Quantum Bayesianism: Difference between revisions
AvalerionV (talk | contribs) m v1.42b - WP:WCW project (Link equal to linktext) |
Sayantan m (talk | contribs) mNo edit summary |
||
Line 98: | Line 98: | ||
*[[Quantum probability]] |
*[[Quantum probability]] |
||
*[[SIC-POVM]] |
*[[SIC-POVM]] |
||
*[[Statistical inference]]{{div col end |
*[[Statistical inference]]{{div col end}} |
||
== References == |
== References == |
||
{{Reflist|2}} |
{{Reflist|2}} |
||
Line 114: | Line 113: | ||
* [https://web.archive.org/web/20090511060206/http://www.uni-konstanz.de/ppm/events/bbqw2005/ Being Bayesian in a Quantum World] – 2005 conference at the [[University of Konstanz]] |
* [https://web.archive.org/web/20090511060206/http://www.uni-konstanz.de/ppm/events/bbqw2005/ Being Bayesian in a Quantum World] – 2005 conference at the [[University of Konstanz]] |
||
{{Quantum mechanics topics|state=expanded}} |
{{Quantum mechanics topics|state=expanded}}{{Quantum information}} |
||
__NOEDITSECTION__ |
__NOEDITSECTION__ |
||
__INDEX__ |
__INDEX__ |
||
__NEWSECTIONLINK__ |
|||
__NONEWSECTIONLINK__ |
|||
[[Category:Interpretations of quantum mechanics]] |
[[Category:Interpretations of quantum mechanics]] |
Revision as of 04:32, 30 April 2017
In physics and the philosophy of physics, quantum Bayesianism (often written Quantum Bayesianism) usually refers to an interpretation of quantum mechanics also known as QBism. This interpretation takes an agent's actions and experiences as the central concerns of the theory and uses a subjective Bayesian account of probabilities to understand the Born rule as a normative addition to good decision-making. Rooted in the prior work of Carlton Caves, Christopher Fuchs, and Rüdiger Schack during the early 2000s, QBism itself is primarily associated with Fuchs and Schack and has more recently been adopted by David Mermin.[1] QBism draws from the fields of quantum information and Bayesian probability and aims to eliminate the interpretational conundrums that have beset quantum theory. The QBist interpretation is historically derivative of the views of the various physicists that are often grouped together as "the" Copenhagen interpretation,[2][3] but is itself distinct from them.[3][4] Theodor Hänsch has characterized QBism as sharpening those older views and making them more consistent.[5]
The term "quantum Bayesianism" may sometimes refer more generically to the use of a Bayesian or personalist (aka "subjective") treatment of the probabilities that appear in quantum theory. QBism, in particular, has been referred to as "the radical Bayesian interpretation".[6]
QBism deals with common questions in the interpretation of quantum theory about the nature of wavefunction superposition, quantum measurement, and entanglement.[7][8][9] It attempts, on a philosophical level, to provide an understanding of quantum theory, and on a more technical level, to derive as much of quantum theory from informational considerations as possible. According to QBism, many, but not all, aspects of the quantum formalism are subjective in nature. For example, in this interpretation, a quantum state is not an element of reality—instead it represents the degrees of belief an agent has in the outcomes of measurements. For this reason, some philosophers of science have deemed QBism a form of anti-realism.[10][11] The originators of the interpretation disagree with this characterization, proposing instead that the theory more properly aligns with a kind of realism they call "participatory realism", wherein reality consists of more than can be captured by any putative third-person account of it.[12][13][14]
In addition to presenting an interpretation of the existing mathematical structure of quantum theory, some QBists have advocated a research program of reconstructing quantum theory from basic physical principles whose QBist character is manifest,[15][16][17] as described in the Reconstructing quantum theory section below. The QBist interpretation itself, as described in the Core positions section, however, does not depend on any particular reconstruction.
QBist foundational research stimulated interest in symmetric, informationally-complete, positive operator-valued measures (SIC-POVMs), which now have applications in quantum theory outside of foundational studies[18][19][20][21] and in pure mathematics.[22] Likewise, a quantum version of the de Finetti theorem, introduced by Caves, Fuchs, and Schack (independently reproving a result found using different means by Størmer[23]) to provide a Bayesian understanding of the idea of an "unknown quantum state",[24][25] has found application elsewhere, in topics like quantum key distribution[26] and entanglement detection.[27]
Part of a series of articles about |
Quantum mechanics |
---|
History and development
E. T. Jaynes, a promoter of the use of Bayesian probability in statistical physics, once suggested that quantum theory is "[a] peculiar mixture describing in part realities of Nature, in part incomplete human information about Nature—all scrambled up by Heisenberg and Bohr into an omelette that nobody has seen how to unscramble."[28] QBism developed out of efforts to separate these parts using the tools of quantum information theory and personalist Bayesian probability theory.
There are many interpretations of probability theory. Broadly speaking, these interpretations fall into one of two categories: those which assert that a probability is an objective property of reality and those which assert that a probability is a subjective, mental construct which an agent may use to quantify their ignorance or degree of belief in a proposition. QBism begins by asserting that all probabilities, even those appearing in quantum theory, are most properly viewed as members of the latter category. Specifically, QBism adopts a personalist Bayesian interpretation along the lines of Italian mathematician Bruno de Finetti[29] and English philosopher Frank Ramsey.[20][30][31]
According to QBists, the advantages of adopting this view of probability are twofold. First, it suggests that quantum mechanics can be thought of as a local theory, because the Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen (EPR) criterion of reality[32] can be rejected. The EPR criterion states, "If, without in any way disturbing a system, we can predict with certainty (i.e., with probability equal to unity) the value of a physical quantity, then there exists an element of reality corresponding to that quantity."[32] Arguments that quantum mechanics should be considered a nonlocal theory depend upon this principle, but to a QBist, it is invalid, because a personalist Bayesian considers all probabilities, even those equal to unity, to be degrees of belief.[33][34] Therefore, QBists do not conclude that quantum mechanics is a nonlocal theory, as many (although not all) other interpretations of quantum theory do.[35] Second, for QBists the role of quantum states, such as the wavefunctions of particles, is to efficiently encode probabilities; so quantum states are degrees of belief themselves. If one considers any single measurement that is a minimal, informationally complete POVM, this is especially clear: A quantum state is mathematically equivalent to a single probability distribution, the distribution over the possible outcomes of that measurement.
