesser values.

Rand expands her view, asserting that the primary focus of man's free will is in the choice: to think or not to think. "Thinking is not an automatic function. In any hour and issue of his life, man is free to think or to evade that effort. Thinking requires a state of full, focused awareness. The act of focusing one's consciousness is volitional. Man can focus his mind to a full, active, purposefully directed awareness of reality—or he can unfocus it and let himself drift in a semiconscious daze, merely reacting to any chance stimulus of the immediate moment, at the mercy of his undirected sensory-perceptual mechanism and of any random, associational connections it might happen to make."[44] According to Rand, therefore, possessing free will, human beings must choose their values: one does not automatically hold one's own life as his ultimate value. Whether in fact a person's actions promote and fulfill his own life or not is a question of fact, as it is with all other organisms, but whether a person will act to promote his well-being is up to him, not hard-wired into his physiology. "Man has the power to act as his own destroyer—and that is the way he has acted through most of his history."[45]

Critics, such as philosopher Robert Nozick[46] and others,[47][48] assert that Rand's foundational argument in ethics is deficient. In the essay "On the Randian Argument", Nozick, while sympathetic to Rand's political conclusions, is particularly critical of Rand's foundational argument in ethics, which states that one's own life is, for each individual, the ultimate value because it makes all other values possible. He argues that to make her argument sound, one needs to explain why someone could not rationally prefer dying and having no values. Thus, her attempt to defend the morality of selfishness is, in his view, essentially an instance of begging the question. Nozick also argues that Rand's solution to David Hume's famous is-ought problem is unsatisfactory. In response, philosophers Douglas Rasmussen and Douglas Den Uyl have argued that Nozick misstated Rand's case.[47][49] According to Libertarian philosopher Michael Huemer, "the theory of 'The Objectivist Ethics' is simultaneously the most distinctive, least plausible, and generally worst defended of all of Rand's major ideas."[48]

The purpose of a moral code, Rand held, is to provide the principles by reference to which man can achieve the values his survival requires.[50] Rand summarizes:

If [man] chooses to live, a rational ethics will tell him what principles of action are required to implement his choice. If he does not choose to live, nature will take its course. Reality confronts a man with a great many 'must's', but all of them are conditional: the formula of realistic necessity is: 'you must, if -' and the if stands for man's choice: 'if you want to achieve a certain goal'.[51]

"Do not confuse altruism with kindness, good will or respect for the rights of others. These are not primaries, but consequences, which, in fact, altruism makes impossible. The irreducible primary of altruism, the basic absolute is self-sacrifice–which means self-immolation, self-abnegation, self-denial self-destruction–which means the self as a standard of evil, the selfless as a standard of the good." - Ayn Rand, Faith and Force: Destroyers of the Modern World[52]

Rand's explanation of values presents the view that an individual's primary moral obligation is to achieve his own well-being—it is for his life and his self-interest that an individual ought to adhere to a moral code.[53] Egoism is a corollary of setting man's life as the moral standard.[54] A corollary to Rand's endorsement of self-interest is her rejection of the ethical doctrine of altruism—which she defined in the sense of Auguste Comte's altruism (he coined the term), as a moral obligation to live for the sake of others. Rand did not use the term "selfishness" with the negative connotations that it usually has, but to refer to a form of rational egoism: "To live, man must hold three things as the supreme and ruling values of his life: Reason, Purpose, Self-esteem."[55]

Says Rand, "Man's mind is his basic tool of survival. Life is given to him, survival is not. His body is given to him, its sustenance is not. His mind is given to him, its content is not. To remain alive he must act and before he can act he must know the nature and purpose of his action. He cannot obtain his food without knowledge of food and of the way to obtain it. He cannot dig a ditch––or build a cyclotron––without a knowledge of his aim and the means to achieve it. To remain alive, he must think."[56] In her novels, The Fountainhead and Atlas Shrugged, she also emphasizes the central importance of productive work, romantic love and art to human happiness, and dramatizes the ethical character of their pursuit. The primary virtue in Objectivist ethics is rationality, as Rand meant it "the recognition and acceptance of reason as one's only source of knowledge, one's only judge of values and one's only guide to action."[57][citation needed]

Rand's egoism rejects subjectivism. There is a difference between rational self-interest as pursuit of one's own life and happiness in reality, and whim-worship or "hedonism." A whim-worshiper or "hedonist," according to Rand, is not motivated by a desire to live his own human life, but by a wish to live on a sub-human level. Instead of using "that which promotes my (human) life" as his standard of value, he mistakes "that which I (mindlessly happen to) value" for a standard of value, in contradiction of the fact that, existentially, he is a human and therefore rational organism. The "I value" in whim-worship or hedonism can be replaced with "we value," "he values," "they value," or "God values," and still it would remain dissociated from reality. Rand repudiated the equation of rational selfishness with hedonistic or whim-worshiping "selfishness-without-a-self." She held that the former is good, and the latter evil, and that there is a fundamental difference between them.[58]

For Rand, all of the principal virtues are applications of the role of reason as man's basic tool of survival: rationality, honesty, justice, independence, integrity, productiveness, and pride—each of which she explains in some detail in "The Objectivist Ethics."[59] The essence of Objectivist ethics is summarized by the oath her Atlas Shrugged character John Galt adhered to:

I swear—by my life and my love of it—that I will never live for the sake of another man, nor ask another man to live for mine.

