Teleological argument: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
No edit summary
No edit summary
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Philosophy of religion (sidebar)}}
{{Philosophy of religion (sidebar)}}
A '''teleological argument''' for the existence of God, also called an '''argument from design'''<ref name="Himma">Himma, Kenneth Einar (2006). [http://www.iep.utm.edu/d/design.htm#SH1b "Design Arguments for the Existence of God"], in James Fieser and Bradley Dowden, eds., ''The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', retrieved 8/24/08</ref><ref name="Ratzsch">Ratzsch, Del, [http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2009/entries/teleological-arguments/ "Teleological Arguments for God's Existence"], ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (Winter 2009 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)</ref><ref name="Toner">Toner, P. (1909). "The Existence of God: [http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/06608b.htm#IBc ''The argument from design'']", in ''The Catholic Encyclopedia''. New York: Robert Appleton Company. Retrieved January 7, 2010.</ref> or '''[[Critique of Pure Reason#Physico-theological .28.22Watch Maker.22.29 Proof of God.27s Existence|physicotheological proof]]''',<ref name="sep-kant-metaphysics">{{cite encyclopedia |last=Grier |first=Michelle |year=2012 |title=Kant's Critique of Metaphysics |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor=Edward N. Zalta |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/kant-metaphysics/#OthPro |edition=Summer 2012 |at=§5.2 The Other Proofs}}</ref> is an ''[[Empirical evidence|a posteriori]]'' argument for the [[existence of God]] based on apparent design (purpose<ref>''[[Oxford English Dictionary]]'', meaning 4. of "design".</ref>) in [[nature (philosophy)|nature]].
A '''teleological argument''' for the existence of God, also called an '''argument from [intelligent] design'''<ref name="Himma">Himma, Kenneth Einar (2006). [http://www.iep.utm.edu/d/design.htm#SH1b "Design Arguments for the Existence of God"], in James Fieser and Bradley Dowden, eds., ''The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', retrieved 8/24/08</ref><ref name="Ratzsch">Ratzsch, Del, [http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2009/entries/teleological-arguments/ "Teleological Arguments for God's Existence"], ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (Winter 2009 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)</ref><ref name="Toner">Toner, P. (1909). "The Existence of God: [http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/06608b.htm#IBc ''The argument from design'']", in ''The Catholic Encyclopedia''. New York: Robert Appleton Company. Retrieved January 7, 2010.</ref>, or '''[[Critique of Pure Reason#Physico-theological .28.22Watch Maker.22.29 Proof of God.27s Existence|physicotheological proof]]''',<ref name="sep-kant-metaphysics">{{cite encyclopedia |last=Grier |first=Michelle |year=2012 |title=Kant's Critique of Metaphysics |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor=Edward N. Zalta |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/kant-metaphysics/#OthPro |edition=Summer 2012 |at=§5.2 The Other Proofs}}</ref> is an ''[[Empirical evidence|a posteriori]]'' argument for the [[existence of God]] based on apparent human-like and design (purpose<ref>''[[Oxford English Dictionary]]'', meaning 4. of "design".</ref>) in [[nature (philosophy)|nature]].


Plato proposed a divine Artificer ([[demiurge]]); others, notably Aristotle, rejected that conclusion in favor of a more [[naturalism (philosophy)|naturalistic]] teleological physics.
The concept of intelligent design appears to have begun with [[Socrates]]. Plato proposed a divine Artificer ([[demiurge]]); others, notably Aristotle, rejected that conclusion in favor of a more [[naturalism (philosophy)|naturalistic]] [[teleology|teleological]] physics.


In the Middle Ages, the Islamic philosopher [[Averroes]] introduced a teleological argument. Later, a teleological argument is the fifth of [[Saint Thomas Aquinas]]' [[Quinque viae|Five Ways]], his rational proofs for the existence of God. The teleological argument was continued by [[empiricism|empiricists]] in the 17th and 18th centuries, who believed that the order in the world suggested the existence of God. [[William Paley]] developed these ideas with his version of the watch maker analogy. He argued that in the same way a watch's complexity implies the existence of its maker, so too, one may infer the Creator of the universe exists, given the evident complexity of Nature. This argument resonates with a notion of the fine-tuned Universe, understood as an alternative to the [[anthropic principle]].
In the Middle Ages, the Islamic philosopher [[Averroes]] introduced a teleological argument. Later, a teleological argument is the fifth of [[Saint Thomas Aquinas]]' [[Quinque viae|Five Ways]], his rational proofs for the existence of God. The teleological argument was continued by [[empiricism|empiricists]] in the 17th and 18th centuries, who believed that the order in the world suggested the existence of God. [[William Paley]] developed these ideas with his version of the watch maker analogy. He argued that in the same way a watch's complexity implies the existence of its maker, so too, one may infer the Creator of the universe exists, given the evident complexity of Nature. This argument resonates with a notion of the fine-tuned Universe, understood as an alternative to the [[anthropic principle]].

Revision as of 20:12, 27 August 2013

A teleological argument for the existence of God, also called an argument from [intelligent] design[1][2][3], or physicotheological proof,[4] is an a posteriori argument for the existence of God based on apparent human-like and design (purpose[5]) in nature.

The concept of intelligent design appears to have begun with Socrates. Plato proposed a divine Artificer (demiurge); others, notably Aristotle, rejected that conclusion in favor of a more naturalistic teleological physics.

In the Middle Ages, the Islamic philosopher Averroes introduced a teleological argument. Later, a teleological argument is the fifth of Saint Thomas Aquinas' Five Ways, his rational proofs for the existence of God. The teleological argument was continued by empiricists in the 17th and 18th centuries, who believed that the order in the world suggested the existence of God. William Paley developed these ideas with his version of the watch maker analogy. He argued that in the same way a watch's complexity implies the existence of its maker, so too, one may infer the Creator of the universe exists, given the evident complexity of Nature. This argument resonates with a notion of the fine-tuned Universe, understood as an alternative to the anthropic principle.