Fuchs introduced the term "QBism" and outlined the interpretation in more or less its present form in 2010,[36] carrying further and demanding consistency of ideas broached earlier, notably in publications from 2002.[37][38] Several subsequent papers have expanded and elaborated upon these foundations, notably a Reviews of Modern Physics article by Fuchs and Schack;[16] an American Journal of Physics article by Fuchs, Mermin, and Schack;[35] and Enrico Fermi Summer School[39] lecture notes by Fuchs and Stacey.[33]
Prior to the 2010 paper,[36] the term "quantum Bayesianism" was used to describe the developments which have since led to QBism in its present form. (The initial Q in the term "quantum Bayesianism" is capitalized in many sources,[3][15][20][31][35][36][40][41][42] but not all.[7][43][44]) However, as noted above, QBism subscribes to a particular kind of Bayesianism which does not suit everyone who might apply Bayesian reasoning to quantum theory (see, for example, the Other uses of Bayesian probability in quantum physics section below). Consequently, Fuchs chose to call the interpretation "QBism," pronounced "cubism," preserving the Bayesian spirit via the CamelCase in the first two letters, but distancing it from Bayesianism more broadly. As this neologism is a homonym of Cubism the art movement, it has motivated conceptual comparisons between the two.[1][45][46] However, QBism itself was not influenced or motivated by Cubism[47] and has no lineage to a potential connection between Cubist art and Bohr's views on quantum theory.
Core positions
According to QBism, quantum theory is a tool which an agent may use to help manage his or her expectations, more like probability theory than a conventional physical theory.[15] Quantum theory, QBism claims, is fundamentally a guide for decision making which has been shaped by some aspects of physical reality. Chief among the tenets of QBism are the following:
- All probabilities, including those equal to zero or one, are valuations that an agent ascribes to his or her degrees of belief in possible outcomes. As they define and update probabilities, quantum states (density operators), channels (completely positive trace-preserving maps), and measurements (positive operator-valued measures) are also the personal judgements of an agent.
- The Born rule rule is normative, not descriptive or prescriptive. It is a relation to which an agent should strive to adhere in his or her probability and quantum state assignments.
- Quantum measurement outcomes are personal experiences for the agent gambling on them. Different agents may confer and agree upon the consequences of a measurement, but the outcome is the experience each of them individually has.
- A measurement apparatus is conceptually an extension of the agent. It should be considered analogous to a sense organ or prosthetic limb—simultaneously a tool and a part of the individual.
Reception and criticism
Reactions to the QBist interpretation have ranged from enthusiastic[15][45] to strongly negative.[48] Some who have criticized QBism claim that it fails to meet the goal of resolving paradoxes in quantum theory. Bacciagaluppi argues that QBism's treatment of measurement outcomes does not ultimately resolve the issue of nonlocality,[49] and Jaeger finds QBism's supposition that the interpretation of probability is key for the resolution to be unnatural and unconvincing.[6] Norsen[50] has accused QBism of solipsism, and Wallace[51] identifies QBism as an instance of instrumentalism; QBists have argued insistently that these characterizations are misunderstandings, and that QBism is neither solipsist nor instrumentalist.[20] A critical article by Nauenberg[52] in the American Journal of Physics prompted a reply by Fuchs, Mermin, and Schack.[53] Some assert that there may be inconsistencies; for example, Stairs argues that when a probability assignment equals one, it cannot be a degree of belief as QBists say.[54] Further, while also raising concerns about the treatment of probability-one assignments, Timpson suggests that QBism may result in a reduction of explanatory power as compared to other interpretations.[7] Fuchs and Schack replied to these concerns in a later article.[55] Mermin advocated QBism in a 2012 Physics Today article,[8] which prompted considerable discussion. Several further critiques of QBism which arose in response to Mermin's article, and Mermin's replies to these comments, may be found in the Physics Today readers' forum.[56] Section 2 of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry on QBism also contains a summary of objections to the interpretation, and some replies.[43] Others are opposed to QBism on more general philosophical grounds; for example, Mohrhoff criticizes QBism from the standpoint of Kantian philosophy.[57]
Certain authors find QBism internally self-consistent, but do not subscribe to the interpretation.[58][59] (For example, Marchildon finds QBism well-defined in a way that, to him, many-worlds interpretations are not, but he ultimately prefers a Bohmian interpretation.[60]) Similarly, Schlosshauer and Claringbold state that QBism is a consistent interpretation of quantum mechanics, but do not offer a verdict on whether it should be preferred.[61] In addition, some agree with most, but perhaps not all, of the core tenets of QBism; Barnum's position,[62] as well as Appleby's,[63] are examples.
