Jump to content

User:Javierfv1212/sandbox: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
No edit summary
No edit summary
Line 1: Line 1:
{{MahayanaBuddhism}}
{{Redirect|Sunyata}}
{{for|the ancient city of Madhyamika|Nagari, Rajasthan}}
{{Buddhist term
'''Madhyamaka''' ({{lang-sa|Madhyamaka}}, {{zh|t=中觀见|p=Zhōngguān Jìan}}; also known as ''Śūnyavāda'') refers primarily to the later schools of [[Buddhist philosophy]]{{sfn|Williams|2000|p=140}} founded by [[Nagarjuna]] (150 CE to 250 CE). According to Madhyamaka, all [[Dharma#Dharmas in Buddhist phenomenology|phenomena]] (''dharmas'') are [[śūnyatā|empty]] (''śūnya'') of "nature,"{{sfn|Brunholzl|2004|p=70}} a "substance" or "essence" ([[Svabhava|svabhāva]]) which gives them "solid and independent existence,"{{sfn|Brunholzl|2004|p=590}} because they are [[Pratītyasamutpāda|dependently co-arisen]]. But this "emptiness" itself is also "empty": it does not have an existence on its own, nor does it refer to a transcendental reality beyond or above phenomenal reality.{{sfn|Cheng|1981}}{{sfn|Garfield|1994}}{{sfn|Garfield|2012}}
| fontsize=100%
| title=Śūnyatā
| pi= Suññatā<br/> ([[Devanagari|Dev]]: सुञ्ञता)
| my= thone nya ta, သုညတ
| sa= Śūnyatā<br/> ([[Devanagari|Dev]]: शून्यता)
| bn= শূন্যতা
| bn-Latn=Shunnôta
| en= emptiness, voidness, openness, thusness, etc.
| zh=[[wiktionary:空|空]]
| zh-Latn=Kōng
| ja=空
| ja-Latn=Kū
| km=សុញ្ញតា<br>(Sonnhata)
| ko=공성(空性)
| ko-Latn= gong-seong
| bo= སྟོང་པ་ཉིད་
| bo-Latn=[[Wylie transliteration|Wylie]]: stong-pa nyid<br/>[[THL Simplified Phonetic Transcription|THL]]: tongpa nyi
| mn=хоосон
|vi=Không ̣(空)}}
{{buddhism}}

'''Śūnyatā''' (Sanskrit; Pali: ''suññatā''), pronounced ‘shoonyataa’, translated into English most often as ''emptiness''<ref>{{cite book|author1=Dale Mathers|author2=Melvin E. Miller|author3=Osamu Ando|title=Self and No-Self: Continuing the Dialogue Between Buddhism and Psychotherapy|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=WVpcAgAAQBAJ |year=2013|publisher=Routledge|isbn=978-1-317-72386-8|page=81}}</ref> and sometimes ''voidness'',<ref>[https://web.archive.org/web/20140228062714/http://www.palikanon.com/english/wtb/s_t/sunna.htm Suñña] - Palikanon.com,</ref> is a Buddhist concept which has multiple meanings depending on its doctrinal context. It can refer to an ontological feature of reality, a meditation state, or a phenomenological analysis of experience. In Buddhist texts, it is often described through metaphors such as [[Maya (religion)|illusions]], dreams, mirages and so forth.<ref name=":1" />

In [[Theravada Buddhism]], suññatā often refers to the [[anatta|non-self]] (Pāli: ''anattā'', Sanskrit: ''anātman''){{refn|group=note|A common translation is "no-self", without a self, but the Pali canon uses ''anattā'' as a singular substantive, meaning "not-self".{{sfn|Bronkhorst|2009|p=124}}}} nature of the [[five aggregates]] of experience and the [[ayatana|six sense spheres]]. Suññatā is also often used to refer to a meditative state or experience.

In [[Mahayana]], ''Sunyata'' refers to the tenet that "all things are empty of intrinsic existence and nature," (''[[svabhava]]'') <ref>{{cite book|author=Paul Williams|title=Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=GMN-AgAAQBAJ|year=2008|publisher=Routledge|isbn=978-1-134-25056-1|pages=68–69}}</ref><ref>{{cite book|author=Christopher W. Gowans|title=Buddhist Moral Philosophy: An Introduction |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yW4KBAAAQBAJ&pg=PT69|year=2014|publisher=Routledge|isbn=978-1-317-65934-1 |pages=69–70 }}</ref> but may also refer to the [[Buddha-nature]] teachings and primordial or empty awareness, as in [[Dzogchen]] and [[Rangtong-Shentong|Shentong]].