Politics: individual rights and capitalism

Objectivism's politics derives immediately from its ethics, which provides the principles for "how man should treat other men." These principles of ethics provide the foundation for "the principles of a proper social system."[60] Objectivists hold that laissez-faire capitalism is "the only moral social system."[61]

In a fully free society, taxation—or, to be exact, payment for governmental services—would be voluntary. Since the proper services of a government—the police, the armed forces, the law courts—are demonstrably needed by individual citizens and affect their interests directly, the citizens would (and should) be willing to pay for such services, as they pay for insurance.

"Government Financing in a Free Society", Ayn Rand

Rand's defense of individual liberty integrates elements from her entire philosophy.[62] Since reason is the means of human knowledge, it is therefore each person's most fundamental means of survival and is necessary to the achievement of values.[63] The use or threat of force neutralizes the practical effect of an individual's reason, whether the force originates from the state or from a criminal. According to Rand, "man's mind will not function at the point of a gun."[64] Therefore, the only type of organized human behavior consistent with the operation of reason is that of voluntary cooperation. Persuasion is the method of reason. By its nature, the overtly irrational cannot rely on the use of persuasion and must ultimately resort to force to prevail.[65] Thus, Rand saw reason and freedom as correlates, just as she saw mysticism and force as corollaries.[66] Based on this understanding of the role of reason, Objectivists hold that the initiation of physical force against the will of another is immoral,[67] as are indirect initiations of force through threats,[68] fraud,[69] or breach of contract.[70] The use of defensive or retaliatory force, on the other hand, is appropriate.[71]

Objectivism holds that because the opportunity to use reason without the initiation of force is necessary to achieve moral values, each individual has an inalienable moral right to act as his own judgment directs and to keep the product of his effort. The fundamental right is the right to life, with other rights following from it, including rights to "liberty, property, and the pursuit of happiness."[72] "A 'right' is a moral principle defining and sanctioning a man's freedom of action in a social context."[73] These rights are specifically understood to be rights to action, not to specific results or objects, and the obligations created by rights are negative in nature: each individual must refrain from violating the rights of others.[74] Objectivists reject alternative notions of rights, such as positive rights[75] or rights belonging to anything other than an individual human being, such as collective rights or animal rights.[76]

Objectivism views the state as both legitimate and critically important.[77] Rand understood the state as the institution with a monopoly on the use of physical force in a given geographical area, so the issue is whether that force is used to protect or to violate individual rights; the state should use force only to protect individual rights,[78] and the "proper functions of a government" are "the police, to protect men from criminals—the armed services, to protect men from foreign invaders—the law courts, to settle disputes among men according to objectively defined laws."[79] In protecting individual rights, the government is acting as an agent of its citizens and "has no rights except the rights delegated to it by the citizens."[80] It is also important that the government act in an impartial manner according to specific, objectively defined laws.[81]

Objectivism holds that the only social system which fully recognizes individual rights is capitalism,[82] specifically what Rand described as "full, pure, uncontrolled, unregulated laissez-faire capitalism."[83] Rand includes socialism,[84] fascism, communism,[85] Nazism,[86] and the welfare state (which she often referred to as the "mixed economy"),[87] as systems under which individual rights are not protected. Far from regarding capitalism as a dog-eat-dog pattern of social organization, Objectivism regards it as a beneficent system in which the innovations of the most creative benefit everyone else in the society. However, unlike some other defenses of capitalism, Objectivism does not treat material benefits, such as economic growth, as the primary defense or moral justification of capitalism.[88] Rather, because capitalism is a moral system that allows individuals to practice virtues such as rationality and productivity, they are able to create material benefits as a result.[89] Objectivism maintains that only societies seeking to establish freedom (or free nations) have a right to self-determination.[90]

Poverty is not a mortgage on the labor of others—misfortune is not a mortgage on achievement—failure is not a mortgage on success—suffering is not a claim check, and its relief is not the goal of existence—man is not a sacrificial animal on anyone's altar nor for anyone's cause—life is not one huge hospital.

 Ayn Rand, The Voice of Reason [91]

Objectivism views limited intellectual property monopolies being granted to certain inventors and artists on a first-to-file basis as moral however, Rand viewed limits as important and held that if patent rights were granted in perpetuity it would necessarily lead to a de facto collectivism. Rand advocated the right to legal abortion.[92] She opposed involuntary military conscription (the "draft")[93] and any form of censorship, including legal restrictions on pornography.[94] Rand opposed racism, and any legal application of racism, and she considered affirmative action to be an example of legal racism.[95] Objectivists have opposed the environmentalist movement as being hostile to technology and, therefore, to humanity itself.[96] Objectivists have also opposed a number of government activities commonly supported by both liberals and conservatives, including antitrust laws,[97] public education,[98] and child labor laws.[99]

As a life-long atheist Rand rejected organized religion and specifically Christianity, which she decreed "the best kindergarten of communism possible."[100] More recent Objectivists have argued that religion is incompatible with American ideals, and the Christian right poses a threat to individual rights.[101] Objectivists have argued against faith-based initiatives,[102] displaying religious symbols in government facilities,[103] and the teaching of "intelligent design" in public schools.[104]