Popularized or semi-popularized media coverage of QBism has appeared in New Scientist,[64][65][66] Scientific American,[67] Nature,[68] Science News,[69] the FQXi Community,[70] the Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung,[46] Quanta Magazine,[29] and Aeon.[71] In addition, Harvard University Press published a popularized treatment of the subject, QBism: The Future of Quantum Physics, in 2016.[15]
Relation to other interpretations
Copenhagen interpretations
The views of many physicists (Bohr, Heisenberg, Rosenfeld, von Weizsäcker, Peres, etc.) are often grouped together as the "Copenhagen interpretation" of quantum mechanics. Several authors have deprecated this terminology, claiming that it is historically misleading and obscures differences between physicists that are as important as their similarities.[72][73][74] QBism shares many characteristics in common with the ideas often labeled as "the Copenhagen interpretation", but the differences are important; to conflate them or to regard QBism as a minor modification of the points of view of Bohr or Heisenberg, for instance, would be a substantial misrepresentation.[4]
QBism takes probabilities to be personal judgments of the individual agent who is using quantum mechanics. This contrasts with older Copenhagen-type views, which hold that probabilities are given by quantum states that are in turn fixed by objective facts about preparation procedures.[75][76] QBism considers a measurement to be any action that an agent takes to elicit a response from the world and the outcome of that measurement to be the experience the world's response induces back on that agent. As a consequence, communication between agents is the only means by which different agents can attempt to compare their internal experiences. Most variants of the Copenhagen interpretation, however, hold that the outcomes of experiments are agent-independent pieces of reality for anyone to access.[4] Although not yet claiming to provide an overt underlying ontology, QBism claims that these points on which it differs from previous Copenhagen-type interpretations resolve the obscurities that many critics have found in the latter, by changing the role that quantum theory plays. Rather than a mechanics of reality, QBism claims that quantum theory is a normative tool which an agent may use to better navigate reality.[33]
Other epistemic interpretations
Approaches to quantum theory, like QBism,[77] which treat quantum states as expressions of information, knowledge, belief, or expectation are called "epistemic" interpretations.[14] These approaches differ from each other in what they consider quantum states to be information or expectations "about", as well as in the technical features of the mathematics they employ. Furthermore, not all authors who advocate views of this type propose an answer to the question of what the information represented in quantum states concerns. In the words of the paper that introduced the Spekkens Toy Model,
if a quantum state is a state of knowledge, and it is not knowledge of local and noncontextual hidden variables, then what is it knowledge about? We do not at present have a good answer to this question. We shall therefore remain completely agnostic about the nature of the reality to which the knowledge represented by quantum states pertains. This is not to say that the question is not important. Rather, we see the epistemic approach as an unfinished project, and this question as the central obstacle to its completion. Nonetheless, we argue that even in the absence of an answer to this question, a case can be made for the epistemic view. The key is that one can hope to identify phenomena that are characteristic of states of incomplete knowledge regardless of what this knowledge is about.[78]
Leifer and Spekkens propose a way of treating quantum probabilities as Bayesian probabilities, thereby considering quantum states as epistemic, which they state is "closely aligned in its philosophical starting point" with QBism.[44] However, they remain deliberately agnostic about what physical properties or entities quantum states are information (or beliefs) about, as opposed to QBism, which offers an answer to that question.[44] Another approach, advocated by Bub and Pitowsky, argues that quantum states are information about propositions within event spaces that form non-Boolean lattices.[79]
Von Neumann's views
R. F. Streater argued that "[t]he first quantum Bayesian was von Neumann," basing that claim on von Neumann's textbook The Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics.[80] Blake Stacey disagrees, arguing that the views expressed in that book on the nature of quantum states and the interpretation of probability are not compatible with QBism, or indeed, with any position that might be called quantum Bayesianism.[31]
Relational quantum mechanics
Comparisons have also been made between QBism and the relational quantum mechanics (RQM) espoused by Carlo Rovelli and others.[20][14][81][82][83] In both QBism and RQM, quantum states are not intrinsic properties of physical systems.[84] Both QBism and RQM deny the existence of an absolute, universal wavefunction. Furthermore, both QBism and RQM insist that quantum mechanics is a fundamentally local theory.[35][83] In addition, Rovelli, like several QBist authors, advocates reconstructing quantum theory from physical principles in order to bring clarity to the subject of quantum foundations.[16][17][33][38][85] One important distinction between the two interpretations is their philosophy of probability: RQM does not adopt the Ramsey–de Finetti school of personalist Bayesianism.[20][14] Moreover, RQM does not insist that a measurement outcome is necessarily an agent's experience.[20]
Other uses of Bayesian probability in quantum physics
QBism should be distinguished from other applications of Bayesian inference in quantum physics, and from quantum analogues of Bayesian inference.[16][86] For example, some in the field of computer science have introduced a kind of quantum Bayesian network, which they argue could have applications in "medical diagnosis, monitoring of processes, and genetics".[87][88] Bayesian inference has also been applied in quantum theory for updating probability densities over quantum states,[89] and MaxEnt methods have been used in similar ways.[86][90] Bayesian methods for quantum state and process tomography are an active area of research.[91]
Reconstructing quantum theory
Adherents of several interpretations of quantum mechanics, QBism included, have been motivated to reconstruct quantum theory. The goal of these research efforts has been to identify a new set of axioms or postulates from which the mathematical structure of quantum theory can be derived, in the hope that with such a reformulation, the features of nature which made quantum theory the way it is might be more easily identified.[68][92] Although the core tenets of QBism do not demand such a reconstruction, some QBists—Fuchs,[38] in particular—have argued that the task should be pursued.
