Jump to content

Popular sovereignty: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Undid revision 567559284 by Hendrick 99 (talk) do not change ENGVAR
PBS (talk | contribs)
moved two very large notes into the notes section. To help with readability made the citations at the end of quotes short, removed sources from further reading that are also references
Line 2: Line 2:
{{Liberalism sidebar |Ideas}}
{{Liberalism sidebar |Ideas}}


'''Popular sovereignty''' or the '''sovereignty of the people''' is the principle that the authority of the government is created and sustained by the consent of its people (Rule by the People), who are the source of all political power. It is closely associated with [[republicanism]] and [[social contract]] philosophers such as [[Thomas Hobbes]], [[John Locke]] and [[Jean-Jacques Rousseau]]. Popular sovereignty expresses a concept and does not necessarily reflect or describe a political reality.<ref>Leonard Levy, ed., ''Encyclopedia of the American Constitution'' (Nadthan Tarcov), "Popular Sovereignty (in Democratic Political Theory), vol 3, p. 1426, 1426 (1986) ISBN 978-0-02-864880-4 (Noting of the "doctrine" of popular sovereignty that it "relates primarily not to the Constitution's [actual] operation but to its source of authority and supremacy, ratification, amendment, and possible abolition.")</ref> It is usually contrasted with the concept of [[parliamentary sovereignty]], and with [[individual sovereignty]].
'''Popular sovereignty''' or the '''sovereignty of the people''' is the principle that the authority of the government is created and sustained by the consent of its people (Rule by the People), who are the source of all political power. It is closely associated with [[republicanism]] and [[social contract]] philosophers such as [[Thomas Hobbes]], [[John Locke]] and [[Jean-Jacques Rousseau]]. Popular sovereignty expresses a concept and does not necessarily reflect or describe a political reality.<ref group=lower-alpha>Leonard Levy notes the "doctrine" of popular sovereignty that it "relates primarily not to the Constitution's [actual] operation but to its source of authority and supremacy, ratification, amendment, and possible abolition" (Tarcov 1986, v. 3, p. 1426, 1426).</ref> It is usually contrasted with the concept of [[parliamentary sovereignty]], and with [[individual sovereignty]].


[[Benjamin Franklin]] expressed the concept when he wrote, "In free governments, the rulers are the servants and the people their superiors and sovereigns."<ref>[http://etext.virginia.edu/jefferson/quotations/jeff0300.htm Thomas Jefferson] ah--~~~~'''UVa Library'''</ref>
[[Benjamin Franklin]] expressed the concept when he wrote, "In free governments, the rulers are the servants and the people their superiors and sovereigns".<ref>[http://etext.virginia.edu/jefferson/quotations/jeff0300.htm Thomas Jefferson], '''UVa Library''' {{verification needed|date=July 2013}}</ref>


The term "squatter sovereignty" is used by [[Jefferson Davis]] in his book ''[[A Short History of the Confederate States of America]]''. This term referred to the influx of new citizens in order to manipulate the ultimate sovereign votes. At the 1860 Democratic National Convention, [[William L. Yancey]] used the phrase "squatter sovereignty" in a speech he gave.<ref>p. 250, Democratic Party. National Convention, Charleston and Baltimore, 1860. Proceedings of the Conventions at Charleston and Baltimore. Washington, 9999</ref>
The term "squatter sovereignty" is used by [[Jefferson Davis]] in his book ''[[A Short History of the Confederate States of America]]''. This term referred to the influx of new citizens in order to manipulate the ultimate sovereign votes. At the 1860 Democratic National Convention, [[William L. Yancey]] used the phrase "squatter sovereignty" in a speech he gave.<ref>p. 250, Democratic Party. National Convention, Charleston and Baltimore, 1860. Proceedings of the Conventions at Charleston and Baltimore. Washington, 9999</ref>
Line 19: Line 19:
{{main|Popular sovereignty in the United States}}
{{main|Popular sovereignty in the United States}}