There have been numerous criticisms of the different versions of the teleological argument. Commonly, critics argue that any implied designer need not have the qualities commonly attributed to the God of classical theism. Moreover, there is a great diversity of spiritual and religious beliefs concerning the identity and attributes of such a Creator, which change from one society to another and from one period of human history to another.

A version of the argument from design is central to both creation science and Intelligent design,[6] but unlike Paley's openness to deistic design through God given laws, they seek scientific confirmation of repeated miraculous interventions in the history of life.[7] When teaching of evolution was reintroduced into public schools in the United States in the late 1950s, efforts were made to have creationism in the form of "creation science" given equal recognition in school science lessons. When it was ruled that this was unconstitutional as teaching one specific religious view, the design argument was reframed as intelligent design which omitted references to God and was claimed to be a "scientific research program". In 2005, a U.S. Federal Court ruled that intelligent design is a religious argument and is not science. It was based on negative arguments that complex systems with a supposed appearance of design could not have evolved, but gave no adequate explanation and ignored published scientific explanations of the evolution of this complexity.[6]

Biologists have presented several explanations for biological complexity, notably the theory of evolution through natural selection, the theory of biological self-organization, as well as a growing number of studies in the field of complex systems. In science, the study of the origins of life comes under the topic of abiogenesis.

History

Classical and early Christian writers

Plato and Aristotle, depicted here in The School of Athens, both developed philosophical arguments addressing the universe's apparent order (logos)

According to Xenophon, Socrates (c. 469 - 399 BC) argued that the adaptation of human parts to one another, such as the eyelids protecting the eyeballs, could not have been due to chance and was a sign of wise planning in the universe.[8]

Plato (c. 427 – c. 347 BC) posited a "demiurge" of supreme wisdom and intelligence as the creator of the cosmos in his work Timaeus. Plato's teleological perspective is also built upon the analysis of a priori order and structure in the world that he had already presented in The Republic. Plato does not propose creation ex nihilo; rather, the demiurge made order from the chaos of the cosmos, imitating the eternal Forms.[9]

Plato's world of eternal and unchanging Forms, imperfectly represented in matter by a divine Artisan, contrasts sharply with the various mechanistic Weltanschauungen, of which atomism was, by the 4th century at least, the most prominent... This debate was to persist throughout the ancient world. Atomistic mechanism got a shot in the arm from Epicurus... while the Stoics adopted a divine teleology... The choice seems simple: either show how a structured, regular world could arise out of undirected processes, or inject intelligence into the system. This was how Aristotle (384–322 bc), when still a young acolyte of Plato, saw matters. Cicero (On the Nature of the Gods 2. 95 = Fr. 12) preserves Aristotle's own cave-image: if troglodytes were brought on a sudden into the upper world, they would immediately suppose it to have been intelligently arranged. But Aristotle grew to abandon this view; although he believes in a divine being, the Prime Mover is not the efficient cause of action in the Universe, and plays no part in constructing or arranging it... But, although he rejects the divine Artificer, Aristotle does not resort to a pure mechanism of random forces. Instead he seeks to find a middle way between the two positions, one which relies heavily on the notion of Nature, or phusis.[10]

— R. J. Hankinson, Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought

Aristotle (c. 384 – 322 BC) argued that the most complete explanation in regard to the natural, as well as the artificial, is for the most part teleological.[11] Based solely on the study of immature specimens, for example, one wouldn't feel confident in one's knowledge of the species.[11][12][13] Similarly, knowledge of what use an animal makes of a feature is crucial to understanding it (for example, that birds use wings for flight).[14] Aristotle did not believe nature is endowed with the same rational purpose and direction as human activity and artifacts.[11] However, he did believe that the adult form is present in the offspring, having been copied from the parent,[13] and that the parts of an organism are good for their purpose.[15][16][17] He maintained that by an imperfect but compelling analogy, one could almost say they're purpose built to suit their essential function.[11][18] Furthermore, knowledge of that function or end-purpose is essential because any other aitia, or explanations one could offer for the organ, would be tremendously informed given the telos.[11]

In his Metaphysics, Aristotle addressed the existence of gods. Rather than envisioning an Artificer as Plato did, he believed that the eternal cosmos required no creation.[13] Aristotle argued for the existence of one or more unmoved movers to serve as nature's role models and constant inspiration (see Prime Mover and Daimon).[12][13][19] Aristotle described the movers as immaterial "active intellects", incapable of perceiving or interacting with the cosmos, thus assuredly "unmoved". To the extent permitted by the vagrancies of matter, he believed the natural pleroma is exerting its full potential, because it has had an eternity in which to do so.[13] This is not to imply a naïve, panglossian idealism, but a logically valid argument from a natural scientist who took a great deal of interest in efficient causal analyses.[11] As a more unsettled account of the species, he briefly recounted survival of the fittest,[20][21] well known even in Aristotle's time.[11][22][23] It would have been infinitely long ago, he argued, and thus would have remained effectively unchanged for an infinitely long duration.[24] Conceding that monstrosities come about by chance,[25][26] he disagrees with those who, like Democritus, ascribe all nature purely to chance[27] because he believes science can only provide a general account of that which is normal, "always, or for the most part".[28]

Marcus Tullius Cicero

Cicero (c. 106 – c. 43 BC) presented an early teleological argument in De Natura Deorum (On the Nature of the Gods), arguing that divine power can be found in reason, which exists throughout nature. He developed an early version of the watchmaker analogy, which was later developed by William Paley.

"When you see a sundial or a water-clock, you see that it tells the time by design and not by chance. How then can you imagine that the universe as a whole is devoid of purpose and intelligence, when it embraces everything, including these artifacts themselves and their artificers?"

— Cicero, De Natura Deorum, ii. 34[29]

As an appeal to general revelation, Paul the Apostle (AD 5-67), argues in Romans 1:18-20, that because it has been made plain to all from what has been created in the world, it is obvious that there is a God.