==Etymology==
==Etymology==
"''Śūnyatā''" ([[Sanskrit]]) is usually translated as "devoidness," "emptiness," "hollow, hollowness," "voidness." It is the noun form of the adjective ''śūnya'' or ''śhūnya'', plus ''-tā'':
* ''śūnya'' means "zero," "nothing," "empty" or "void".<ref>Monier-Williams, Sir Monier (2nd edn, 1899) [http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/cgi-bin/serveimg.pl?file=/scans/MWScan/MWScanjpg/mw1085-zuSkavraNa.jpg ''A Sanskrit-English Dictionary'']. Reprinted Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi 1986: p.1085.</ref> ''Śūnya'' comes from the root ''śvi'', meaning "hollow".
* ''-tā'' means "-ness";


''Madhya'' is a Sanskrit word meaning "middle". It is cognate with Latin ''med-iu-s'' and English ''mid''. The ''-ma'' suffix is a superlative, giving ''madhyama'' the meaning of "mid-most" or "medium". The ''-ka'' suffix is used to form adjectives, thus ''madhyamaka'' means "middleling". The ''-ika'' suffix is used to form possessives, with a collective sense, thus ''mādhyamika'' mean "belonging to the mid-most" (the ''-ika'' suffix regularly causes a lengthening of the first vowel and elision of the final ''-a'').
==Development of the concept==
Over time, many different philosophical schools or tenet-systems (Sanskrit: ''siddhānta'')<ref>Klein, Anne C. (1991). ''Knowing Naming & Negation a sourcebook on Tibetan, Sautrantika''. Snowlion publications, {{ISBN|0-937938-21-1}}</ref> have developed within Buddhism in an effort to explain the exact philosophical meaning of emptiness.


In a Buddhist context these terms refer to the "middle path" (''madhyama pratipada'') between the extremes of annihilationism (''ucchedavāda'') and eternalism (''śassatavāda''), for example:
After the Buddha, emptiness was further developed by the [[Abhidharma]] schools, [[Nagarjuna|Nāgārjuna]] and the [[Madhyamaka|Mādhyamaka]] school, an early Mahāyāna school. Emptiness ("positively" interpreted) is also an important element of the [[Tathagatagarbha|Buddha nature]] literature, which played a formative role in the evolution of subsequent Mahāyāna doctrine and practice.
<blockquote>
''ity etāv ubhāv antāv anupagamya madhyamayā pratipadā tathāgato dharmaṃ deśayati |'' - Kātyāyana Sūtra. <br />
Thus, the Tathāgata teaches the Dharma by a middle path avoiding both these extremes. </blockquote>


* ''Madhyamaka'' refers to the school of thought associated with Nāgārjuna and his commentators.
==Early Buddhism==
* ''Mādhyamika'' refers to adherents of the Madhyamaka school.
{{Main|Presectarian Buddhism}}


Note that in both words the stress is on the first syllable.
===Pāli Nikāyas===
[[Image:Foam - big.jpg|thumb|right|A simile from the Pali scriptures (SN 22.95) compares [[Rūpa#Buddhism|form]] and [[Vedanā|feelings]] with foam and bubbles.]]
{{See also|Sati (Buddhism)}}


==Emptiness==
The Pali canon uses the term emptiness in three ways: "(1) as a meditative dwelling, (2) as an attribute of objects, and (3) as a type of awareness-release."<ref name="accesstoinsight.org">[http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/mn/mn.122.than.html MN 122. See, e.g., Maha-suññata Sutta: The Greater Discourse on Emptiness translated from the Pali by Thanissaro Bhikkhu," Retrieved on 30 July 2013 from "Access to Insight" at www.accesstoinsight.org]</ref>
{{main|Svatantrika-Prasaṅgika distinction}}
Central to Madhyamaka philosophy is ''[[śūnyatā]]'', "emptiness." The term refers to the "emptiness" of inherent existence: all [[Dharma#Dharmas in Buddhist phenomenology|phenomena]] are [[śūnyatā|empty]] of "substance" or "essence" ({{lang-sa|[[svabhāva]]}}) or inherent existence, because they are [[Pratītyasamutpāda|dependently co-arisen]]. At a conventional level, "things" do exist, but ultimately they are "empty" of inherent existence. But this "emptiness" itself is also "empty": it does not have an existence on its own, nor does it refer to a transcendental reality beyond or above phenomenal reality.{{sfn|Cheng|1981}}{{sfn|Garfield|1994}}{{sfn|Garfield|2012}}