The application of the doctrine of popular sovereignty receives particular emphasis in American history, notes historian Christian G. Fritz's ''American Sovereigns: The People and America's Constitutional Tradition Before the Civil War'', a study of the early history of American constitutionalism.<ref name="Fritz">Christian G. Fritz, [http://books.google.com/books?id=ZpKCvUacmSwC&pg=RA1-PA168&lpg=RA1-PA168&dq=christian+g+fritz+%22american+sovereigns%22&source=web&ots=UjY_WKHNjv&sig=Y2_7OZMg6ksk_866oiD44FArH-w&hl=en#PRA1-PA1,M1 ''American Sovereigns: The People and America's Constitutional Tradition Before the Civil War''] (Cambridge University Press, 2008) at p. 290, 400. ISBN 978-0-521-88188-3</ref> In describing how Americans attempted to apply this doctrine prior to the territorial struggle over slavery that led to the Civil War, political scientist Donald S. Lutz noted the variety of American applications:::
The application of the doctrine of popular sovereignty receives particular emphasis in American history, notes historian Christian G. Fritz's ''American Sovereigns: The People and America's Constitutional Tradition Before the Civil War'', a study of the early history of American constitutionalism.<ref name="Fritz">Christian G. Fritz, [http://books.google.com/books?id=ZpKCvUacmSwC&pg=RA1-PA168&lpg=RA1-PA168&dq=christian+g+fritz+%22american+sovereigns%22&source=web&ots=UjY_WKHNjv&sig=Y2_7OZMg6ksk_866oiD44FArH-w&hl=en#PRA1-PA1,M1 ''American Sovereigns: The People and America's Constitutional Tradition Before the Civil War''] (Cambridge University Press, 2008) at p. 290, 400. ISBN 978-0-521-88188-3</ref> In describing how Americans attempted to apply this doctrine prior to the territorial struggle over slavery that led to the Civil War, political scientist Donald S. Lutz noted the variety of American applications:


{{quote|To speak of popular sovereignty is to place ultimate authority in the people. There are a variety of ways in which sovereignty may be expressed. It may be immediate in the sense that the people make the law themselves, or mediated through representatives who are subject to election and recall; it may be ultimate in the sense that the people have a negative or veto over legislation, or it may be something much less dramatic. In short, popular sovereignty covers a multitude of institutional possibilities. In each case, however, popular sovereignty assumes the existence of some form of popular consent, and it is for this reason that every definition of republican government implies a theory of consent.|<ref>Donald S. Lutz, ''Popular Consent and Popular Control: Whig Political Theory in the Early State Constitutions'' (Louisiana State Univ. Press, 1980) at p. 38 ISBN 978-0-8071-0596-2 Additional support for the centrality of popular sovereignty include: Ronald M. Peters, Jr., ''The Massachusetts Constitution of 1780: A Social Compact'' (Univ. of Massachusetts Press, 1978) at p.1 ISBN 978-0-8071-1506-0 (suggests the following as embodying the meaning of popular sovereignty for Americans – "The concept of popular sovereignty holds simply that in a society organized for political action, the will of the people as a whole is the only right standard of political action."); Donald S. Lutz, ''The Origins of American Constitutionalism'' (Louisiana State Univ. Press, 1988) at p. 10 ISBN 978-0-8071-1506-0 (suggests that popular sovereignty came to have meaning in “the way Americans viewed themselves as a people. They firmly believed that on their own authority they could form themselves into a community, create or replace a government to order their community, select and replace those who hold government office, determine which values bind them as a community and thus which values should guide them those in government when making decisions for the community, and replace political institutions at variance with these values."); Joel H. Silbey, ed., ''Encyclopedia of the American Legislative System'' (3 vols., Charles Scribner's Sons, 