Marcus Minucius Felix (c. late 2nd to 3rd century), an Early Christian writer, argued for the existence of God based on the analogy of an ordered house in his The Orders of Minucius Felix.[30]

Augustine of Hippo (AD 354–430) presented a classic teleological perspective in his work City of God. He describes the "city of man" and essentially posits that God's plan is to replace the city of man with the city of God (at some as-yet-unknown point in the future). Whether this is to happen gradually or suddenly is not made clear in Augustine's work. He did not, however, make a formal argument for the existence of God; rather, God's existence is already presumed and Augustine is giving a proposed view of God's teleology. Augustine's perspective follows from and is built upon the neo-Platonic views of his era, which in turn have their original roots in Plato's cosmogony.

Averroes

Averroes (Ibn Rushd) introduced teleological arguments into his interpretations of Aristotle from an Islamic perspective in Moorish Spain in the latter half of the 12th Century. His work was highly controversial, officially banned in both Christendom and Islamic Spain.[31] Averroes' teleological arguments can be characterized as presuming one god.[32] He proposes that order and continual motion in the world is caused by God's intellect. In knowing all forms and patterns, God provides order to the Lesser Intelligences.[33]

Aquinas

The fifth of Thomas Aquinas' proofs of God's existence was based on teleology

Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274) presented a form of the teleological argument in his Summa Theologica. In his work, Aquinas presented five ways in which he attempted to prove the existence of God, the quinque viae. These arguments feature only a posteriori arguments, rather than traditional dogma.[34] He sums up his teleological argument as follows.

The fifth way is taken from the governance of the world. We see that things which lack knowledge, such as natural bodies, act for an end, and this is evident from their acting always, or nearly always, in the same way, so as to obtain the best result. Hence it is plain that they achieve their end, not fortuitously, but designedly. Now whatever lacks knowledge cannot move towards an end, unless it be directed by some being endowed with knowledge and intelligence; as the arrow is directed by the archer. Therefore, some intelligent being exists by whom all natural things are directed to their end; and this being we call God.

— St Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica: Article 3, Question 2[35]

Aquinas notes that the existence of final causes, by which a cause is directed toward an effect, can only be explained by an appeal to intelligence. However, as natural bodies aside from humans do not possess intelligence, there must, he reasons, exist a being that directs final causes at every moment. That being is what we call God.[35]

British empiricists

The 17th-century Dutch writers Lessius and Grotius argued that the intricate structure of the world, like that of a house, was unlikely to have arisen by chance.[36] The empiricist John Locke, writing in the late 17th century, developed the Aristotelian idea that, excluding geometry, all science must attain its knowledge a posteriori - through sensual experience.[37] In response to Locke, Anglican Irish Bishop George Berkeley advanced a form of idealism in which things only continue to exist when they are perceived.[38] When humans do not perceive objects, they continue to exist because God is perceiving them. Therefore, in order for objects to remain in existence, God must exist omnipresently.[39]

David Hume, in the mid-18th century, presented arguments both for and against the teleological argument in his Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. The character Cleanthes, summarizing the teleological argument, likens the universe to a man-made machine, and concludes by the principle of similar effects and similar causes that it must have a designing intelligence. Philo is not satisfied with the teleological argument, however. He attempts a number of refutations, including one that arguably foreshadows Darwin's theory, and makes the point that if God resembles a human designer, then assuming divine characteristics such as omnipotence and omniscience is not justified. He goes on to joke that far from being the perfect creation of a perfect designer, this universe may be "only the first rude essay of some infant deity... the object of derision to his superiors".[40]

Look round the world: contemplate the whole and every part of it: You will find it to be nothing but one great-machine, subdivided into an infinite number of lesser machines, which again admit of subdivisions to a degree beyond what human senses and faculties can trace and explain. All these various machines, and even their most minute parts, are adjusted to each other with an accuracy, which ravishes into admiration all men who have ever contemplated them. The curious adapting of means to ends, throughout all nature, resembles exactly, though it much exceeds, the productions of human contrivance; of human design, thought, wisdom, and intelligence. Since therefore the effects resemble each other, we are led to infer, by all the rules of analogy, that the causes also resemble; and that the Author of Nature is somewhat similar to the mind of man; though possessed of much larger faculties, proportioned to the grandeur of the work which he has executed. By this argument a posteriori, and by this argument alone, do we prove at once the existence of a Deity, and his similarity to human mind and intelligence.[40]

— David Hume, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion

Watchmaker analogy

William Paley's "watchmaker analogy" is one of the most famous teleological arguments

The watchmaker analogy, framing the argument with reference to a timepiece, dates back to Cicero, who used the example of a sundial or water-clock in his reasoning that the presence of order and purpose signify the existence of a designer. It was also used by Robert Hooke[41] and Voltaire, the latter of whom remarked: "L'univers m'embarrasse, et je ne puis songer Que cette horloge existe, et n'ait point d'horloger";[42] "I'm puzzled by the world; I cannot dream The timepiece real, its maker but a dream".[43]

William Paley presented the watchmaker analogy in his Natural Theology (1802).[44]

[S]uppose I found a watch upon the ground, and it should be inquired how the watch happened to be in that place, I should hardly think … that, for anything I knew, the watch might have always been there. Yet why should not this answer serve for the watch as well as for [a] stone [that happened to be lying on the ground]?… For this reason, and for no other; namely, that, if the different parts had been differently shaped from what they are, if a different size from what they are, or placed after any other manner, or in any order than that in which they are placed, either no motion at all would have been carried on in the machine, or none which would have answered the use that is now served by it.

— William Paley, Natural Theology[45]

Paley wrote in response to Hume's objection to analogy between artefacts and worlds, choosing to use the example of a watch as a reliable indicator of divine design. He identifies two features of a watch which demonstrate that it is designed. First, a watch performs a valuable purpose, timekeeping, which a designer would find useful; secondly, the watch would be unable to perform such a purpose if its parts were any different, or arranged in any other way. Paley argued that the world of nature displays more functional complexity than that found in the watch. As the adaptation found in natural organisms seems to be both complex and achieves a purpose, Paley reasons that this must be evidence of divine design.