Aesthetics: metaphysical value-judgments

The Objectivist theory of art flows from its epistemology, by way of "psycho-epistemology" (Rand's term for an individual's characteristic mode of functioning in acquiring knowledge). Art, according to Objectivism, serves a human cognitive need: it allows human beings to grasp concepts as though they were percepts. Objectivism defines "art" as a "selective re-creation of reality according to an artist's metaphysical value-judgments"—that is, according to what the artist believes to be ultimately true and important about the nature of reality and humanity. In this respect Objectivism regards art as a way of presenting abstractions concretely, in perceptual form.[105]

The human need for art, on this view, stems from the need for cognitive economy. A concept is already a sort of mental shorthand standing for a large number of concretes, allowing a human being to think indirectly or implicitly of many more such concretes than can be held explicitly in mind. But a human being cannot hold indefinitely many concepts explicitly in mind either—and yet, on the Objectivist view, needs a comprehensive conceptual framework to provide guidance in life. Art offers a way out of this dilemma by providing a perceptual, easily grasped means of communicating and thinking about a wide range of abstractions, including one's metaphysical value-judgments. Objectivism regards art as an effective way to communicate a moral or ethical ideal.[106]

Objectivism does not, however, regard art as propagandistic: even though art involves moral values and ideals, its purpose is not to educate, only to show or project. Moreover, art need not be, and usually is not, the outcome of a full-blown, explicit philosophy. Usually it stems from an artist's sense of life (which is preconceptual and largely emotional).[107]

Rand held that Romanticism was the highest school of literary art, noting that Romanticism was "based on the recognition of the principle that man possesses the faculty of volition," absent which, Rand believed, literature is robbed of dramatic power, adding:

What the Romanticists brought to art was the primacy of values… Values are the source of emotions: a great deal of emotional intensity was projected in the work of the Romanticists and in the reactions of their audiences, as well as a great deal of color, imagination, originality, excitement, and all the other consequences of a value-oriented view of life.[108]

The term "romanticism," however, is often affiliated with emotionalism, to which Objectivism is completely opposed. Historically, many romantic artists were philosophically subjectivist. Most Objectivists who are also artists subscribe to what they call romantic realism, which is how Rand labeled her own work.[109]

Post-Rand development

Since Rand's death, others have developed and applied her ideas in their own work. In 1991, prominent Objectivist Leonard Peikoff published Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand, a comprehensive exposition of Rand's philosophy. Chris Matthew Sciabarra discusses Rand's ideas and theorizes about their intellectual origins in Ayn Rand: The Russian Radical (1995). Surveys such as On Ayn Rand by Allan Gotthelf (1999), Ayn Rand by Tibor R. Machan (2000), and Objectivism in One Lesson by Andrew Bernstein (2009) provide briefer introductions to Rand's ideas.

Some scholars have focused on applying Objectivism in more specific areas. Tibor Machan has developed Rand's contextual conception of human knowledge (while also drawing on the insights of J. L. Austin and Gilbert Harman) in works such as Objectivity,[110] and David Kelley has explicated Rand's epistemological ideas in works such as The Evidence of the Senses (1986) and A Theory of Abstraction (2001). In the field of ethics, Kelley has argued in works such as Unrugged Individualism (1996) and The Contested Legacy of Ayn Rand (2000) that Objectivists should pay more attention to the virtue of benevolence and place less emphasis on issues of moral sanction. Kelley's views have been controversial, with critics arguing that he contradicts important principles of Objectivism.[111]

An author who focuses on Rand's ethics, Tara Smith, stays closer to Rand's original ideas in such works as Moral Rights and Political Freedom (1995), Viable Values (2000), and Ayn Rand's Normative Ethics (2006).[112] In collaboration with Leonard Peikoff, David Harriman has developed a theory of scientific induction based upon Rand's theory of concepts in The Logical Leap: Induction in Physics (2010).[113]

The political aspects of Rand's philosophy are discussed by Andrew Bernstein in The Capitalist Manifesto (2005). Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics by George Reisman (1996) attempts to integrate Objectivist methodology and insights with both Classical and Austrian economics. In psychology, Professor Edwin A. Locke and Ellen Kenner have explored Rand's ideas in The Selfish Path to Romance: How to Love with Passion & Reason.[114] Other writers have explored the application of Objectivism to fields ranging from art, as in What Art Is by Louis Torres and Michelle Marder Kamhi (2000), to teleology, as in The Biological Basis of Teleological Concepts by Harry Binswanger (1990).

Intellectual impact

Academic philosophers have generally dismissed Rand's ideas and have marginalized her philosophy.[115][116][117][118][119] Because of Rand's criticism of contemporary intellectuals,[120] Objectivism has been called "fiercely anti-academic".[121] David Sidorsky, a professor of moral and political philosophy at Columbia University, says Rand's work is "outside the mainstream" and is more of an ideological movement than a well-grounded philosophy.[122] Rand is not found in the comprehensive academic reference texts The Oxford Companion to Philosophy or The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, but is the subject of entries in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,[123] The Dictionary of Modern American Philosophers,[124] the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy,[125] and The Routledge Dictionary of Twentieth-Century Political Thinkers.[126] A listing of Rand also appears in the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, featuring the assessment "The influence of Rand's ideas was strongest among college students in the USA but attracted little attention from academic philosophers. Her outspoken defence of capitalism in works like Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal (1967), and her characterization of her position as a defence of the 'virtue of selfishness' in her novel of the same title (published in 1974), also brought notoriety, but kept her out of the intellectual mainstream."[127]