The most extensively explored QBist reformulation of quantum theory involves the use of SIC-POVMs to rewrite quantum states (either pure or mixed) as a set of probabilities defined over the outcomes of a "Bureau of Standards" measurement.[20][93][94][95] That is, if one expresses a density matrix as a probability distribution over the outcomes of a SIC-POVM experiment, one can reproduce all the statistical predictions implied by the density matrix from the SIC-POVM probabilities instead. The Born rule then takes the role of relating one valid probability distribution to another, rather than of deriving probabilities from something apparently more fundamental. Fuchs, Schack and others have taken to calling this restatment of the Born rule the urgleichung, from the German for "primal equation" (see Ur- prefix), because of the central role it plays in their reconstruction of quantum theory.[16][96]
The following discussion presumes some familiarity with the mathematics of quantum information theory, and in particular, the modeling of measurement procedures by POVMs. Consider a quantum system to which is associated a -dimensional Hilbert space. If a set of rank-1 projectors satisfyingexists, then one may form a SIC-POVM . An arbitrary quantum state may be written as a linear combination of the SIC projectorswhere is the Born rule probability for obtaining SIC measurement outcome implied by the state assignment . We follow the convention that operators have hats while experiences (that is, measurement outcomes) do not. Now consider an arbitrary quantum measurement, denoted by the POVM . The urgleichung is the expression obtained from forming the Born rule probabilities, , for the outcomes of this quantum measurement, where is the Born rule probability for obtaining outcome implied by the state assignment . The term may be understood to be a conditional probability in a cascaded measurement scenario: Imagine that an agent plans to perform two measurements, first a SIC measurement and then the measurement. After obtaining an outcome from the SIC measurement, the agent will update her state assignment to a new quantum state before performing the second measurement. If she uses the Lüders rule[97] for state update and obtains outcome from the SIC measurement, then . Thus the probability for obtaining outcome for the second measurement conditioned on obtaining outcome for the SIC measurement is .
Note that the urgleichung is structurally very similar to the law of total probability, which is the expressionThey functionally differ only by a dimension-dependent affine transformation of the SIC probability vector. As QBism says that quantum theory is an empirically-motivated normative addition to probability theory, many QBists find the appearance of a structure in quantum theory analogous to one in probability theory to be an indication that a reformulation featuring the urgleichung prominently may help to reveal the properties of nature which made quantum theory so successful.
It is important to recognize that the urgleichung does not replace the law of total probability. Rather, the urgleichung and the law of total probability apply in different scenarios because and refer to different situations. is the probability that an agent assigns for obtaining outcome on her second of two planned measurements, that is, for obtaining outcome after first making the SIC measurement and obtaining one of the outcomes. , on the other hand, is the probability an agent assigns for obtaining outcome when she does not plan to first make the SIC measurement. The law of total probability is a consequence of coherence within the operational context of performing the two measurements as described. The urgleichung, in contrast, is a relation between different contexts which finds its justification in the predictive success of quantum physics.
The SIC representation of quantum states also provides a reformulation of quantum dynamics. Consider a quantum state with SIC representation . The time evolution of this state is found by applying a unitary operator to form the new state , which has the SIC representation
The second equality is written in the Heisenberg picture of quantum dynamics, with respect to which the time evolution of a quantum system is captured by the probabilities associated with a rotated SIC measurement of the original quantum state . Then the Schrödinger equation is completely captured in the urgleichung for this measurement:In these terms, the Schrödinger equation is an instance of the Born rule applied to the passing of time; an agent uses it to relate how she will gamble on informationally complete measurements potentially performed at different times.
Those QBists who find this approach promising are pursuing a complete reconstruction of quantum theory featuring the urgleichung as the key postulate.[96] As of 2017, alternative reconstruction efforts are in the beginning stages.[42]
See also
References
- ^ a b Mermin, N. David (2014-03-27). "Physics: QBism puts the scientist back into science". Nature. 507 (7493): 421–423. doi:10.1038/507421a.
- ^ Tammaro, Elliott (2014-08-09). "Why Current Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics are Deficient". arXiv:1408.2093 [quant-ph].
- ^ a b c Schlosshauer, Maximilian; Kofler, Johannes; Zeilinger, Anton (2013-08-01). "A snapshot of foundational attitudes toward quantum mechanics". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 44 (3): 222–230. arXiv:1301.1069. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2013.04.004.
- ^ a b c Mermin, N. David (2017-01-01). "Why QBism Is Not the Copenhagen Interpretation and What John Bell Might Have Thought of It". In Bertlmann, Reinhold; Zeilinger, Anton (eds.). Quantum [Un]Speakables II. The Frontiers Collection. Springer International Publishing. pp. 83–93. arXiv:1409.2454. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-38987-5_4. ISBN 9783319389851.
- ^ Hänsch, Theodor. "Changing Concepts of Light and Matter". The Pontifical Academy of Sciences. Retrieved 2017-04-18.
{{cite web}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ a b Jaeger, Gregg (2009). "3.7. The radical Bayesian interpretation". Entanglement, information, and the interpretation of quantum mechanics (Online-Ausg. ed.). Berlin: Springer. pp. 170–179. ISBN 978-3-540-92127-1.
- ^ a b c Timpson, Christopher Gordon (2008). "Quantum Bayesianism: A study" (postscript). Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 39 (3): 579–609. arXiv:0804.2047. Bibcode:2008SHPMP..39..579T. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2008.03.006.
- ^ a b Mermin, N. David (2012-07-01). "Commentary: Quantum mechanics: Fixing the shifty split". Physics Today. 65 (7): 8–10. doi:10.1063/PT.3.1618. ISSN 0031-9228.
- ^ Mermin, N. David (2012-11-30). "Measured responses to quantum Bayesianism". Physics Today. 65 (12): 12–15. doi:10.1063/PT.3.1803. ISSN 0031-9228.
- ^ Bub, Jeffrey (2016). Bananaworld: Quantum Mechanics for Primates. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 232. ISBN 978-0198718536.
- ^ Ladyman, James; Ross, Don; Spurrett, David; Collier, John (2007). Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 184. ISBN 9780199573097.