====Emptiness of dhammas====
===Dependent Origination===
Nagarjuna further develops the notion of dependent arising, arguing that every ''dharma'', or every "thing", does not exist on its own, but depending on other "things" and causes:
According to [[Bhikkhu Analayo]]:
{{quote|<poem>
{{quote|In the Pāli discourses the adjective suñña occurs with a much higher frequency than the corresponding noun suññatā. This is not a matter of mere philological interest, but points to an emphasis in early Buddhism on qualifying phenomena as 'being empty' rather than on an abstract state of empty-'ness'."<ref>{{cite book|last=Analayo|first=Bhikkhu|authorlink=Bhikkhu Analayo|title=Excursions into the Thought-World of the Pali Discourses|year=2012|publisher=[[Pariyatti]]|page=272|ISBN=9781928706984}}</ref>}}
Whatever is [[Pratītyasamutpāda|dependent arising]]
We declared that to be [[Śūnyatā|emptiness]].
That is [[Prajñaptir upādāya|dependent designation]],
And is itself the [[middle way]].</poem>|Nāgārjuna, {{IAST|''Mūlamadhyamakakārikā''}} 24:18}}


===Svabhava - essence===
One example of this usage is in the ''Pheṇapiṇḍūpama Sutta'' ([[Samyutta Nikaya|SN]] 22:95), which states that on close inspection, each of the five aggregates are seen as being void (''rittaka''), hollow (''tucchaka''), coreless (''asāraka''). In the text a series of contemplations is given for each aggregate: form is like “a lump of foam” (''pheṇapiṇḍa''); sensation like “a water bubble” (''bubbuḷa''); perception like “a mirage” (''marici''); formations like “a plantain tree” (''kadalik-khandha''); and cognition is like “a magical illusion” (''māyā'').<ref name=":1">Shi Huifeng, Is "Illusion" a Prajñāpāramitā Creation? The Birth and Death of a Buddhist Cognitive Metaphor, Fo Guang University, Journal of Buddhist Philosophy , Vol.2, 2016. </ref>
Nagarjuna follows his own logic to its end, wondering what the subsequent consequences are of his propositions. Since all "things" are dependently arisen, how then can a non-existing "thing" cause another "thing" to come into being? In Chapter 15 of the [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]] Nagarjuna centers on the words [[svabhava]] {{refn|group=note|'Own-beings',{{sfn|Warder|2000|p=360}} unique nature or substance,{{sfn|Kalupahana|1994|p=162}} an identifying characteristic; an identity; an essence,{{sfn|Hayes|1994|p=317}}}} parabhava{{refn|group=note|A differentiating characteristic,{{sfn|Hayes|1994|p=317}} the fact of being dependent,{{sfn|Hayes|1994|p=317}}}} [[bhava]] {{refn|group=note|'Being',{{sfn|Warder|2000|p=361}} 'self-nature or substance'{{sfn|Kalupahana|1994|p=165}}}} and [[abhava]]:{{refn|group=note|Not being present; absence:{{sfn|Hayes|1994|p=316}}}}
{{quote|Nagarjuna's critique of the notion of own-nature{{refn|group=note|svabhava}} (''Mk.'' ch. 15) argues that anything which arises according to conditions, as all phenomena do, can have no inherent nature, for what is depends on what conditions it. Moreover, if there is nothing with own-nature, there can be nothing with 'other-nature' (''para-bhava''), i.e. something which is dependent for its existence and nature on something ''else'' which has own-nature. Furthermore, if there is neither own-nature nor other-nature, there cannot be anything with a true, substantial existent nature (''bhava''). If there is no true existent, then there can be no non-existent (''abhava'').{{sfn|Harvey|1995|p=97}}}}