File:Ayn Rand quote, American Adventure, Epcot Center, Walt Disney World.jpg.jpg
Quote from Ayn Rand at the Epcot Center, Walt Disney World

In recent years Rand's works are more likely to be encountered in the classroom.[121] The Ayn Rand Society, dedicated to fostering the scholarly study of Objectivism, is affiliated with the American Philosophical Association's Eastern Division.[128] Aristotle scholar and Objectivist Allan Gotthelf, chairman of the Society,[129] and his colleagues have argued for more academic study of Objectivism, viewing the philosophy as a unique and intellectually interesting defense of classical liberalism that is worth debating.[130] Since 1999 a refereed Journal of Ayn Rand Studies began.[131] In 2006 the University of Pittsburgh held a conference focusing on Objectivism.[132] In addition, there is a growing list of Objectivist philosophers, including Tara Smith and James G. Lennox, who hold tenured positions at leading American philosophy departments.[133] Objectivist programs and fellowships have been supported at the University of Pittsburgh[134] University of Texas at Austin[135] and University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill.[136]

Rand's philosophy has had a significant impact on the work of a range of notable academics and scholars, including: Martin Anderson,[137] Petr Beckmann,[138] Andrew Bernstein,[139] Harry Binswanger,[140] Allan Gotthelf,[141] Robert Hessen,[142] John Hospers,[143] David Kelley,[144] James G. Lennox,[145] Liu Junning,[146] Edwin A. Locke,[147] Tibor Machan,[148] Charles Murray,[149] Leonard Peikoff,[150] Douglas B. Rasmussen,[151] George Reisman,[152] John Ridpath,[153] Murray Rothbard,[154] Chris Matthew Sciabarra,[155] George H. Smith,[156] Tara Smith,[157] and Walter E. Williams.[158] In recent decades, annual conferences have been conducted featuring lectures by such academics and scholars, highlighting their recent work.[159]

According to one Rand biographer, most people "encounter" Rand's works in their "formative years." [160] (However, individuals who were first influenced by Objectivism as mature adults include Alan Greenspan, John Hospers, Charles Sures and Edith Efron.[161]) Rand's former protégé Nathaniel Branden referred to Rand's "especially powerful appeal to the young,"[162] while Onkar Ghate of the Ayn Rand Institute said Rand "appeals to the idealism of youth."[163] This appeal has alarmed a number of critics of the philosophy.[164] Many of these young people later abandon their "affection or admiration" for Rand and are often said to have "outgrown" them, according to Brian Doherty, since few of the "tens of millions" of her readers actually "internalize" Rand's message.[165] Supporters of Rand's work recognize the phenomenon, but attribute it to the loss of youthful idealism and inability to resist social pressures for intellectual conformity.[163][165] In contrast, Jennifer Burns says some critics "dismiss Rand as a shallow thinker appealing only to adolescents," although Burns thinks the critics "miss her significance" as a "gateway drug" to right-wing politics.[166]