- ^ Fuchs, Christopher A. (2017). "On Participatory Realism". In Durham, Ian T.; Rickles, Dean (eds.). Information and Interaction: Eddington, Wheeler, and the Limits of Knowledge. arXiv:1601.04360. ISBN 9783319437606. OCLC 967844832.
- ^ Fuchs, Christopher A.; Timpson, Christopher G. "Does Participatory Realism Make Sense? The Role of Observership in Quantum Theory". FQXi: Foundational Questions Institute. Retrieved 2017-04-18.
{{cite web}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ a b c d Cabello, Adán (2017). "Interpretations of quantum theory: A map of madness". In Lombardi, Olimpia; Fortin, Sebastian; Holik, Federico; López, Cristian (eds.). What is Quantum Information?. Cambridge University Press. pp. 138–143. arXiv:1509.04711. ISBN 9781107142114.
{{cite book}}
: Unknown parameter|class=
ignored (help) - ^ a b c d e von Baeyer, Hans Christian (2016). QBism: The Future of Quantum Physics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ISBN 067450464X.
- ^ a b c d e Fuchs, Christopher A.; Schack, Ruediger (2013-01-01). "Quantum-Bayesian coherence". Reviews of Modern Physics. 85 (4): 1693–1715. arXiv:1301.3274. Bibcode:2013RvMP...85.1693F. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.85.1693.
- ^ a b Fuchs, Christopher A.; Stacey, Blake C. (2016-01-01). "Some Negative Remarks on Operational Approaches to Quantum Theory". In Chiribella, Giulio; Spekkens, Robert W. (eds.). Quantum Theory: Informational Foundations and Foils. Fundamental Theories of Physics. Springer Netherlands. pp. 283–305. arXiv:1401.7254. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-7303-4_9. ISBN 9789401773027.
- ^ Scott, A. J. (2006-01-01). "Tight informationally complete quantum measurements". Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and General. 39 (43): 13507. arXiv:quant-ph/0604049. Bibcode:2006JPhA...3913507S. doi:10.1088/0305-4470/39/43/009. ISSN 0305-4470.
- ^ Wootters, William K.; Sussman, Daniel M. "Discrete phase space and minimum-uncertainty states - Open Access Library". www.oalib.com. arXiv:0704.1277. Retrieved 2017-03-07.
{{cite journal}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ a b c d e f g h Fuchs, Christopher A.; Schlosshauer, Maximilian; Stacey, Blake C. (2014-05-10). "My Struggles with the Block Universe". arXiv:1405.2390 [quant-ph].
- ^ Appleby, D. M.; Bengtsson, Ingemar; Brierley, Stephen; Grassl, Markus; Gross, David; Larsson, Jan-Åke (2012-05-01). "The Monomial Representations of the Clifford Group". Quantum Info. Comput. 12 (5–6): 404–431. arXiv:1102.1268. Bibcode:2011arXiv1102.1268A. ISSN 1533-7146.
- ^ Appleby, Marcus; Flammia, Steven; McConnell, Gary; Yard, Jon (2017-04-24). "SICs and Algebraic Number Theory". Foundations of Physics: 1–18. arXiv:1701.05200. doi:10.1007/s10701-017-0090-7. ISSN 0015-9018.
- ^ Størmer, E. (1969). "Symmetric states of infinite tensor products of C*-algebras". J. Funct. Anal. 3: 48–68. doi:10.1016/0022-1236(69)90050-0.
- ^ Caves, Carlton M.; Fuchs, Christopher A.; Schack, Ruediger (2002-08-20). "Unknown quantum states: The quantum de Finetti representation". Journal of Mathematical Physics. 43 (9): 4537–4559. arXiv:quant-ph/0104088. Bibcode:2002JMP....43.4537C. doi:10.1063/1.1494475. ISSN 0022-2488.
- ^ J. Baez (2007). "This Week's Finds in Mathematical Physics (Week 251)". Retrieved 2017-04-18.
{{cite web}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ Renner, Renato (2005-12-30). "Security of Quantum Key Distribution". arXiv:quant-ph/0512258.
- ^ Doherty, Andrew C.; Parrilo, Pablo A.; Spedalieri, Federico M. (2005-01-01). "Detecting multipartite entanglement". Physical Review A. 71 (3): 032333. arXiv:quant-ph/0407143. Bibcode:2005PhRvA..71c2333D. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.71.032333.
- ^ Jaynes, E. T. (1990). "Probability in Quantum Theory". In Zurek, W. H. (ed.). Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information. Redwood City, CA: Addison-Wesley. p. 381.
- ^ a b Gefter, Amanda. "A Private View of Quantum Reality". Quanta. Retrieved 2017-04-24.
{{cite news}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ Keynes, John Maynard (2012-01-01). "F. P. Ramsey". Essays in biography. Martino Fine Books. ISBN 161427326X. OCLC 922625832.
- ^ a b c Stacey, Blake C. (2016-05-28). "Von Neumann Was Not a Quantum Bayesian". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences. 374 (2068): 20150235. arXiv:1412.2409. Bibcode:2016RSPTA.37450235S. doi:10.1098/rsta.2015.0235. ISSN 1364-503X.
- ^ a b Fine, Arthur (2016-01-01). "The Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen Argument in Quantum Theory". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2016 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
- ^ a b c d Fuchs, Christopher A.; Stacey, Blake C. (2016-12-21). "QBism: Quantum Theory as a Hero's Handbook". arXiv:1612.07308 [quant-ph].
- ^ The issue of the interpretation of probabilities equal to unity in quantum theory occurs even for probability distributions over a finite number of alternatives, and thus it is distinct from the issue of events that happen almost surely in measure-theoretic treatments of probability.