Natural theology strongly influenced British science, with the expectation as expressed by Adam Sedgwick in 1831 that truths revealed by science could not conflict with the moral truths of religion.[46] These natural philosophers saw God as the first cause, and sought secondary causes to explain design in nature: the leading figure Sir John Herschel wrote in 1836 that by analogy with other intermediate causes "the origination of fresh species, could it ever come under our cognizance, would be found to be a natural in contradistinction to a miraculous process".[47]

As a theology student, Charles Darwin found Paley's arguments compelling. However, he later developed his theory of evolution in his 1859 book On the Origin of Species, which offers an alternate explanation of biological order. In his autobiography, Darwin wrote that "The old argument of design in nature, as given by Paley, which formerly seemed to me so conclusive, fails, now that the law of natural selection has been discovered".[48] Darwin struggled with the problem of evil of suffering in nature, but remained inclined to believe that nature depended upon "designed laws" and commended Asa Gray for pointing out that Darwin's work supported teleology.[49]

Fine-tuned Universe

A modern variation of the teleological argument is built upon the concept of the fine-tuned Universe: According to the website Biologos: "Fine-tuning refers to the surprising precision of nature’s physical constants, and the beginning state of the Universe. To explain the present state of the universe, even the best scientific theories require that the physical constants of nature and the beginning state of the Universe have extremely precise values."[50] Also, the fine-tuning of the Universe is the apparent delicate balance of conditions necessary for human life. In this view, speculation about a vast range of possible conditions in which life cannot exist is used to explore the probability of conditions in which life can and does exist.[note 1] In terms of a teleological argument, the intuition in relation to a fine-tuned universe would be that God must have been responsible, if achieving such perfect conditions is so improbable.[45][50] However, in regard to fine-tuning, Kenneth Himma writes: "The mere fact that it is enormously improbable that an event occurred... by itself, gives us no reason to think that it occurred by design… As intuitively tempting as it may be...”[45] Himma attributes the “Argument from Suspicious Improbabilities”, a formalization of “the fine-tuning intuition” to George N. Schlesinger:

To understand Schlesinger’s argument, consider your reaction to two different events. If John wins a 1-in-1,000,000,000 lottery game, you would not immediately be tempted to think that John (or someone acting on his behalf) cheated. If, however, John won three consecutive 1-in-1,000 lotteries, you would immediately be tempted to think that John (or someone acting on his behalf) cheated. Schlesinger believes that the intuitive reaction to these two scenarios is epistemically justified. The structure of the latter event is such that it… justifies a belief that intelligent design is the cause… Despite the fact that the probability of winning three consecutive 1-in-1,000 games is exactly the same as the probability of winning one 1-in-1,000,000,000 game, the former event… warrants an inference of intelligent design.

Himma considers Schlesinger’s argument to be subject to the same vulnerabilities he noted in other versions of the design argument:

While Schlesinger is undoubtedly correct in thinking that we are justified in suspecting design in the case [of winning] three consecutive lotteries, it is because—and only because—we know two related empirical facts about such events. First, we already know that there exist intelligent agents who have the right motivations and causal abilities to deliberately bring about such events. Second, we know from past experience with such events that they are usually explained by the deliberate agency of one or more of these agents. Without at least one of these two pieces of information, we are not obviously justified in seeing design in such cases… [T]he problem for the fine-tuning argument is that we lack both of the pieces that are needed to justify an inference of design. First, the very point of the argument is to establish the fact that there exists an intelligent agency that has the right causal abilities and motivations to bring the existence of a universe capable of sustaining life. Second, and more obviously, we do not have any past experience with the genesis of worlds and are hence not in a position to know whether the existence of fine-tuned universes are usually explained by the deliberate agency of some intelligent agency. Because we lack this essential background information, we are not justified in inferring that there exists an intelligent Deity who deliberately created a universe capable of sustaining life.[45]

Antony Flew, who spent most of his life as an atheist, converted to deism late in life because of the anthropic principle.[51] He concluded that the fine-tuning of the universe was too precise to be the result of chance, so accepted the existence of God. He said that his commitment to "go where the evidence leads" meant that he ended up accepting the existence of God.[52] Flew proposed the view, held earlier by Fred Hoyle, that the universe is too young for life to have developed purely by chance and that, therefore, an intelligent being must exist which was involved in designing the conditions required for life to evolve.[51]

Would you not say to yourself, “Some super-calculating intellect must have designed the properties of the carbon atom, otherwise the chance of my finding such an atom through the blind forces of nature would be utterly minuscule.” Of course you would… A common sense interpretation of the facts suggests that a superintellect has monkeyed with physics, as well as with chemistry and biology, and that there are no blind forces worth speaking about in nature. The numbers one calculates from the facts seem to me so overwhelming as to put this conclusion almost beyond question.[53]

— Fred Hoyle, Engineering and Science, The Universe: Past and Present Reflections

Creation Science and intelligent design

A version of the argument from design is central to both creation science and Intelligent design,[6] but unlike Paley's openness to deistic design through God given laws, they seek scientific confirmation of repeated miraculous interventions in the history of life, and argue that their theistic science should be taught in science classrooms.[7]

Teaching of evolution was effectively barred from United States public school curricula by the outcome of the 1925 Scopes Trial, but in the 1960s the National Defense Education Act led to Biological Sciences Curriculum Study reintroducing teaching of evolution. In response, there was a resurgence of creationism which was presented as "creation science", based on biblical literalism but with Bible quotes optional. A 1989 survey found that virtually all literature promoting creation science presented the design argument, with John D. Morris saying "any living thing gives such strong evidence for design by an intelligent designer that only a willful ignorance of the data (II Peter 3:5) could lead one to assign such intricacy to chance." Such publications introduced concepts central to intelligent design, including irreducible complexity (a variant of the watchmaker analogy) and specified complexity (closely resembling a fine-tuning argument). The United States Supreme Court Edwards v. Aguillard ruling barred the teaching of "Creation Science" in public schools as breaching the separation of church and state, and a group of creationists rebranded Creation Science as "intelligent design" which was presented as a scientific theory rather than as a religious argument.[6]