Psychologist Albert Ellis has argued that adherence to Objectivism can result in hazardous psychological effects.[167] After he was expelled from Rand's circle, her former lover and notable psychologist Nathaniel Branden criticized Objectivism's "destructive moralism," something he reports having engaged in himself when he was associated with Rand. He now argues that Rand's fiction, if not her explicit ideas, "subtly encourages repression, self-alienation, and guilt." However, Branden has retained his support for Objectivist ethics.[168][169]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ a b Rubin, Harriet (2007-09-15). "Ayn Rand's Literature of Capitalism". The New York Times. Retrieved 2007-09-18.
  2. ^ Rand, Ayn. "What Is Capitalism?". Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal. p. 23.
  3. ^ Peikoff 1991, p. 36
  4. ^ "About the Author" in Rand 1992, pp. 1170–1171
  5. ^ Peikoff 1991, pp. 4–11
  6. ^ Rand 1992, p. 1040.
  7. ^ Peikoff 1991, p. 11
  8. ^ Rand 1992, p. 1016.
  9. ^ Peikoff 1991, p. 5
  10. ^ Gotthelf, Allan (2000). On Ayn Rand. Wadsworth.
  11. ^ Rand 1990
  12. ^ [1]
  13. ^ Rand 1992, p. 1037.
  14. ^ Peikoff 1991, p. 14
  15. ^ Peikoff 1991, pp. 31–33; an example of the Objectivist approach to metaphysical argumentation may be found in George H. Smith, Atheism: The Case Against God, 1974, Nash, chapters 1-7, ISBN 0-8402-1115-5 and ISBN 0-87975-124-X.
  16. ^ Rand 1961, p. 124
  17. ^ Rand 1964, p. 22.
  18. ^ Rand 1990, p. 5
  19. ^ Branden, Nathaniel (1963). "The Stolen Concept". The Objectivist Newsletter. 2 (1): 2, 4. {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help); Unknown parameter |month= ignored (help)
  20. ^ Rand 1990, p. 3.
  21. ^ a b Kelley 1986.
  22. ^ Kelley (1986); Peikoff 1991, pp. 44–48.
  23. ^ Peikoff 1991, pp. 116–121.
  24. ^ Rand 1961, p. 64.
  25. ^ Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology, by Ayn Rand, edited by Harry Binswanger and Leonard Peikoff, Plume Books; 2 Expanded edition, 1990, ISBN 978-0452010307, pg 36.
  26. ^ Rand 1982, pp. 62–63.
  27. ^ Rand 1961, p. 223; Peikoff 1991, pp. 182–185.
  28. ^ Rand 1990, p. 81.
  29. ^ Rand 1961, p. 31.
  30. ^ Peikoff, Leonard. "The Analytic-Synthetic Dichotomy." in Rand 1990, pp. 97–98. The quotes within this passage are of Rand's material elsewhere in the same book.
  31. ^ Rand 1990, p. 12; for more on Rand's theory of concepts see also Kelley, David "A Theory of Abstraction" and "The Psychology of Abstraction", Cognition and Brain Theory vol. vii, no. 3 and 4 (Summer/Fall 1984), and Rasmussen, Douglas B., "Quine and Aristotelian Essentialism," The New Scholasticism 58 (Summer, 1984)
  32. ^ Rand 1990, pp. 15–28.
  33. ^ Peikoff, Leonard. "The Analytic-Synthetic Dichotomy," in Rand 1990, p. 94.
  34. ^ Peikoff, Leonard. "The Analytic-Synthetic Dichotomy". in Rand 1990, pp. 116–118.
  35. ^ Lecture by Leonard Peikoff, cited in Sciabarra 1995.
  36. ^ Peikoff 1991, pp. 171–181.
  37. ^ Branden, Nathaniel (1963). "Intellectual Ammunition Department: What Is the Objectivist View of Agnosticism?". The Objectivist Newsletter. 2 (4): 15. {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help); Unknown parameter |month= ignored (help)
  38. ^ e.g., Machan, Tibor R. (1999). Ayn Rand. New York: Peter Lang, pp. 134–151.
  39. ^ Campbell, Robert L. (2008, Fall). The Peikovian Doctrine of the Arbitrary Assertion. Journal of Ayn Rand Studies, 10(1), 85–170.
  40. ^ Rand 1990, p. 289
  41. ^ Campbell, R. L. (1999, Fall). Ayn Rand and the Cognitive Revolution in Psychology. Journal of Ayn Rand Studies, 1(1), 107–134. http://hubcap.clemson.edu/~campber/randcogrev.html
  42. ^ Rand 1964, p. 13.
  43. ^ Rand 1964, p. 18; for more on Rand's metaethics see Binswanger, Harry (1990). The Biological Basis of Teleological Concepts. Los Angeles: Ayn Rand Institute Press. pp. 58–66. ISBN 0-9625336-0-2., Smith, Tara (2000). Viable Values. Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 0-8476-9760-6. and Gotthelf, Allan (editor) (2010). Metaethics, Egoism, and Virtue: Studies in Ayn Rand's Normative Theory. University of Pittsburgh Press/Ayn Rand Society Philosophical Studies. ISBN 0822944006. {{cite book}}: |first= has generic name (help)
  44. ^ Rand 1964, p. 22; for more on Rand's theory of volition, see Binswanger, Harry (1991). "Volition as Cognitive Self-Regulation". Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes. 50 (2): 154–178. doi:10.1016/0749-5978(91)90019-P. {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help); Unknown parameter |month= ignored (help); Branden, Nathaniel (1969). "Man: A Being of Volitional Consciousness". The Psychology of Self-Esteem. Los Angeles: Nash Publishing. ISBN 0-8402-1109-0.; and Peikoff 1991, pp. 55–72.
  45. ^ Rand 1992, p. 1013.