- ^ a b c d Fuchs, Christopher A.; Mermin, N. David; Schack, Ruediger (2014-07-22). "An introduction to QBism with an application to the locality of quantum mechanics". American Journal of Physics. 82 (8): 749–754. arXiv:1311.5253. Bibcode:2014AmJPh..82..749F. doi:10.1119/1.4874855. ISSN 0002-9505.
- ^ a b c Fuchs, Christopher A. (2010-03-26). "QBism, the Perimeter of Quantum Bayesianism". arXiv:1003.5209 [quant-ph].
- ^ Caves, Carlton M.; Fuchs, Christopher A.; Schack, Ruediger (2002-01-01). "Quantum probabilities as Bayesian probabilities". Physical Review A. 65 (2): 022305. arXiv:quant-ph/0106133. Bibcode:2002PhRvA..65b2305C. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.65.022305.
- ^ a b c C. A. Fuchs, "Quantum Mechanics as Quantum Information (and only a little more),'' in Quantum Theory: Reconsideration of Foundations, edited by A. Khrennikov (Växjö University Press, Växjö, Sweden, 2002), pp. 463–543. arXiv:quant-ph/0205039.
- ^ "International School of Physics "Enrico Fermi"". Italian Physical Society. Retrieved 2017-04-18.
{{cite web}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ Leifer, M. S. (2015-01-01). Aguirre, Anthony; Foster, Brendan; Merali, Zeeya (eds.). It From Bit or Bit From It?. The Frontiers Collection. Springer International Publishing. pp. 5–23. arXiv:1311.0857. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-12946-4_2. ISBN 9783319129457.
{{cite book}}
: Unknown parameter|class=
ignored (help) - ^ Schlosshauer, Maximilian (2011). Elegance and Enigma: The Quantum Interviews. Springer. p. 253. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-20880-5. ISBN 978-3-642-20879-9.
- ^ a b Chiribella, Giulio; Cabello, Adán; Kleinmann, Matthias. "The Observer Observed: a Bayesian Route to the Reconstruction of Quantum Theory". FQXi: Foundational Questions Institute. Retrieved 2017-04-18.
{{cite web}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ a b Healey, Richard (2016). "Quantum-Bayesian and Pragmatist Views of Quantum Theory". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
- ^ a b c Leifer, Matthew S.; Spekkens, Robert W. (2013). "Towards a Formulation of Quantum Theory as a Causally Neutral Theory of Bayesian Inference". Phys. Rev. A. 88 (5): 052130. arXiv:1107.5849. Bibcode:2013PhRvA..88e2130L. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.88.052130.
- ^ a b c Mermin, N. David (2013-01-28). "Annotated Interview with a QBist in the Making". arXiv:1301.6551 [quant-ph].
- ^ a b von Rauchhaupt, Ulf (9 February 2014). "Philosophische Quantenphysik : Ganz im Auge des Betrachters". Frankfurter Allgemeine Sonntagszeitung (in German). Vol. 6. p. 62. Retrieved 2017-04-18.
{{cite news}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ "Q3: Quantum Metaphysics Panel". Vimeo. 13 February 2016. Retrieved 2017-04-18.
{{cite web}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ Motl, Luboš. "Bohr, Heisenberg, Landau wouldn't find QBism new". The Reference Frame. Retrieved 2017-04-18.
{{cite web}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ Bacciagaluppi, Guido (2014-01-01). Galavotti, Maria Carla; Dieks, Dennis; Gonzalez, Wenceslao J.; Hartmann, Stephan; Uebel, Thomas; Weber, Marcel (eds.). A Critic Looks at QBism. The Philosophy of Science in a European Perspective. Springer International Publishing. pp. 403–416. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-04382-1_27. ISBN 9783319043814.
- ^ Norsen, Travis (2014). "Quantum Solipsism and Non-Locality" (PDF). Int. J. Quant. Found. John Bell Workshop.
- ^ Wallace, David (2007-12-03). "The Quantum Measurement Problem: State of Play". arXiv:0712.0149 [quant-ph].
- ^ Nauenberg, Michael (2015-03-01). "Comment on QBism and locality in quantum mechanics". American Journal of Physics. 83 (3): 197–198. arXiv:1502.00123. Bibcode:2015AmJPh..83..197N. doi:10.1119/1.4907264. ISSN 0002-9505.
- ^ Fuchs, Christopher A.; Mermin, N. David; Schack, Ruediger (2015-02-10). "Reading QBism: A Reply to Nauenberg". American Journal of Physics. 83 (3): 198. arXiv:1502.02841. Bibcode:2015AmJPh..83..198F. doi:10.1119/1.4907361.
- ^ Stairs, Allen (2011). "A loose and separate certainty: Caves, Fuchs and Schack on quantum probability one" (pdf). Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 42 (3): 158–166. Bibcode:2011SHPMP..42..158S. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2011.02.001.
- ^ Fuchs, Christopher A.; Schack, Rüdiger (2015-01-01). "QBism and the Greeks: why a quantum state does not represent an element of physical reality". Physica Scripta. 90 (1): 015104. arXiv:1412.4211. Bibcode:2015PhyS...90a5104F. doi:10.1088/0031-8949/90/1/015104. ISSN 1402-4896.
- ^ "Physics Today: Vol 65, No 12". physicstoday.scitation.org. Retrieved 2017-04-09.
- ^ Mohrhoff, Ulrich (2014-09-10). "QBism: A Critical Appraisal". arXiv:1409.3312 [quant-ph].
- ^ Marchildon, Louis (2015-07-01). "Why I am not a QBist". Foundations of Physics. 45 (7): 754–761. arXiv:1403.1146. Bibcode:2015FoPh...45..754M. doi:10.1007/s10701-015-9875-8. ISSN 0015-9018.