In chapter 15 of the Mulamadhyamakakarika, "Nagarjuna is playing on the word 'thing'".<ref group=web name=Batchelor>[https://www.myspace.com/shivatao/blog/283271465 Stephen Batchelor: Verses from the Center. Romanization and Literal English Translation of the Tibetan Text]</ref>{{refn|group=note|Stephen Batchelor, Verses from the Centre, Chapter 15 (Investigation of Essences), note for verse 3: "There is a problem here with the Tibetan translation from Sanskrit. Svabhava is translated as rang bzhin, but parabhava rather clumsily as gzhan gyi dngos po [the term first appears in I:3]. A [[Tibet]]an reader would thus lose the etymological connection between "own-thing" (svabhava) and "other-thing" (parabhava), which then link up with "thing" (bhava) and no-thing (abhava). Nagarjuna is playing on the word "thing".<ref group=web name=Batchelor />}} Nagarjuna uses the ambivalence inherent in the term ''svabhava'':
According to Shi Huifeng, the terms void (''rittaka''), hollow (''tucchaka'') and coreless (''asāraka'') are also used in the early texts to refer to words and things which are deceptive, false, vain and worthless.<ref name=":1" /> This sense of worthlessness and vacuousness is also found in other uses of the term ''māyā'', such as the following:<blockquote>“Monks, sensual pleasures are impermanent, hollow, false, deceptive; they are illusory (''māyākatame''), the prattle of fools.”<ref name=":1" /></blockquote>The ''Suñña Sutta'',<ref name="Bhikkhu_1997d_3585">{{harvnb|Bhikkhu|1997d}}.</ref> part of the [[Pali Canon|Pāli canon]], relates that the monk [[Ananda|Ānanda]], [[Gautama Buddha|Buddha's]] attendant asked,
{{quote|[T]he word "svabhava" can be interpreted in two different ways. It can be rendered either as '''identity''' [...] or as '''causal independence'''.{{sfn|Hayes|2003|p=4}}}}
{{quote|It is said that the world is empty, the world is empty, lord. In what respect is it said that the world is empty?" The Buddha replied, "Insofar as it is empty of a self or of anything pertaining to a self: Thus it is said, Ānanda, that the world is empty.}}


This ambiguity is easily lost in translation:
According to [[Thanissaro Bhikku]]:
{{quote|When one reads Nagarjuna's argument in Sanskrit, it is not immediately obvious that the argument has taken advantage of an ambiguity in the key term. But when one tries to translate his argument into some other language, such as English or Tibetan, one finds that it is almost impossible to translate his argument in a way that makes sense in translation. This is because the terms in the language of translation do not have precisely the same range of ambiguities as the words in the original Sanskrit. In English, we are forced to disambiguate, and in disambiguating, we end up spoiling the apparent integrity of the argument.{{sfn|Hayes|2003|p=4}}}}
{{quote|Emptiness as a quality of [[Dharmas#Buddhist phenomenology|dharmas]], in the early canons, means simply that one cannot identify them as one's own self or having anything pertaining to one's own self ... Emptiness as a mental state, in the early canons, means a mode of perception in which one neither adds anything to nor takes anything away from what is present, noting simply, "There is this." This mode is achieved through a process of intense concentration, coupled with the insight that notes more and more subtle levels of the presence and absence of disturbance (see MN 121).<ref>Thanissaro Bhikku, The Buddhist Religions: An Historical Introduction, P 96.</ref>}}


The doctrine of [[Pratītyasamutpāda|dependent arising]] cannot be reconciled with "a conception of self-nature or substance".{{sfn|Kalupahana|1994|p=165}} Nagarjuna refutes "the commentarial doctrine of the 'own-being' of principles as contrary to the ''[[Tripitaka]]''":{{sfn|Warder|2000|p=360}}
====Meditative state====
{{quote|Nagarjuna had no objection to the [[Abhidhamma]] formulation of causal relations so long as the relata are not regarded as having a unique nature or substance (''[[svabhava]]'').{{sfn|Kalupahana|1994|p=162}}}}
Emptiness as a meditative state is said to be reached when "not attending to any themes, he [the bhikku] enters & remains in internal emptiness" (MN 122). This meditative dwelling is developed through the "four formless states" of meditation or [[Arūpajhāna]]s and then through "themeless concentration of awareness."<ref name="accesstoinsight.org"/>