Scientists disagreed with the assertion that intelligent design is scientific, and its introduction into the science curriculum of a Pennsylvania school district led to the 2005 Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District trial, which ruled that the "intelligent design" arguments are essentially religious in nature and not science.[54] The court took evidence from theologian John F. Haught and ruled that "ID is not a new scientific argument, but is rather an old religious argument for the existence of God. He traced this argument back to at least Thomas Aquinas in the 13th century, who framed the argument as a syllogism: Wherever complex design exists, there must have been a designer; nature is complex; therefore nature must have had an intelligent designer." "This argument for the existence of God was advanced early in the 19th century by Reverend Paley" "The only apparent difference between the argument made by Paley and the argument for ID, as expressed by defense expert witnesses Behe and Minnich, is that ID's 'official position' does not acknowledge that the designer is God."[55]

Proponents of the intelligent design movement such as Cornelius G. Hunter, have asserted that the methodological naturalism upon which science is based is religious in nature.[56] They commonly refer to it as 'scientific materialism' or as 'methodological materialism' and conflate it with 'metaphysical naturalism'.[57] They use this assertion to support their claim that modern science is atheistic, and contrast it with their preferred approach of a revived natural philosophy which welcomes supernatural explanations for natural phenomena and supports theistic science. This ignores the distinction between science and religion, established in Ancient Greece, in which science can not use supernatural explanations.[54]

Intelligent design advocate Michael Behe proposed a development of Paley's watch analogy in which he argued in favour of intelligent design. Unlike Paley, Behe only attempts to prove the existence of an intelligent designer, rather than the God of classical theism. Behe uses the analogy of a mousetrap to propose irreducible complexity: he argues that if a mousetrap loses just one of its parts, it can no longer function as a mousetrap. He argues that irreducible complexity in an object guarantees the presence of intelligent design. Behe claims that there are instances of irreducible complexity in the natural world and that parts of the world must have been designed.[58] This negative argument against step by step evolution ignores longstanding evidence that evolution proceeds through changes of function from preceding systems. The specific examples Behe proposes have been shown to have simpler homologues which could act as precursors with different functions. His arguments have been rebutted, both in general and in specific cases by numerous scientific papers. In response, Behe has only been able to present unsupported assertions of improbability, or argue that the explanations lack detail despite having given no detail in his own claim.[6]

Modern developments

University of Chicago geneticist James A. Shapiro, writing in the Boston Review, states that advancements in microbiology, molecular biology and genetics, in so far as they overlap with information science, introduces hard science with implications for the teleological argument. Genome reorganization is a biological process discovered by Nobel Laureate Barbara McClintock. Shapiro states that these natural genetic engineering systems can produce radical reorganizations of the 'genetic apparatus within a single cell generation'. One protozoa called Oxytricha in response to stress, is capable of splitting its chromosomes into thousands of pieces which are then reassembled into a 'distinct kind of functional genome'.[59] Shapiro suggests what he calls a 'Third Way'; a non-creationist, non-Darwinian type of evolution:

What significance does an emerging interface between biology and information science hold for thinking about evolution? It opens up the possibility of addressing scientifically rather than ideologically the central issue so hotly contested by fundamentalists on both sides of the Creationist-Darwinist debate: Is there any guiding intelligence at work in the origin of species displaying exquisite adaptations…" [59]

Criticism

David Hume

David Hume outlined his criticisms of the teleological argument in his Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion.

David Hume presented a criticism of the teleological argument in his Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. The character Philo, a religious sceptic, voices Hume's criticisms of the argument. He argues that the design argument is built upon a faulty analogy as, unlike with man-made objects, we have not witnessed the design of a universe, so do not know whether the universe was the result of design. Moreover, the size of the universe makes the analogy problematic: although our experience of the universe is of order, there may be chaos in other parts of the universe.[60] Philo argues:

A very small part of this great system, during a very short time, is very imperfectly discovered to us; and do we thence pronounce decisively concerning the origin of the whole?

— David Hume, Dialogues 2[60]

Philo also proposes that the order in nature may be due to nature alone. If nature contains a principle of order within it, the need for a designer is removed. Philo argues that even if the universe is indeed designed, it is unreasonable to justify the conclusion that the designer must be an omnipotent, omniscient, benevolent God - the God of classical theism.[60] It is impossible, he argues, to infer the perfect nature of a creator from the nature of its creation. Philo argues that the designer may have been defective or otherwise imperfect, suggesting that the universe may have been a poor first attempt at design.[61] Hume also pointed out that the argument does not necessarily lead to the existence of one God: “why may not several deities combine in contriving and framing the world?” (p. 108).[40]

Wesley C. Salmon developed Hume's insights, arguing that all things in the universe which exhibit order are, to our knowledge, created by material, imperfect, finite beings or forces. He also argued that there are no known instances of an immaterial, perfect, infinite being creating anything. Using the probability calculus of Bayes Theorem, Salmon concludes that it is very improbable that the universe was created by the type of intelligent being theists argue for.[62]

Nancy Cartwright accuses Salmon of begging the question. One piece of evidence he uses in his probabilistic argument - that atoms and molecules are not caused by design - is equivalent to the conclusion he draws, that the universe is probably not caused by design. The atoms and molecules are what the universe is made up of and whose origins are at issue. Therefore, they cannot be used as evidence against the theistic conclusion.[63]

Complexity does not imply design

The teleological argument assumes that one can infer the existence of intelligent design merely by examination, and because life is reminiscent of something a human might design, it too must have been designed. Life is described as "orderly" or "ordered", as well as other natural products of physical processes, such as diamonds and snowflakes. It is argued, however, that the presence of this kind of natural physical process is also evidence for a designer, and that these particular systems are repetitive in nature and less complex than a non-repetitive system like DNA.[citation needed]

The design claim is often challenged as an argument from ignorance, since it is often unexplained or unsupported, or explained by conjecture.[citation needed] Supporters of design suggest that natural objects and man-made objects have similar properties, therefore both must be designed. However, different objects can have similar properties for different reasons, such as stars and light bulbs. Proponents must therefore demonstrate that only design can cause one or more orderly systems.[citation needed]

Most professional biologists support the modern evolutionary synthesis, not merely as an alternative explanation for the complexity of life but a better explanation with more supporting evidence. Living organisms obey the same physical laws as inanimate objects. Over very long periods of time self-replicating structures arose and later formed DNA.