- ^ Leifer, Matthew. "Interview with an anti-Quantum zealot". Elliptic Composability. Retrieved 10 March 2017.
{{cite web}}
:|archive-date=
requires|archive-url=
(help); Check date values in:|archive-date=
(help); Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ Marchildon, Louis (2015). "Multiplicity in Everett's interpretation of quantum mechanics". Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 52 (B): 274–284. arXiv:1504.04835. Bibcode:2015SHPMP..52..274M. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.08.010.
- ^ Schlosshauer, Maximilian; Claringbold, Tangereen V. B. (2015). "Entanglement, scaling, and the meaning of the wave function in protective measurement". Protective Measurement and Quantum Reality: Towards a New Understanding of Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge University Press. pp. 180–194. arXiv:1402.1217. doi:10.1017/cbo9781107706927.014.
- ^ Barnum, Howard N. (2010-03-23). "Quantum Knowledge, Quantum Belief, Quantum Reality: Notes of a QBist Fellow Traveler". arXiv:1003.4555 [quant-ph].
- ^ Appleby, D. M. (2007-01-01). "Concerning Dice and Divinity". AIP Conference Proceedings. 889: 30–39. arXiv:quant-ph/0611261. Bibcode:2007AIPC..889...30A. doi:10.1063/1.2713444.
- ^ Chalmers, Matthew (2014-05-07). "QBism: Is quantum uncertainty all in the mind?". New Scientist. Retrieved 2017-04-09.
{{cite news}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ Mermin, N. David (2014-06-05). "QBism in the New Scientist". arXiv:1406.1573 [quant-ph].
- ^ Webb, Richard (2017-11-30). "Physics may be a small but crucial fraction of our reality". New Scientist. Retrieved 2017-04-22.
{{cite news}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ von Baeyer, Hans Christian (2013). "Quantum Weirdness? It's All in Your Mind". Scientific American. 308 (6): 46–51. doi:10.1038/scientificamerican0613-46. PMID 23729070.
- ^ a b Ball, Philip (2013-09-12). "Physics: Quantum quest". Nature. 501 (7466): 154–156. Bibcode:2013Natur.501..154B. doi:10.1038/501154a.
- ^ Siegfried, Tom (2014-01-30). "'QBists' tackle quantum problems by adding a subjective aspect to science". Science News. Retrieved 2017-04-20.
- ^ Waldrop, M. Mitchell. "Painting a QBist Picture of Reality". fqxi.org. Retrieved 2017-04-20.
{{cite web}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ Frank, Adam (2017-03-13). Powell, Corey S. (ed.). "Materialism alone cannot explain the riddle of consciousness". Aeon. Retrieved 2017-04-22.
{{cite news}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ Peres, Asher (2002-03-01). "Karl Popper and the Copenhagen interpretation". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 33 (1): 23–34. arXiv:quant-ph/9910078. Bibcode:2002SHPMP..33...23P. doi:10.1016/S1355-2198(01)00034-X.
- ^ Żukowski, Marek (2017-01-01). "Bell's Theorem Tells Us Not What Quantum Mechanics Is, but What Quantum Mechanics Is Not". In Bertlmann, Reinhold; Zeilinger, Anton (eds.). Quantum [Un]Speakables II. The Frontiers Collection. Springer International Publishing. pp. 175–185. arXiv:1501.05640. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-38987-5_10. ISBN 9783319389851.
- ^ Camilleri, Kristian (2009-02-01). "Constructing the Myth of the Copenhagen Interpretation". Perspectives on Science. 17 (1): 26–57. ISSN 1530-9274.
- ^ Peres, Asher (1984-07-01). "What is a state vector?". American Journal of Physics. 52 (7): 644–650. Bibcode:1984AmJPh..52..644P. doi:10.1119/1.13586. ISSN 0002-9505.
- ^ Caves, Carlton M.; Fuchs, Christopher A.; Schack, Rüdiger (2007-06-01). "Subjective probability and quantum certainty". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. Probabilities in quantum mechanics. 38 (2): 255–274. arXiv:quant-ph/0608190. Bibcode:2007SHPMP..38..255C. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2006.10.007.
- ^ Harrigan, Nicholas; Spekkens, Robert W. (2010-02-01). "Einstein, Incompleteness, and the Epistemic View of Quantum States". Foundations of Physics. 40 (2): 125–157. arXiv:0706.2661. Bibcode:2010FoPh...40..125H. doi:10.1007/s10701-009-9347-0. ISSN 0015-9018.
- ^ Spekkens, Robert W. (2007-01-01). "Evidence for the epistemic view of quantum states: A toy theory". Physical Review A. 75 (3): 032110. arXiv:quant-ph/0401052. Bibcode:2007PhRvA..75c2110S. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.75.032110.
- ^ Bub, Jeffrey; Pitowsky, Itamar (2010-01-01). "Two dogmas about quantum mechanics". In Saunders, Simon; Barrett, Jonathan; Kent, Adrian; Wallace, David (eds.). Many Worlds?: Everett, Quantum Theory & Reality. Oxford University Press. pp. 433–459. arXiv:0712.4258.
- ^ Streater, R. F. (2007). Lost Causes in and beyond Physics. Springer. p. 70. ISBN 3-540-36581-8.
- ^ Brukner, Časlav (2017-01-01). "On the Quantum Measurement Problem". In Bertlmann, Reinhold; Zeilinger, Anton (eds.). Quantum [Un]Speakables II. The Frontiers Collection. Springer International Publishing. pp. 95–117. arXiv:1507.05255. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-38987-5_5. ISBN 9783319389851.