The rejection of inherent existence does not imply that there is no existence at all.{{sfn|Warder|2000|p=361}} What it does mean is that there is no "unique nature or substance (''[[svabhava]]'')"{{sfn|Kalupahana|1994|p=162}} in the "things" we perceive. This may not necessarily be in contrast to the Abhidhamma point of view, given the ambivalence in the terms used by Nagarjuna:
The Cūlasuññata-sutta (MN III 104) and the Mahāsuññata-sutta (MN III 109) outline how a monk can "dwell in emptiness" through a gradual step by step mental cultivation process, they both stress the importance of the impermanence of mental states and the absence of a self.
{{quote|What Nagarjuna is saying is that no being has a fixed and permanent nature. What the abhidarmikas maintained was that every thing has features that distinguish it from other things.{{sfn|Hayes|2003|p=10}}{{refn|group=note|Warder: "From Nagarjuna's own day onwards his doctrine was subject to being misunderstood as nihilistic: because he rejected 'existence' of beings and spoke of their 'emptiness' (of own-being), careless students (and critics who were either not very careful or not very scrupulous) have concluded that he maintained that ultimately the universe was an utter nothingness. In fact, his rejection of 'non-existence' is as emphatic as his rejection of 'existence', and must therefore lead us to the conclusion that what he is attacking are the notions or assertions themselves as metaphysical concepts imposed on ultimate reality, which is entirely beyond any possible concept or definition.{{sfn|Warder|2000|p=363}}}}}}


===Two truths===
In the Kāmabhu Sutta S IV.293, it is explained that a [[bhikkhu]] can experience a [[Jhana in Theravada#Cessation of feelings and perceptions|trancelike contemplation]] in which perception and feeling cease. When he emerges from this state, he recounts three types of "contact" (''[[Sparśa|phasso]]''):
Madhyamaka discerns [[Two truths doctrine|two levels of truth]], conventional truth and ultimate truth,{{sfn|Cheng|1981}} to make clear that it does make sense to speak of existence. Ultimately, we realize that all phenomena are sunyata, empty of concrete existence. Conventionally, we ''do'' perceive concrete objects which we are aware of.{{sfn|Brunholzl|2004|p=73}} Yet, this perceived reality is an experiential reality, not an ontological reality with substantial or independent existence.{{sfn|Brunholzl|2004|p=73}}
# "emptiness" (''suññato''),
# "signless" (''animitto''),
# "undirected" (''appa{{IAST|ṇ}}ihito'').<ref>[http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sn/sn41/sn41.006.than.html SN 41.6. See, e.g., Thanissaro Bhikkhu (trans.) (2004), "SN 41.6 Kamabhu Sutta: With Kamabhu (On the Cessation of Perception & Feeling)," retrieved Feb 4 2009 from "Access to Insight" at www.accesstoinsight.org]</ref>
The meaning of emptiness as contemplated here is explained at M I.297 and S IV.296-97 as the "emancipation of the mind by emptiness" (''suññatā cetovimutti'') being consequent upon the realization that "this world is empty of self or anything pertaining to self" (''suññam ida{{IAST|ṃ}} attena vā attaniyena vā'').<ref>[http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/mn/mn.043.than.html MN 43 and SN 41.7. See, e.g., respectively, Thanissaro Bhikkhu (trans.) (2006), "MN 43 Mahavedalla Sutta: The Greater Set of Questions-and-Answers," retrieved February 4, 2009 from "Access to Insight"]</ref><ref>[http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sn/sn41/sn41.007.than.html Thanissaro Bhikkhu (trans.) (2004), "SN 41.7 Godatta Sutta: To Godatta (On Awareness-release)," retrieved February 4, 2009 from "Access to Insight"]</ref>


The ultimate truth of ''sunyata'' does not refer to "nothingness" or "non-existence"; it refers to the absence of inherent existence.{{sfn|Chenh|1981}}
The term "emptiness" (''suññatā'') is also used in two suttas in the ''Majjhima Nikāya'', in the context of a progression of mental states. The texts refer to each state's emptiness of the one below.<ref>MN 121 and MN 122. See, e.g., respectively, Thanissaro (1997a) and Thanissaro (1997b).</ref>