Does not prove the existence of God

Voltaire argued that, at best, the teleological argument could only indicate the existence of a powerful, but not necessarily all-powerful or all-knowing, intelligence.

In his Traité de métaphysique Voltaire observed that, even if the argument from design could prove the existence of a powerful intelligent designer, it would not prove that this designer is God.[64]

... from this sole argument I cannot conclude anything further than that it is probable that an intelligent and superior being has skillfully prepared and fashioned the matter. I cannot conclude from that alone that this being has made matter out of nothing and that he is infinite in every sense.

— Voltaire, Traité de métaphysique[64]

Søren Kierkegaard questioned the existence of God, rejecting all rational arguments for God's existence (including the teleological argument) on the grounds that reason is inevitably accompanied by doubt.[65] He proposed that the argument from design does not take into consideration future events which may serve to undermine the proof of God's existence: the argument would never finish proving God's existence.[66] In the Philosophical Fragments, Kierkegaard writes:

The works of God are such that only God can perform them. Just so, but where then are the works of the God? The works from which I would deduce his existence are not directly and immediately given. The wisdom in nature, the goodness, the wisdom in the governance of the world -- are all these manifest, perhaps, upon the very face of things? Are we not here confronted with the most terrible temptations to doubt, and is it not impossible finally to dispose of all these doubts? But from such an order of things I will surely not attempt to prove God's existence; and even if I began I would never finish, and would in addition have to live constantly in suspense, lest something so terrible should suddenly happen that my bit of proof would be demolished.

— Søren Kierkegaard, Philosophical Fragments[66]

Argument from improbability

Richard Dawkins is harshly critical of theology, creation and intelligent design in his book The God Delusion in which he contends that an appeal to intelligent design can provide no explanation for biology because it not only begs the question of the designer's own origin; but an intelligent designer must itself be far more complex and difficult to explain than anything it is capable of designing.[67] He believes the chances of life arising on a planet like the Earth are many orders of magnitude less probable than most people would think, but the anthropic principle effectively counters skepticism with regard to improbability. For example, Fred Hoyle suggested that potential for life on Earth was no more probable than a Boeing 747 being assembled by a hurricane from the scrapyard. He argues that a one-time event is subject to improbability but once under way, natural selection itself is nothing like random chance. Furthermore, he refers to his counter argument to the argument from improbability by that same name:[67]

The argument from improbability is the big one. In the traditional guise of the argument from design, it is easily today's most popular argument offered in favour of the existence of God and it is seen, by an amazingly large number of theists, as completely and utterly convincing. It is indeed a very strong and, I suspect, unanswerable argument—but in precisely the opposite direction from the theist's intention. The argument from improbability, properly deployed, comes close to proving that God does not exist. My name for the statistical demonstration that God almost certainly does not exist is the Ultimate Boeing 747 gambit.



The creationist misappropriation of the argument from improbability always takes the same general form, and it doesn't make any difference… [if called] 'intelligent design' (ID). Some observed phenomenon—often a living creature or one of its more complex organs, but it could be anything from a molecule up to the universe itself—is correctly extolled as statistically improbable. Sometimes the language of information theory is used: the Darwinian is challenged to explain the source all the information in living matter, in the technical sense of information content as a measure of improbability or 'surprise value'… However statistically improbable the entity you seek to explain by invoking a designer, the designer himself has got to be at least as improbable. God is the Ultimate Boeing 747.

…The whole argument turns on the familiar question 'Who made God?'… A designer God cannot be used to explain organized complexity because any God capable of designing anything would have to be complex enough to demand the same kind of explanation in his own right. God presents an infinite regress from which he cannot help us to escape. This argument… demonstrates that God, though not technically disprovable, is very very improbable indeed.[67]

— Richard Dawkins, The God Delusion

Dawkins considered the argument from improbability to be "much more powerful" than the teleological argument, or argument from design, although he sometimes implies the terms are used interchangeably. He paraphrases St.Thomas' teleological argument as follows: “Things in the world, especially living things, look as though they have been designed. Nothing that we know looks designed unless it is designed. Therefore there must have been a designer, and we call him God.” [67]

George H. Smith, in his book Atheism: The Case Against God, points out what he considers to be a flaw in the argument from design:

Consider the idea that nature itself is the product of design. How could this be demonstrated? Nature… provides the basis of comparison by which we distinguish between designed objects and natural objects. We are able to infer the presence of design only to the extent that the characteristics of an object differ from natural characteristics. Therefore, to claim that nature as a whole was designed is to destroy the basis by which we differentiate between artifacts and natural objects. (p. 268)

Perception of purpose in biology

Richard Dawkins suggests that while biology can at first seem to be purposeful and ordered, upon closer inspection its true function becomes questionable. Dawkins rejects the claim that biology serves any designed function, claiming rather that biology only mimics such purpose. In his book The Blind Watchmaker, Dawkins states that animals are the most complex things in the known universe: “Biology is the study of complicated things that give the appearance of having been designed for a purpose.” He argues that natural selection should suffice as an explanation of biological complexity without recourse to divine provenance.[68]

Proponents of intelligent design creationism, such as William A. Dembski question the philosophical assumptions made by critics with regard to what a designer would or would not do. Dembski claims that such arguments are not merely beyond the purview of science: often they are tacitly or overtly theological while failing to provide a serious analysis of the hypothetical objective's relative merit. Some critics, such as Stephen Jay Gould even suggest that any purported 'cosmic' designer would only design optimally, while at the same time offering numerous biological criticisms to demonstrate that ideal is manifestly untenable. Dembski characterizes both Dawkins' and Gould's argument as a rhetorical straw man.[69] He suggests a principle of constrained optimization more realistically describes the best any designer could hope to achieve:

Not knowing the objectives of the designer, Gould was in no position to say whether the designer proposed a faulty compromise among those objectives… In criticizing design, biologists tend to place a premium on functionalities of individual organisms and see design as optimal to the degree that those individual functionalities are maximized. But higher-order designs of entire ecosystems might require lower-order designs of individual organisms to fall short of maximal function. [69]

— William A. Dembski, The Design Revolution: Answering the Toughest Questions About Intelligent Design

See also

Notes

  1. ^ For example, if the force of the Big Bang explosion had been different by 1/1060 or the strong interaction force was only 5% different, life would be impossible. (Himma, 2009).