1994) Vol. I, p. 37 ISBN 978-0-684-19243-7 (entry for "Constitutional Conventions," states "The justification of the American Revolution and republican government—-as opposed to the monarchical forms of government in Europe—rested on the theory of popular sovereignty. In essence, that theory established the basic premise of American political life: the ultimate and sole legitimacy of government rests on the consent of 'the people.' Defining 'the people' became one of the central issues in the development of the American experience, but soon after declaring independence, American revolutionaries came to agree that popular sovereignty underlay America's republican governments. If identifying 'the people' and their role in changing government took many decades, the problem of how to locate popular sovereignty was solved relatively quickly by the institutional device of the constitutional convention.")</ref>}}
{{quote|To speak of popular sovereignty is to place ultimate authority in the people. There are a variety of ways in which sovereignty may be expressed. It may be immediate in the sense that the people make the law themselves, or mediated through representatives who are subject to election and recall; it may be ultimate in the sense that the people have a negative or veto over legislation, or it may be something much less dramatic. In short, popular sovereignty covers a multitude of institutional possibilities. In each case, however, popular sovereignty assumes the existence of some form of popular consent, and it is for this reason that every definition of republican government implies a theory of consent.|Donald S. Lutz<ref>Lutz 1980, p. 38</ref><ref name=centrality-of-popular-sovereignty group=lower-alpha/>
}}
The American Revolution marked a departure in the concept of popular sovereignty as it had been discussed and employed in the European historical context. With their Revolution, Americans substituted the sovereignty in the person of [[King George III]], with a collective sovereign—composed of the people. Thenceforth, American revolutionaries generally agreed and were committed to the principle that governments were legitimate only if they rested on popular sovereignty – that is, the sovereignty of the people.<ref>Paul K. Conkin, ''Self-Evident Truths: Being a Discourse on the Origins & Development of the First Principles of American Government—Popular Sovereignty, Natural Rights, and Balance & Separation of Powers '' (Indiana Univ. Press, 1974), at p. 52 ISBN 978-0-253-20198-0 (describing "the almost unanimous acceptance of popular sovereignty at the level of abstract principle"); Edmund S. Morgan, "The Problem of Popular Sovereignty," in ''Aspects of American Liberty: Philosophical, Historical and Political'' (The American Philosophical Society, 1977), at p. 101 (concluding the American Revolution "confirmed and completed the subordination of government to the will of the people"); Willi Paul Adams, ''The First American Constitutions: Republican Ideology and the Making of the State Constitutions in the Revolutionary Era'' (University of North Carolina Press, 1980), at p. 137 ISBN 978-0-7425-2069-1 (asserting that statements of the "principle" of the people’s sovereignty "expressed the very heart of the consensus among the victors of 1776").</ref> This idea—often linked with the notion of the consent of the governed—was not invented by the American revolutionaries. Rather, the consent of the governed and the idea of the people as a sovereign had clear 17th and 18th century intellectual roots in English history.<ref>On the English origins of the sovereignty of the people and consent as the basis of government, see John Phillip Reid, ''Constitutional History of the American Revolution'' (4 vols., University of Wisconsin Press, 1986–1993), Vol. III: 97–101, 107–10 ISBN 0-299-13070-3 ; Edmund S. Morgan, ''Inventing the People: The Rise of Popular Sovereignty in England and America'' (W.W. Norton and Company, 1988) ISBN 0-393-30623-2</ref>