  46. ^ Nozick, Robert (1971). "On the Randian Argument". The Personalist. 52: 282–304. {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help); Unknown parameter |month= ignored (help) Reprinted in Nozick, Socratic Puzzles, 1997, ISBN 0-674-81653-6.
  47. ^ a b O'Neil, Patrick M. (1983). "Ayn Rand and the Is-Ought Problem" (PDF). Journal of Libertarian Studies. 7 (1): 81–99. {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help); Unknown parameter |month= ignored (help)
  48. ^ a b Huemer, Michael (January 22, 2010). "Why Ayn Rand? Some Alternate Answers". Cato Institute. Retrieved 2010-04-13.
  49. ^ Den Uyl, Douglas; Rasmussen, Douglas (1978). "Nozick On the Randian Argument". The Personalist. 59: 184–205. {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help); Unknown parameter |month= ignored (help) Reprinted along with Nozick's article in Reading Nozick, J. Paul, ed., 1981, Rowman & Littlefield.
  50. ^ Peikoff, Leonard (February 27, 1989). "Why Should One Act on Principle?". The Intellectual Activist. 4 (20). {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  51. ^ Rand, "Causality Versus Duty", p. 118-119
  52. ^ Ayn Rand, "Faith and Force: Destroyers of the Modern World," Philosophy: Who Needs it, 1982, New American Library, p. 74.
  53. ^ Smith, Tara (2006). Ayn Rand's Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 23–24. ISBN 0-521-86050-4.
  54. ^ Peikoff 1991, p. 230
  55. ^ Rand 1961, p. 128
  56. ^ Rand 1992, p. 1012.
  57. ^ Rand 1964, p. 25.
  58. ^ Rand 1964, p. 18.
  59. ^ See also Smith, Tara, The Virtuous Egoist: Ayn Rand's Normative Ethics Cambridge University Press, 2006 ISBN 978-0-521-86050-5.
  60. ^ Rand 1982, p. 4
  61. ^ Peikoff 1991, p. 380
  62. ^ Peikoff 1991, p. 354; Sciabarra 1995, p. 274
  63. ^ Bernstein, Andrew (2009). Objectivism in One Lesson: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Ayn Rand. Lanham, Maryland: Hamilton Books. pp. 25–31. ISBN 0-7618-4359-0.
  64. ^ Rand 1967, p. 141
  65. ^ Peikoff 1991, pp. 310–313
  66. ^ Rand 1982, p. 66
  67. ^ Rand 1964, p. 36; Peikoff 1991, p. 310; Smith 1997, pp. 143–147
  68. ^ Smith 1997, pp. 150–155
  69. ^ Peikoff 1991, pp. 319
  70. ^ Rand 1964, pp. 129–130
  71. ^ Rand 1964, p. 126; Peikoff 1991, p. 320
  72. ^ Peikoff 1991, pp. 351–352. The Objectivist understanding of rights is explored at length in Smith 1997.
  73. ^ Rand 1964, p. 110
  74. ^ Peikoff 1991, p. 355
  75. ^ Smith 1997, pp. 165–182; cf. Touchstone, Kathleen (2006). Then Athena Said: Unilateral Transfers and the Transformation of Objectivist Ethics. Lanham, Maryland: University Press of America. p. 108. ISBN 0-7618-3519-9.
  76. ^ Peikoff 1991, pp. 356–358; Rand 1964, pp. 120
  77. ^ Peikoff 1991, p. 364
  78. ^ Rand 1964, pp. 125–128
  79. ^ Rand 1964, p. 131
  80. ^ Rand 1964, p. 129
  81. ^ Rand 1964, p. 128; Peikoff 1991, pp. 364–365
  82. ^ Rand 1967, p. 19
  83. ^ Rand 1964, p. 37
  84. ^ Rand 1964, p. 106
  85. ^ Rand 1967, p. 180
  86. ^ Peikoff, Leonard (1982). The Ominous Parallels: The End of Freedom in America. New York: Stein & Day. ISBN 0-8128-2850-X.
  87. ^ Rand 1967, pp. 206–207, 211
  88. ^ Peikoff 1991, pp. 392–395; Sciabarra 1995, p. 284
  89. ^ Sciabarra 1995, p. 292; Bernstein, Andrew (2005). The Capitalist Manifesto. Lanham, Maryland: University Press of America. p. 223. ISBN 0-7618-3220-3.; Reisman, George (1996). Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics (PDF). Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books. p. 19. ISBN 0-915463-73-3.
  90. ^ Rand 1964, p. 103
  91. ^ The Voice of Reason: Essays in Objectivist Thought, by Ayn Rand, Leonard Peikoff, Peter Schwartz, New American Library, 1989, ISBN 0-453-00634-5, pg 175.
  92. ^ Rand, Ayn (1989). "Of Living Death". The Voice of Reason. Edited by Leonard Peikoff. New York: New American Library. ISBN 0-453-00634-5.
  93. ^ Rand 1967, pp. 226–228
  94. ^ Rand 1982, pp. 173–184
  95. ^ Rand 1964, pp. 173–184; cf. Wortham, Anne (1981). The Other Side of Racism. Columbus, Ohio: Ohio State University Press. ISBN 0-8142-0318-3.
  96. ^ Rand, Ayn (1999). "The Anti-Industrial Revolution". Return of the Primitive. Edited by Peter Schwartz. New York: Meridian. pp. 270–290. ISBN 0-452-01184-1.; Berliner, Michael S (April 18, 2008). "The Danger of Environmentalism". Ayn Rand Institute. Retrieved June 21, 2009.
  97. ^ Greenspan, Alan. "Antitrust" in Rand 1967, pp. 63–71
  98. ^ Branden, Nathaniel. "Common Fallacies about Capitalism" in Rand 1967, pp. 89–92
  99. ^ Hessen, Robert. "The Effects of the Industrial Revolution on Women and Children" in Rand 1967, pp. 110–113
  100. ^ Burns 2009, pp. 43
  101. ^ Peikoff, Leonard (1986). "Religion Versus America". The Objectivist Forum. 7 (3). {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help); Unknown parameter |month= ignored (help)
  102. ^ Epstein, Alex (February 4, 2003). "Faith-Based Initiatives Are an Assault on Secular Government". Ayn Rand Institute. Retrieved June 19, 2009.