References

  1. ^ Himma, Kenneth Einar (2006). "Design Arguments for the Existence of God", in James Fieser and Bradley Dowden, eds., The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, retrieved 8/24/08
  2. ^ Ratzsch, Del, "Teleological Arguments for God's Existence", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2009 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)
  3. ^ Toner, P. (1909). "The Existence of God: The argument from design", in The Catholic Encyclopedia. New York: Robert Appleton Company. Retrieved January 7, 2010.
  4. ^ Grier, Michelle (2012). "Kant's Critique of Metaphysics". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2012 ed.). §5.2 The Other Proofs.
  5. ^ Oxford English Dictionary, meaning 4. of "design".
  6. ^ a b c d e Eugenie C. Scott. Biological design in science classrooms. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. May 15, 2007 [Retrieved 2009-06-02];104(Suppl 1):8669–8676. doi:10.1073/pnas.0701505104. PMID 17494747. PMC 1876445.
  7. ^ a b Attention: This template ({{cite doi}}) is deprecated. To cite the publication identified by doi:10.1042/bj20081534, please use {{cite journal}} (if it was published in a bona fide academic journal, otherwise {{cite report}} with |doi=10.1042/bj20081534 instead. .pdf
  8. ^ Xenophon, Memorabilia I.4.6; Franklin, James (2001). The Science of Conjecture: Evidence and Probability Before Pascal. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. p. 229. ISBN 0-8018-6569-7.
  9. ^ Brickhouse, Thomas; Smith, Nicholas D. (April 21, 2005). "Plato". Internet Encycopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved November 12, 2011.
  10. ^ Hankinson, R. J. (1997). Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought. Oxford University Press. p. 125. ISBN 978-0-19-924656-4.
  11. ^ a b c d e f g Nussbaum, M.C. (1985). Aristotle's de Motu Animalium. Princeton paperbacks. Princeton University Press. p. 60,66,69–70,73–81,94–98,101. ISBN 978-0-691-02035-8. LCCN 77072132.
  12. ^ a b Toulmin, S.E.; Goodfield, J. (1965). The Discovery of Time. Pelican books. University of Chicago Press. pp. 44–45. ISBN 978-0-226-80842-0. LCCN 81071398.
  13. ^ a b c d e Furley, D.J. (1999). From Aristotle to Augustine. History of Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 13–17, 21–26, 28. ISBN 978-0-415-06002-8. LCCN 98008543.
  14. ^ Aristotle. History of Animals. I 2.
  15. ^ Aristotle. History of Animals. I 5.
  16. ^ Lloyd, G.E.R. (1996). Aristotelian Explorations. Cambridge University Press. p. 59. ISBN 978-0-521-55619-4. LCCN lc95050624. ...flying belongs to the ousia [definition] of a bird... the nature of fish, according to the logos of their ousia, [functional definition] is to be swimmers...
  17. ^ Dawkins, Richard (2006). The God Delusion. Houghton Mifflin Co. p. 167. ISBN 978-0-618-68000-9. LCCN 2006015506. The observed fact is that every species, and every organ that has ever been looked at within every species, is good at what it does. The wings of birds, bees and bats are good at flying. Eyes are good at seeing. Leaves are good at photosynthesizing.
  18. ^ Aristotle. Physics. II 7–9.
  19. ^ Burkert, Walter (1985). Greek Religion. Harvard University Press. p. 331. ISBN 978-0-674-36281-9. LCCN 84025209.
  20. ^ Ross, D.; Ackrill, J.L. (2004). Aristotle. Routledge. p. 80. ISBN 978-0-415-32857-9.
  21. ^ Hull, D.L.; Ruse, M. (2007). The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. Cambridge Companions to Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. p. 174. ISBN 978-0-521-61671-3. LCCN 2006025898.
  22. ^ Aristotle. Physics. I 2 (¶15).
  23. ^ Aristotle. Parts of Animals. I 1.
  24. ^ Aristotle. Physics. III 4 (¶9).
  25. ^ Aristotle. Physics. II 8  (¶2).
  26. ^ Aristotle. Physics. II 8  (¶5).
  27. ^ Aristotle. Physics. II 8  (¶8).
  28. ^ Aristotle. Physics. II 8.
  29. ^ M.T.CiceroDe natura Deorum(the nature of the gods),book II,XXIV
  30. ^ Marcus Minucius Felix (2010). The Octavius of Minucius Felix. OrthodoxEbook. pp. 359–361.
  31. ^ Turner, W. (1907)."Averroes" in The Catholic Encyclopedia. New York: Robert Appleton Company.
  32. ^ Johnson, Monte Ransome (2005). Aristotle on teleology. Oxford University Press. pp. 20–21. ISBN 978-0-19-928530-3.
  33. ^ Kogan, Barry S. (1985). Averroes and the metaphysics of causation. SUNY Press. pp. 240–243. ISBN 978-0-88706-063-2.
  34. ^ Davies, Brian (1992). The Thought of Thomas Aquinas. Oxford University Press. p. 30, footnote 30. ISBN 978-0-19-152044-0.
  35. ^ a b Himma, Kenneth Einar (December 23, 2003). "Design Arguments for the Existence of God". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved November 14, 2011.
  36. ^ Franklin, James (2001). The Science of Conjecture: Evidence and Probability Before Pascal. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. pp. 244–5. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/0-8108-6569-7 |0-8108-6569-7 [[Category:Articles with invalid ISBNs]]]]. {{cite book}}: Check |isbn= value: invalid character (help)