The American Revolution marked a departure in the concept of popular sovereignty as it had been discussed and employed in the European historical context. With their Revolution, Americans substituted the sovereignty in the person of [[King George III]], with a collective sovereign—composed of the people. Thenceforth, American revolutionaries generally agreed and were committed to the principle that governments were legitimate only if they rested on popular sovereignty – that is, the sovereignty of the people.<ref name=sovereignty-of-the-people group=lower-alpha/> This idea—often linked with the notion of the consent of the governed—was not invented by the American revolutionaries. Rather, the consent of the governed and the idea of the people as a sovereign had clear 17th and 18th century intellectual roots in English history.<ref>On the English origins of the sovereignty of the people and consent as the basis of government, see: Reid 1986–1993, v. III, pp. 97–101, 107–110; Morgan 1988, {{page needed|date=August 2013}}</ref>


===1850s===
===1850s===
{{main|Origins of the American Civil War|Kansas–Nebraska Act}}
{{main|Origins of the American Civil War|Kansas–Nebraska Act}}
In the 1850s, in the runup to the Civil War, Northern Democrats led by Senator [[Lewis Cass]] of Michigan and [[Stephen A. Douglas]] of Illinois promoted popular sovereignty as a middle position on the slavery issue. It said that actual residents of territories should be able to decide by voting whether or not slavery would be allowed in the territory. The federal government did not have to make the decision, and by appealing to democracy Cass and Douglas hoped they could finesse the question of support for or opposition to slavery. Douglas applied popular sovereignty to Kansas in the [[Kansas Nebraska Act]] which passed Congress in 1854. The Act had two unexpected results. By dropping the Missouri Compromise of 1820 (which said slavery would never be allowed in Kansas), it was a major boost for the expansion of slavery. Overnight outrage united anti-slavery forces across the North into an "anti-Nebraska" movement that soon was institutionalized as the [[History of the Republican Party (United States)|Republican Party]], with its firm commitment to stop the expansion of slavery. Second, pro- and anti-slavery elements moved into Kansas with the intention of voting slavery up or down, leading to a raging civil war, known as "[[Bleeding Kansas]]." Abraham Lincoln targeted popular sovereignty in the Lincoln-Douglas Debates of 1858, leaving Douglas in a position that alienated Southern pro-slavery Democrats who thought he was too weak in his support of slavery. The Southern Democrats broke off and ran their own candidate against Lincoln and Douglas in 1860.<ref>Christopher Childers, "Interpreting Popular Sovereignty: A Historiographical Essay," ''Civil War History,'' March 2011, Vol. 57 Issue 1, pp. 48–70</ref>
In the 1850s, in the runup to the Civil War, Northern Democrats led by Senator [[Lewis Cass]] of Michigan and [[Stephen A. Douglas]] of Illinois promoted popular sovereignty as a middle position on the slavery issue. It said that actual residents of territories should be able to decide by voting whether or not slavery would be allowed in the territory. The federal government did not have to make the decision, and by appealing to democracy Cass and Douglas hoped they could finesse the question of support for or opposition to slavery. Douglas applied popular sovereignty to Kansas in the [[Kansas Nebraska Act]] which passed Congress in 1854. The Act had two unexpected results. By dropping the Missouri Compromise of 1820 (which said slavery would never be allowed in Kansas), it was a major boost for the expansion of slavery. Overnight outrage united anti-slavery forces across the North into an "anti-Nebraska" movement that soon was institutionalized as the [[History of the Republican Party (United States)|Republican Party]], with its firm commitment to stop the expansion of slavery. Second, pro- and anti-slavery elements moved into Kansas with the intention of voting slavery up or down, leading to a raging civil war, known as "[[Bleeding Kansas]]." Abraham Lincoln targeted popular sovereignty in the Lincoln-Douglas Debates of 1858, leaving Douglas in a position that alienated Southern pro-slavery Democrats who thought he was too weak in his support of slavery. The Southern Democrats broke off and ran their own candidate against Lincoln and Douglas in 1860.<ref>Childers 2011, pp. 48–70</ref>


==See also==
==See also==
Line 37: Line 39:
* [[Scottish Constitutional Commission]]
* [[Scottish Constitutional Commission]]
* [[Sovereign Citizen Movement]]
* [[Sovereign Citizen Movement]]

==Further reading==
* Childers, Christopher. "Interpreting Popular Sovereignty: A Historiographical Essay," ''Civil War History'' Volume 57, Number 1, March 2011 pp. 48–70 [http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/civil_war_history/v057/57.1.childers.html in Project MUSE]
* Childers, Christopher. ''The Failure of Popular Sovereignty: Slavery, Manifest Destiny, and the Radicalization of Southern Politics'' (University of Kansas Press, 2012) 334 pp.
* Etcheson, Nicole. "The Great Principle of Self-Government: Popular Sovereignty and Bleeding Kansas," ''Kansas History'' 27 (Spring–Summer 2004): 14–29, links it to [[Jacksonian Democracy]]
* Morgan, Edmund S. ''Inventing the People: The Rise of Popular Sovereignty in England and America'' (1988).
* Johannsen, Robert W. ''Stephen A. Douglas'' (Oxford Univ. Press, 1973), pp. 576–613.


==Notes==
==Notes==
{{reflist}}
{{reflist|group=lower-alpha |refs=
<ref name=centrality-of-popular-sovereignty>Additional support for the centrality of popular sovereignty include:
*Ronald M. Peters, Jr., suggests the following as embodying the meaning of popular sovereignty for Americans – "The concept of popular sovereignty holds simply that in a society organized for political action, the will of the people as a whole is the only right standard of political action" (Peters, Jr. 1978, p. 1}};
*Donald S. Lutz suggests that popular sovereignty came to have meaning in "the way Americans viewed themselves as a people. They firmly believed that on their own authority they could form themselves into a community, create or replace a government to order their community, select and replace those who hold government office, determine which values bind them as a community and thus which values should guide them those in government when making decisions for the community, and replace political institutions at variance with these values" (Lutz 1980, p. 10);
*Joel H. Silbey, states "The justification of the American Revolution and republican government—-as opposed to the monarchical forms of government in Europe—rested on the theory of popular sovereignty. In essence, that theory established the basic premise of American political life: the ultimate and sole legitimacy of government rests on the consent of 'the people.' Defining 'the people' became one of the central issues in the development of the American experience, but soon after declaring independence, American revolutionaries came to agree that popular sovereignty underlay America's republican governments. If identifying 'the people' and their role in changing government took many decades, the problem of how to locate popular sovereignty was solved relatively quickly by the institutional device of the constitutional convention" (Silbey 1994, v. I, p. 37).</ref>