  103. ^ Binswanger, Harry (March 3, 2005). "The Ten Commandments vs. America". Ayn Rand Institute. Retrieved June 19, 2009.
  104. ^ Lockitch, Keith (December 11, 2005). "'Intelligent Design' Is about Religion versus Reason". Orange County Register.
  105. ^ Peikoff 1991, p. 417
  106. ^ Peikoff 1991, p. 422
  107. ^ Peikoff 1991, p. 426
  108. ^ Rand, Ayn, "What is Romanticism?," The Romantic Manifesto
  109. ^ See also, Thomas, William, edit., The Literary Art of Ayn Rand, The Objectivist Center, 2005. ISBN 1-57724-070-7, Holzer, Erika, Ayn Rand: My Fiction Writing Teacher, Madison Press, 2005, and Torres, Louis, and Kamhi, Michelle Marder, What Art Is: the Esthetic Theory of Ayn Rand, Open Court, 2000.
  110. ^ Ashgate, 2004.
  111. ^ Peikoff, Leonard (May 18, 1989). "Fact and Value". The Intellectual Activist. 5 (1). {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help); Schwartz, Peter (May 18, 1989). "On Moral Sanctions". The Intellectual Activist. 5 (1). {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  112. ^ Khawaja, Irfan (December 2000). "Comments on Tara Smith's Viable Values". Retrieved 2009-05-29. [The book] lays out the essential features of Ayn Rand's Objectivist Ethics in a clear and persuasive way...; Hsieh, Diana (2007). "Egoism Explained: A Review of Tara Smith's Ayn Rand's Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist". The Objective Standard. 2 (1). [Smith provides] a full and accurate understanding of Rand's revolutionary moral code. {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help); Unknown parameter |month= ignored (help)
  113. ^ Harriman, David, The Logical Leap, 2010, New American Library.
  114. ^ Locke, Edwin, and Kenner, Ellen, Platform, 2011
  115. ^ Den Uyl & Rasmussen 1984, p. 36
  116. ^ Gladstein, Mimi Reisel (1999). The New Ayn Rand Companion. Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press. p. 2. ISBN 0-313-30321-5. OCLC 40359365.
  117. ^ Gotthelf 2000, p. 1 harvnb error: multiple targets (2×): CITEREFGotthelf2000 (help)
  118. ^ Heyl, Jenny A. (1995). "Ayn Rand (1905-1982)". In Waithe, Mary Ellen (ed) (ed.). Contemporary Women Philosophers: 1900-today. A History of Women Philosophers series. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. p. 223. ISBN 0-7923-2808-6. {{cite book}}: |editor-first= has generic name (help)
  119. ^ Machan 2000, p. 9
  120. ^ For Rand's severe critique of the 20th century's "intellectual bankruptcy", and what she believed led to it, see Rand, Ayn, For the Intellectual, title essay, Random House, 1961; however, Rand did give qualified endorsement of the work of certain contemporary thinkers, e.g., Aristotle, by John Herman Randall and Reason and Analysis by Brand Blanshard.
  121. ^ a b McLemee, Scott (1999). "The Heirs Of Ayn Rand: Has Objectivism Gone Subjective?". Lingua Franca. 9 (6): 45–55. {{cite journal}}: Unknown parameter |month= ignored (help)
  122. ^ Harvey, Benjamin (May 15, 2005). "Ayn Rand at 100: An 'ism' struts its stuff". Rutland Herald. Retrieved July 20, 2007. {{cite news}}: Italic or bold markup not allowed in: |publisher= (help)
  123. ^ Badhwar & Long 2010
  124. ^ Salmieri, Gregory; Gotthelf, Allan (2005). "Ayn Rand". In Shook, John (ed) (ed.). The Dictionary of Modern American Philosophers. London: Thoemmes Continuum. ISBN 1-84371-037-4. {{cite book}}: |editor-first= has generic name (help)
  125. ^ Hicks, Stephen R. C. (July 7, 2005). "Ayn Rand (1905-1982)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved March 15, 2011.
  126. ^ Stevens, Jacqueline (1998). "Ayn Rand". In Benewick, Robert; Green, Philip (eds) (eds.). The Routledge Dictionary of Twentieth-Century Political Thinkers (2nd ed.). London: Routledge. pp. 263–264. ISBN 0-415-15881-8. {{cite book}}: |editor2-first= has generic name (help); Unknown parameter |lastauthoramp= ignored (|name-list-style= suggested) (help)
  127. ^ Kukathas, Chandran (1998). "Rand, Ayn (1905–82)". In Craig, Edward (ed) (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 8. New York: Routledge. pp. 55–56. ISBN 0-415-07310-3. OCLC 318280731. {{cite encyclopedia}}: |editor-first= has generic name (help)
  128. ^ "Proceedings and Addresses of The American Philosophical Association – Eastern Division Program" (PDF). 2006. Retrieved 2007-07-25.
  129. ^ Ayn Rand Society
  130. ^ Uyl, Douglas J. Den (1998). "On Rand as philosopher" (PDF). Reason Papers. 23: 70–71. Retrieved 2007-07-20. {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  131. ^ Sharlet, Jeff (1999-04-09). "Ayn Rand has finally caught the attention of scholars: New books and research projects involve philosophy, political theory, literary criticism, and feminism". The Chronicle of Higher Education. 45 (31): 17–18. {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  132. ^ "Concepts and Objectivity: Knowledge, Science, and Values" (PDF). Retrieved 2007-07-20.