  37. ^ Claiborne Chappell, Vere (1994). The Cambridge companion to Locke. Cambridge University Press. pp. 161–164. ISBN 978-0-521-38772-9.
  38. ^ Dicker, Georges (2011). Berkeley's Idealism: A Critical Examination. Oxford University Press. p. 260. ISBN 978-0-19-538146-7.
  39. ^ Downing, Lisa. "George Berkeley". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved November 17, 2011.
  40. ^ a b c Hume, David (1779). Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (The Second ed.). London: s.n. pp. 47–48.
  41. ^ Hooke, Rober (2003). Micrographia. Courier Dover Publications. p. 2. ISBN 978-0-486-49564-4.
  42. ^ Voltaire (s.n., 1772). Les cabales,: oeuvre pacifique. Oxford University. p. 9. ISBN 978-1-165-51896-8. {{cite book}}: Check date values in: |year= (help); Cite has empty unknown parameter: |coauthors= (help)
  43. ^ Harbottle, Thomas Benfield (1908). Dictionary of quotations: French. S. Sonnenschein. p. 101. ISBN 978-1-4212-5720-4. {{cite book}}: Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help)
  44. ^ Paley 1809, p. 1.
  45. ^ a b c d Himma, Kenneth Einar (12 April 2009). "Design Arguments for the Existence of God". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved November 19, 2011.
  46. ^ Browne, E. Janet (1995), Charles Darwin: vol. 1 Voyaging, London: Jonathan Cape, ISBN 1-84413-314-1, p. 129
  47. ^ Wyhe, John van. (2007) Mind the gap: Did Darwin avoid publishing his theory for many years?. Notes and Records of the Royal Society 61: 177-205. p. 197
    Babbage, Charles (1838) The Ninth Bridgewater Treatise. 2nd edn. London: John Murray. pp. 225–227
  48. ^ Darwin 1958, pp. 59, 87.
  49. ^ Miles, Sara Joan, Charles Darwin and Asa Gray Discuss Teleology and Design, PSCF (2001) 53: 196-201.
  50. ^ a b http://biologos.org/questions/fine-tuning
  51. ^ a b Allen, Diogenes (2010). Theology for a Troubled Believer: An Introduction to the Christian Faith. Westminster John Knox Press. p. 42. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/780664223229 |780664223229 [[Category:Articles with invalid ISBNs]]]]. {{cite book}}: Check |isbn= value: invalid character (help)
  52. ^ D'Souza, Dinesh (2007). What's so great about Christianity. Regnery. pp. 132–3. ISBN 978-1-59698-517-9.
  53. ^ Hoyle, Fred (1981). "The Universe: Past and Present Reflections". Engineering and Science: 8–12. {{cite journal}}: Unknown parameter |month= ignored (help)
  54. ^ a b Pigliucci, Massimo (2010). Nonsense on Stilts: How to Tell Science from Bunk. University of Chicago Press. p. 177. ISBN 978-0-226-66786-7. LCCN 2009049778. [E]ven back in Aristotle's time, a fundamental assumption of doing things scientifically is that the supernatural is out: no explanations that invoke non-natural causes are allowed.
  55. ^ Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District, 04 cv 2688 (December 20, 2005)., Ruling, p. 24.
  56. ^ . "Science's Blind Spot: The Unseen Religion of Scientific Naturalism". Grand Rapids, MI: Brazos Press, (2007)
  57. ^ Methodological Naturalism and Philosophical Naturalism: Clarifying the Connection (2000), Barbara Forrest, Retrieved 2007-05-20.
  58. ^ Oppy, Graham (2006). Arguing About Gods. Cambridge University Press. pp. 187–189. ISBN 978-0-521-86386-5.
  59. ^ a b Shapiro, James, The Third Way, http://www.bostonreview.net/BR22.1/shapiro.html
  60. ^ a b c Fiesar, James (June 30, 2011). "David Hume (1711-1776)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved November 24, 2011.
  61. ^ Auerbach, Albert A. (2001). The God Hypothesis and Other Theories of the Universe. Infinity Publishing. pp. 59–60. ISBN 978-0-7414-0245-5.
  62. ^ Wesley C. Salmon, "Religion and Science: A New Look at Hume's Dialogues", Philosophical Studies, 33 (1978), 143-176.
  63. ^ Nancy Cartwright, "Comments on Wesley Salmon's 'Science and Religion'...", Philosophical Studies, 33 (1978), 177-183.
  64. ^ a b Voltaire (1901) [1734]. "On the Existence of God". The Works of Voltaire: The Henriade: Letters and miscellanies. Vol. XXI. trans. William F. Fleming. Werner. pp. 239–240.
  65. ^ Southwell, Gareth (2011-01-06). Words Of Wisdom: Philosophy's Most Important Quotations And Their Meanings. Quercus. ISBN 978-1-78087-092-2.
  66. ^ a b Søren Kierkegaard, Philosophical Fragments (1844).
  67. ^ a b c d Dawkins, Richard (2006). The God Delusion. Houghton Mifflin Co. pp. 103, 136–138, 162–166. ISBN 978-0-618-68000-9. LCCN 2006015506.
  68. ^ Dawkins, Richard (1986). The Blind Watchmaker: Why the Evidence of Evolution Reveals a Universe without Design. Norton. p. 1. ISBN 978-0-393-31570-7. LCCN 96229669.
  69. ^ a b Dembski, William A. (2004). The Design Revolution: Answering the Toughest Questions About Intelligent Design. InterVarsity Press. pp. 58–59, 61. ISBN 978-0-8308-3216-3. LCCN 2003020589.

Further reading

External links

Template:Link GA