<ref name=sovereignty-of-the-people>
*Paul K. Conkin, describes "the almost unanimous acceptance of popular sovereignty at the level of abstract principle" (Conkin 1974, p. 52);
* Edmund S. Morgan, concludes thatthe American Revolution "confirmed and completed the subordination of government to the will of the people" (Morgan 1977, p. 101);
* Willi Paul Adams asserts that statements of the "principle" of the people’s sovereignty "expressed the very heart of the consensus among the victors of 1776" (Adams 1980, p. 137).</ref>
}}

{{reflist|30em}}

==References==
* Adams, Willi Paul (1980), ''The First American Constitutions: Republican Ideology and the Making of the State Constitutions in the Revolutionary Era'', University of North Carolina Press, ISBN 978-0-7425-2069-1
* Childers, Christopher (March 2011), "[http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/civil_war_history/v057/57.1.childers.html Interpreting Popular Sovereignty: A Historiographical Essay]", ''Civil War History'' '''57''' (1): 48–70
* Conkin, Paul K. (1974), ''Self-Evident Truths: Being a Discourse on the Origins & Development of the First Principles of American Government—Popular Sovereignty, Natural Rights, and Balance & Separation of Powers'', Indiana University Press, ISBN 978-0-253-20198-0
* Lutz, Donald S. (1980), ''Popular Consent and Popular Control: Whig Political Theory in the Early State Constitutions'', Louisiana State Univ. Press, ISBN 978-0-8071-0596-2</ref>
* Lutz, Donald S. (1988), ''The Origins of American Constitutionalism'', Louisiana State University Press, ISBN 978-0-8071-1506-0
* Morgan, Edmund S. (1977), "The Problem of Popular Sovereignty", Aspects of American Liberty: Philosophical, Historical and Political (''The American Philosophical Society'')
* Morgan, Edmund S. (1988), ''Inventing the People: The Rise of Popular Sovereignty in England and America'', W.W. Norton and Company, ISBN 0-393-30623-2
* Peters, Jr., Ronald M. (1978) ''The Massachusetts Constitution of 1780: A Social Compact'', University of Massachusetts Press, ISBN 978-0-8071-1506-0
* Reid, John Phillip (1986–1993), ''Constitutional History of the American Revolution'' '''III''' (4 volumes ed.), University of Wisconsin Press, ISBN 0-299-13070-3
* Silbey, Joel H., ed. (1994), "Constitutional Conventions", ''Encyclopedia of the American Legislative System'' (3 volumes ed.) (Charles Scribner's Sons) '''I''', ISBN 978-0-684-19243-7
* Tarcov, Nadthan (1986), "Popular Sovereignty (in Democratic Political Theory)", in Levy, Leonard, ''Encyclopedia of the American Constitution'' '''3''', ISBN 978-0-02-864880-4

==Further reading==
* {{Citation |last=Childers |first=Christopher |title=The Failure of Popular Sovereignty: Slavery, Manifest Destiny, and the Radicalization of Southern Politics |publisher=University of Kansas Press |year= 2012 |pages=334}}
* {{Citation |last=Etcheson |first=Nicole |title=The Great Principle of Self-Government: Popular Sovereignty and Bleeding Kansa |journal=Kansas History |volume=27 |date=Spring–Summer 2004 |pages=14–29}} links it to [[Jacksonian Democracy]]
* {{Citation |last=Johannsen |first=Robert W. |title=Stephen A. Douglas |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=1973 |pages=576–613}}.


{{Liberalism}}
{{Liberalism}}

Revision as of 14:11, 9 August 2013

Popular sovereignty or the sovereignty of the people is the principle that the authority of the government is created and sustained by the consent of its people (Rule by the People), who are the source of all political power. It is closely associated with republicanism and social contract philosophers such as Thomas Hobbes, John Locke and Jean-Jacques Rousseau. Popular sovereignty expresses a concept and does not necessarily reflect or describe a political reality.[a] It is usually contrasted with the concept of parliamentary sovereignty, and with individual sovereignty.

Benjamin Franklin expressed the concept when he wrote, "In free governments, the rulers are the servants and the people their superiors and sovereigns".[1]

The term "squatter sovereignty" is used by Jefferson Davis in his book A Short History of the Confederate States of America. This term referred to the influx of new citizens in order to manipulate the ultimate sovereign votes. At the 1860 Democratic National Convention, William L. Yancey used the phrase "squatter sovereignty" in a speech he gave.[2] Popular sovereignty also can be described as the voice of the people.