According to Hayes, the two truths may also refer to two different goals in life: the highest goal of nirvana, and the lower goal of "commercial good". The highest goal is the liberation from attachment, both material ''and'' intellectual.{{sfn|Hayes|2003|p=8-9}}
===Āgamas===
The Chinese [[Āgama (Buddhism)|Agamas]] contain various parallels to the ''Pheṇapiṇḍūpama Sutta.'' One partial parallel from the [[Ekottara Agama]] describes the body with different metaphors: “a ball of snow”, “a heap of dirt”, “a mirage”, “an illusion” (māyā), or “an empty fist used to fool a child”.<ref name=":1" /> According to Shi Huifeng, the Samyukta Agama parallel uses the same five metaphors as the Pali text, but uses four abjectives to describe each: "adding “nothingness” (''wusuoyou'' 無所有 ; *''akiṃcanya'' ) before solid (''wulao'' 無牢; ''riktaka''), unreal (''wushi'' 無實; ''tucchaka'') and insubstantial (''wuyou jiangu'' 無有堅固; ''asāraka'')."<ref name=":1" />


Insight into the emptiness of "things' is part of developing [[Wisdom in Buddhism|wisdom]], seeing things as they are. Conceiving of concrete and unchanging objects leads to clinging and suffering. [[Buddhapalita]] says:
In a similar vein, the Mūla-Sarvāstivādin ''Māyājāla Sūtra,'' gives two sets of metaphors for each of the sensory consciousnesses to illustrate their vain illusory character, giving two for each:<ref name=":1" />
{{quote|What is the reality of things just as it is? It is the absence of essence. Unskilled persons whose eye of intelligence is obscured by the darkness of delusion conceive of an essence of things and then generate attachment and hostility with regard to them.|{{IAST|''Buddhapālita-mula-madhyamaka-vrtti''}} P5242,73.5.6-74.1.2{{sfn|Tsong Khapa|2002}}}}


===The emptiness of emptiness===
# Forms - a madman wandering naked, an illusory army.
Ultimate truth also does not refer to "absolute truth," some absolute reality above or beyond the "relative reality."{{sfn|Cheng|1981}} On the contrary, emptiness itself is "empty" of inherent existence:{{sfn|Garfield|1994}}
# Sounds - a drunkard who sleeps with his mother, an echo
{{quote|Ultimate truth does not point to a transcendent reality, but to the transcendence of deception. It is critical to emphasize that the ultimate truth of emptiness is a negational truth. In looking for inherently existent phenomena it is revealed that it cannot be found. This absence is not findable because it is not an entity, just as a room without an elephant in it does not contain an elephantless substance. Even conventionally, elephantlessness does not exist. Ultimate truth or emptiness does not point to an essence or nature, however subtle, that everything is made of.<ref group=web name="Susan Kahn" />{{refn|group=note|Susan Kahn further explains: "The emptiness of emptiness refutes ultimate truth as yet another argument for essentialism under the guise of being beyond the conventional or as the foundation of it. To realize emptiness is not to find a transcendent place or truth to land in but to see the conventional as merely conventional. Here lies the key to liberation. For to see the deception is to be free of deception, like a magician who knows the magic trick. When one is no longer fooled by false appearances, phenomena are neither reified nor denied. They are understood interdependently, as ultimately empty and thus, as only conventionally real. This is the Middle Way."<ref group=web name="Susan Kahn">[http://emptinessteachings.com/2014/09/11/the-two-truths-of-buddhism-and-the-emptiness-of-emptiness/ Susan Kahn, ''The Two Truths of Buddhism and The Emptiness of Emptiness.'']</ref>}}}}
# Odors - man pursued by an assasin, a reflection in a mirror
# Tastes - a spiteful disciple, a mirage
# Tactiles - a man harassed by bandits, sense pleasures in a dream
# Mentals - a basket of snakes, illusory ornaments.