- ^ Marlow, Thomas (2006-03-07). "Relationalism vs. Bayesianism". arXiv:r-qc/0603015.
- ^ a b Smerlak, Matteo; Rovelli, Carlo (2007-02-26). "Relational EPR". Foundations of Physics. 37 (3): 427–445. arXiv:quant-ph/0604064. Bibcode:2007FoPh...37..427S. doi:10.1007/s10701-007-9105-0. ISSN 0015-9018.
- ^ Cabello, Adán; Gu, Mile; Gühne, Otfried; Larsson, Jan-Åke; Wiesner, Karoline (2016-01-01). "Thermodynamical cost of some interpretations of quantum theory". Physical Review A. 94 (5). arXiv:1509.03641. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.94.052127.
- ^ Rovelli, Carlo (1996-08-01). "Relational quantum mechanics". International Journal of Theoretical Physics. 35 (8): 1637–1678. arXiv:quant-ph/9609002. Bibcode:1996IJTP...35.1637R. doi:10.1007/BF02302261. ISSN 0020-7748.
- ^ a b Baez, John (2003-09-12). "Bayesian Probability Theory and Quantum Mechanics". Retrieved 2017-04-18.
{{cite web}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ Tucci, Robert R. (1995-01-30). "Quantum bayesian nets". International Journal of Modern Physics B. 09 (3): 295–337. arXiv:quant-ph/9706039. Bibcode:1995IJMPB...9..295T. doi:10.1142/S0217979295000148. ISSN 0217-9792.
- ^ Moreira, Catarina; Wichert, Andreas (2016). "Quantum-Like Bayesian Networks for Modeling Decision Making". Frontiers in Psychology: Cognition. 7. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2016.00011.
{{cite journal}}
: CS1 maint: unflagged free DOI (link) - ^ Jones, K. R. W. (1991). "Principles of quantum inference". Annals of Physics. 207: 140–170. Bibcode:1991AnPhy.207..140J. doi:10.1016/0003-4916(91)90182-8. Retrieved 2017-03-07.
{{cite journal}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameter:|dead-url=
(help) - ^ Bužek, V.; Derka, R.; Adam, G.; Knight, P. L. (1998). "Reconstruction of Quantum States of Spin Systems: From Quantum Bayesian Inference to Quantum Tomography". Annals of Physics. 266 (2): 454–496. Bibcode:1998AnPhy.266..454B. doi:10.1006/aphy.1998.5802. Retrieved 2017-03-07.
{{cite journal}}
: Cite has empty unknown parameters:|et al=
and|dead-url=
(help) - ^ Granade, Christopher; Combes, Joshua; Cory, D. G. (2016-01-01). "Practical Bayesian tomography". New Journal of Physics. 18 (3): 033024. arXiv:1509.03770. Bibcode:2016NJPh...18c3024G. doi:10.1088/1367-2630/18/3/033024. ISSN 1367-2630.
- ^ Chiribella, Giulio; Spekkens, Rob W. (2016). "Introduction". Quantum Theory: Informational Foundations and Foils. Fundamental Theories of Physics. Vol. 181. Springer. pp. 1–18. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-7303-4. ISBN 978-94-017-7302-7.
- ^ Fuchs, Christopher A.; Schack, Rüdiger (2010-01-08). "A Quantum-Bayesian Route to Quantum-State Space". Foundations of Physics. 41 (3): 345–356. arXiv:0912.4252. Bibcode:2011FoPh...41..345F. doi:10.1007/s10701-009-9404-8. ISSN 0015-9018.
- ^ Appleby, D. M.; Ericsson, Åsa; Fuchs, Christopher A. (2010-04-27). "Properties of QBist State Spaces". Foundations of Physics. 41 (3): 564–579. arXiv:0910.2750. Bibcode:2011FoPh...41..564A. doi:10.1007/s10701-010-9458-7. ISSN 0015-9018.
- ^ Rosado, José Ignacio (2011-01-28). "Representation of Quantum States as Points in a Probability Simplex Associated to a SIC-POVM". Foundations of Physics. 41 (7): 1200–1213. arXiv:1007.0715. Bibcode:2011FoPh...41.1200R. doi:10.1007/s10701-011-9540-9. ISSN 0015-9018.
- ^ a b Appleby, Marcus; Fuchs, Christopher A.; Stacey, Blake C.; Zhu, Huangjun (2016-12-09). "Introducing the Qplex: A Novel Arena for Quantum Theory". arXiv:1612.03234 [quant-ph].
- ^ Busch, Paul; Lahti, Pekka (2009-01-01). "Lüders Rule". In Greenberger, Daniel; Hentschel, Klaus; Weinert, Friedel (eds.). Compendium of Quantum Physics. Springer Berlin Heidelberg. pp. 356–358. doi:10.1007/978-3-540-70626-7_110. ISBN 9783540706229.
External links
- Notes on a Paulian Idea: Foundational, Historical, Anecdotal and Forward-Looking Thoughts on the Quantum – Cerro Grande Fire Series, Volume 1
- My Struggles with the Block Universe – Cerro Grande Fire Series, Volume 2
- Quantum-Bayesian and Pragmatist Views of Quantum Theory – Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy article
- Painting a QBist Picture of Reality – Foundational Questions Institute article
- Why the multiverse is all about you – The Philosopher's Zone interview with Fuchs
- A Private View of Quantum Reality – Quanta Magazine interview with Fuchs
- Rüdiger Schack on quantum Bayesianism – Machine Intelligence Research Institute interview with Schack
- Participatory Realism – 2017 conference at the Stellenbosch Institute for Advanced Study
- Being Bayesian in a Quantum World – 2005 conference at the University of Konstanz