Origins

Popular sovereignty in its modern sense, that is, including all the people and not just noblemen, is an idea that dates to the social contracts school (mid-17th to mid-18th centuries), represented by Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679), John Locke (1632–1704), and Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778), author of The Social Contract, a prominent political work that clearly highlighted the ideals of "general will" and further matured the idea of popular sovereignty. The central tenet is that legitimacy of rule or of law is based on the consent of the governed. Popular sovereignty is thus a basic tenet of most democracies. Hobbes, Locke and Rousseau were the most influential thinkers of this school, all postulating that individuals choose to enter into a social contract with one another, thus voluntarily giving up some of their natural freedom in return for protection from dangers derived from the freedom of others. Whether men were seen as naturally more prone to violence and rapine (Hobbes) or cooperation and kindness (Rousseau), the idea that a legitimate social order emerges only when the liberties and duties are equal among citizens binds the social contract thinkers to the concept of popular sovereignty.

A parallel development of a theory of popular sovereignty can be found among the School of Salamanca (see e.g. Francisco de Vitoria (1483–1546) or Francisco Suarez (1548–1617)), who (like the theorists of the divine right of kings and Locke) saw sovereignty as emanating originally from God, but (unlike divine right theorists and in agreement with Locke) passing from God to all people equally, not only to monarchs.

Republics and popular monarchies are theoretically based on popular sovereignty. However, a legalistic notion of popular sovereignty does not necessarily imply an effective, functioning democracy: a party or even an individual dictator may claim to represent the will of the people, and rule in its name, pretending to detain auctoritas. That would be congruent with Hobbes's view on the subject, but not with most modern definitions that see democracy as a necessary condition of popular sovereignty.

The application of the doctrine of popular sovereignty receives particular emphasis in American history, notes historian Christian G. Fritz's American Sovereigns: The People and America's Constitutional Tradition Before the Civil War, a study of the early history of American constitutionalism.[3] In describing how Americans attempted to apply this doctrine prior to the territorial struggle over slavery that led to the Civil War, political scientist Donald S. Lutz noted the variety of American applications:

To speak of popular sovereignty is to place ultimate authority in the people. There are a variety of ways in which sovereignty may be expressed. It may be immediate in the sense that the people make the law themselves, or mediated through representatives who are subject to election and recall; it may be ultimate in the sense that the people have a negative or veto over legislation, or it may be something much less dramatic. In short, popular sovereignty covers a multitude of institutional possibilities. In each case, however, popular sovereignty assumes the existence of some form of popular consent, and it is for this reason that every definition of republican government implies a theory of consent.

— Donald S. Lutz[4][b]

The American Revolution marked a departure in the concept of popular sovereignty as it had been discussed and employed in the European historical context. With their Revolution, Americans substituted the sovereignty in the person of King George III, with a collective sovereign—composed of the people. Thenceforth, American revolutionaries generally agreed and were committed to the principle that governments were legitimate only if they rested on popular sovereignty – that is, the sovereignty of the people.[c] This idea—often linked with the notion of the consent of the governed—was not invented by the American revolutionaries. Rather, the consent of the governed and the idea of the people as a sovereign had clear 17th and 18th century intellectual roots in English history.[5]