  133. ^ Philosophy departments of the United States, ranked by the Philosophical Gourmet Report,
  134. ^ Fricke, Erika (2004). "Follow Reason: An Objectivist viewpoint". Pitt Magazine. University of Pittsburgh. Retrieved 2009-06-17. {{cite web}}: Unknown parameter |month= ignored (help)
  135. ^ New fellowship for study of Objectivism established at The University of Texas at Austin | The University of Texas at Austin
  136. ^ Carolina Development, UNC-Chapel Hill
  137. ^ McConnell, Scott, "Martin Anderson," 100 Voices: an Oral History of Ayn Rand, New American Library, 2010, pp. 264–267
  138. ^ Branden, Barbara, The Passion of Ayn Rand, Doubleday, 1986, p. 409
  139. ^ Andrew Bernstein, "The Integration of Plot and Theme in We the Living," Mayhew, Robert, ed., Lexington Press, 2004, pp. 279-285, and his Objectivism in One Lesson, Hamilton Books, 2009
  140. ^ Harry Binswanger, The Ayn Rand Lexicon, New American Library, 1986, and "Ayn Rand's Life: Highlights and Sidelights," Second Renaissance Books, 1994
  141. ^ McConnell, Scott, "Allan Gotthelf," 100 Voices: an Oral History of Ayn Rand, 2010, New American Library, pp. 329-349
  142. ^ In Defense of the Corporation, Hoover Instit. Press, 1979, pp. ix-x
  143. ^ John Hospers, "Conversations with Ayn Rand," Liberty, July, 1990, pp. 23-36, Sept., 1990, pp. 42-52
  144. ^ David Kelley, Unrugged Individualism: The Selfish Basis of Benevolence, 1996 (rev 2nd ed 2003) ISBN 1-57724-066-9
  145. ^ James G. Lennox is a founding member of the Ayn Rand Society, affil. American Philosophical Assoc., "Proceedings and Addresses of The American Philosophical Association – Eastern Division Program" (PDF). 2006. http://www.apa.udel.edu/apa/publications/proceedings/v80n1/public/80_1_public.pdf. Retrieved 2007-07-25
  146. ^ "Liu Junning". Retrieved 2011-01-06.
  147. ^ McConnell, Scott, "Edwin A. Locke," 100 Voices: an Oral History of Ayn Rand, 2010, New American Library, pp. 350-352
  148. ^ Tibor Machan, Ayn Rand, 2000, Objectivity, Ashgate, 2004, and Classical Individualism: The Supreme Importance of Each Human Being, Routledge, 1998
  149. ^ Branden Barbara, The Passion of Ayn Rand, Doubleday, 1986, p. 418
  150. ^ Leonard Peikoff, "My Thirty Years with Ayn Rand," The Voice of Reason: Essays in Objectivist Thought, New American Library, 1988, pp. 334-353
  151. ^ Norms of Liberty, Reading Rasmussen and Den Uyl: Critical Essays on "Norms of Liberty", edit. Skoble, Aeon J. , 2008
  152. ^ George Reisman, Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics, 1986, Ottawa, Illinois: Jameson Books. p. 19, ISBN 0-915463-73-3
  153. ^ McConnell, Scott, "John Ridpath," 100 Voices: an Oral History of Ayn Rand, 2010, New American Library, pp. 352-360
  154. ^ Burns, Jennifer, Goddess of the Market: Ayn Rand and the American Right, Oxford Univ. Press, 2009, p. 145, 182
  155. ^ Chris Matthew Sciabarra, Ayn Rand: the Russian Radical, Pennsylvania State Univ. Press, 1995
  156. ^ George H. Smith, Atheism, Ayn Rand and Other Heresies, 1991. ISBN 0-87975-577-6
  157. ^ Tara Smith, The Virtuous Egoist: Ayn Rand's Normative Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 2006 ISBN 978-0-521-86050-5
  158. ^ Williams states that Rand's is "one of the best defenses and explanations of capitalism one is likely to read," Williams, Walter. "Book Recommendation List". Walter E. Williams Homepage. Retrieved 2010-11-16.
  159. ^ "Objectivist Conferences". Retrieved 2010-12-14.
  160. ^ Heller, Anne C. (2009). Ayn Rand and the World She Made. New York: Doubleday. p. xii. ISBN 978-0-385-51399-9.
  161. ^ Greenspan, The Age of Turbulence, Penguin Press, 2007; Hospers, "Conversations with Ayn Rand," Liberty, July, 1990, pp. 23-36, Sept., 1990, pp. 42-52; Sures, Facets of Ayn Rand, ARI, 2001 pp. 53-68; McConnell, Scott, "Al Ramrus," 100 Voices: an Oral History of Ayn Rand, 2010, New American Library, pp. 157-164.
  162. ^ Branden, Nathaniel. "The Benefits and Hazards of the Philosophy of Ayn Rand".
  163. ^ a b Ghate, Onkar (February 2, 2008). "The Appeal of Ayn Rand". Capitalism Magazine.
  164. ^ Gladstein 1999, p. 111
  165. ^ a b Doherty, Brian (2007). Radicals for Capitalism: A Freewheeling History of the Modern American Libertarian Movement. New York: Public Affairs. p. 544. ISBN 1-58648-350-1. {{cite book}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  166. ^ Burns 2009, p. 4
  167. ^ Ellis, Albert (1968). Is Objectivism A Religion?. New York: Lyle Stuart.
  168. ^ Branden, N., Honoring the Self, 1983, p. 205)
  169. ^ Branden, Nathaniel (1984). "The Benefits and Hazards of the Philosophy of Ayn Rand". Journal of Humanistic Psychology. 24 (4): 39–64. doi:10.1177/0022167884244004. Retrieved 2008-04-08. {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)

References