1850s

In the 1850s, in the runup to the Civil War, Northern Democrats led by Senator Lewis Cass of Michigan and Stephen A. Douglas of Illinois promoted popular sovereignty as a middle position on the slavery issue. It said that actual residents of territories should be able to decide by voting whether or not slavery would be allowed in the territory. The federal government did not have to make the decision, and by appealing to democracy Cass and Douglas hoped they could finesse the question of support for or opposition to slavery. Douglas applied popular sovereignty to Kansas in the Kansas Nebraska Act which passed Congress in 1854. The Act had two unexpected results. By dropping the Missouri Compromise of 1820 (which said slavery would never be allowed in Kansas), it was a major boost for the expansion of slavery. Overnight outrage united anti-slavery forces across the North into an "anti-Nebraska" movement that soon was institutionalized as the Republican Party, with its firm commitment to stop the expansion of slavery. Second, pro- and anti-slavery elements moved into Kansas with the intention of voting slavery up or down, leading to a raging civil war, known as "Bleeding Kansas." Abraham Lincoln targeted popular sovereignty in the Lincoln-Douglas Debates of 1858, leaving Douglas in a position that alienated Southern pro-slavery Democrats who thought he was too weak in his support of slavery. The Southern Democrats broke off and ran their own candidate against Lincoln and Douglas in 1860.[6]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Leonard Levy notes the "doctrine" of popular sovereignty that it "relates primarily not to the Constitution's [actual] operation but to its source of authority and supremacy, ratification, amendment, and possible abolition" (Tarcov 1986, v. 3, p. 1426, 1426).
  2. ^
    • Paul K. Conkin, describes "the almost unanimous acceptance of popular sovereignty at the level of abstract principle" (Conkin 1974, p. 52);
    • Edmund S. Morgan, concludes thatthe American Revolution "confirmed and completed the subordination of government to the will of the people" (Morgan 1977, p. 101);
    • Willi Paul Adams asserts that statements of the "principle" of the people’s sovereignty "expressed the very heart of the consensus among the victors of 1776" (Adams 1980, p. 137).
  1. ^ Thomas Jefferson, UVa Library [verification needed]
  2. ^ p. 250, Democratic Party. National Convention, Charleston and Baltimore, 1860. Proceedings of the Conventions at Charleston and Baltimore. Washington, 9999
  3. ^ Christian G. Fritz, American Sovereigns: The People and America's Constitutional Tradition Before the Civil War (Cambridge University Press, 2008) at p. 290, 400. ISBN 978-0-521-88188-3
  4. ^ Lutz 1980, p. 38
  5. ^ On the English origins of the sovereignty of the people and consent as the basis of government, see: Reid 1986–1993, v. III, pp. 97–101, 107–110; Morgan 1988, [page needed]
  6. ^ Childers 2011, pp. 48–70

References

  • Adams, Willi Paul (1980), The First American Constitutions: Republican Ideology and the Making of the State Constitutions in the Revolutionary Era, University of North Carolina Press, ISBN 978-0-7425-2069-1
  • Childers, Christopher (March 2011), "Interpreting Popular Sovereignty: A Historiographical Essay", Civil War History 57 (1): 48–70
  • Conkin, Paul K. (1974), Self-Evident Truths: Being a Discourse on the Origins & Development of the First Principles of American Government—Popular Sovereignty, Natural Rights, and Balance & Separation of Powers, Indiana University Press, ISBN 978-0-253-20198-0
  • Lutz, Donald S. (1980), Popular Consent and Popular Control: Whig Political Theory in the Early State Constitutions, Louisiana State Univ. Press, ISBN 978-0-8071-0596-2</ref>
  • Lutz, Donald S. (1988), The Origins of American Constitutionalism, Louisiana State University Press, ISBN 978-0-8071-1506-0
  • Morgan, Edmund S. (1977), "The Problem of Popular Sovereignty", Aspects of American Liberty: Philosophical, Historical and Political (The American Philosophical Society)
  • Morgan, Edmund S. (1988), Inventing the People: The Rise of Popular Sovereignty in England and America, W.W. Norton and Company, ISBN 0-393-30623-2
  • Peters, Jr., Ronald M. (1978) The Massachusetts Constitution of 1780: A Social Compact, University of Massachusetts Press, ISBN 978-0-8071-1506-0
  • Reid, John Phillip (1986–1993), Constitutional History of the American Revolution III (4 volumes ed.), University of Wisconsin Press, ISBN 0-299-13070-3
  • Silbey, Joel H., ed. (1994), "Constitutional Conventions", Encyclopedia of the American Legislative System (3 volumes ed.) (Charles Scribner's Sons) I, ISBN 978-0-684-19243-7
  • Tarcov, Nadthan (1986), "Popular Sovereignty (in Democratic Political Theory)", in Levy, Leonard, Encyclopedia of the American Constitution 3, ISBN 978-0-02-864880-4

Further reading

  • Childers, Christopher (2012), The Failure of Popular Sovereignty: Slavery, Manifest Destiny, and the Radicalization of Southern Politics, University of Kansas Press, p. 334
  • Etcheson, Nicole (Spring–Summer 2004), "The Great Principle of Self-Government: Popular Sovereignty and Bleeding Kansa", Kansas History, 27: 14–29 links it to Jacksonian Democracy
  • Johannsen, Robert W. (1973), Stephen A. Douglas, Oxford University Press, pp. 576–613.