===Essentialism and nihilism===
Other Sarvāstivādin Agama sutras (extant in Chinese) which have emptiness as a theme include Samyukta Agama 335 - ''Paramārtha-śunyatā-sūtra'' (Sutra on ultimate emptiness) and Samyukta Agama 297 - ''Mahā-śunyatā-dharma-paryāya'' (Greater discourse on emptiness). These sutras have no parallel Pali suttas.<ref>Shì hùifēng, “Dependent Origination = Emptiness”—Nāgārjuna’s Innovation? An Examination of the Early and Mainstream Sectarian Textual Sources, page 26</ref> These sutras associate emptiness with [[dependent origination]], which shows that this relation of the two terms was already established in pre-[[Nagarjuna]] sources. The sutra on great emptiness states:
What remains is the middle way between eternalism and annihilationism:{{sfn|Kalupahana|1994|p=165}}
{{quote|"What is the Dharma Discourse on Great Emptiness? It is this— ‘When this exists, that exists; when this arises, that arises.’"<ref>Shì hùifēng, “Dependent Origination = Emptiness”—Nāgārjuna’s Innovation? An Examination of the Early and Mainstream Sectarian Textual Sources, page 28.</ref>}}
{{quote|The object of the critique is to show that the eternalist view is untenable and further to show that the 'own-being' theory adopted by some Buddhists did not really differ, when its implications were strictly worked out, from the eternalist theory of [[Brahmanism]] (the theory of an [[Ātman (Hinduism)|eternal 'soul']] and other eternal 'substances').{{sfn|Warder|2000|p=361}}}}


These two views are considered to be the ''two extreme views'':
The phrase "when this exists..." is a common gloss on [[dependent origination]]. Sarvāstivādin Agamas also speak of a certain emptiness [[samadhi]] (''śūnyatāsamādhi'') as well as stating that all dharmas are "classified as conventional".<ref>Shì hùifēng, “Dependent Origination = Emptiness”—Nāgārjuna’s Innovation? An Examination of the Early and Mainstream Sectarian Textual Sources, page 22, 27.</ref>
# ''Essentialism''{{sfn|Garfield|1995|p=88 footnote}} or ''eternalism'' (sastavadava){{sfn|Warder|2000|p=361}} - a belief that things inherently exist and are therefore efficacious objects of [[tṛṣṇā|craving]] and [[Upādāna|clinging]];{{sfn|Garfield|1995|p=88 footnote}}
# ''Nihilism''{{sfn|Garfield|1995|p=88 footnote}} or ''annihilationism'' (ucchedavada){{sfn|Warder|2000|p=361}} - views that lead one to believe that there is no need to be responsible for one's actions. Nagarjuna argues that we naively and innately perceive things as substantial, and it is this predisposition which is the root delusion that lies at the basis of all suffering.{{sfn|Garfield|1995|p=88 footnote}}


Madhyamaka represents the [[Middle way]] between them.
Mun-Keat Choong and [[Yin Shun]] have both published studies on the various uses of emptiness in the [[Early Buddhist Texts]] (Pali Canon and Chinese [[Āgama (Buddhism)|Agamas]]).<ref>Choong, Mun-Keat; The Notion of Emptiness in Early Buddhism, Motilal Banarsidass Publishe, 1999.</ref><ref>Yìn Shùn; An Investigation into Emptiness (Kōng zhī Tànjìu 空之探究) (1985)</ref> Choong has also published a collection of translations of Agama sutras from the Chinese on the topic of emptiness.<ref>[https://www.une.edu.au/__data/assets/pdf_file/0006/76164/2ed-2010-Annotated-Trans-SA-sutras-Emptiness-and-the-Middle-Way2.pdf Choong; Annotated Translation of Sutras from the Chinese Samyuktagama relevant to the Early Buddhist Teachings on Emptiness and the Middle Way (2004; second edition, International Buddhist College, Thailand, 2010.]</ref>


===The limits of language===
==Early Buddhist schools and Abhidharma==
Madhyamaka uses language to make clear the limits of our concepts. Ultimately, reality cannot be depicted by concepts.{{sfn|Cheng|1981}}{{sfn|Garfield|1995|p=102}} This creates a tension, since it does have to use concepts to convey its teachings:
Many of the [[early Buddhist schools]] featured sunyata as an important part of their teachings.
{{quote|This dynamic philosophical tension—a tension between the Madhyamika accounts of the limits of what can be coherently said and its analytical ostension of what cannot be said without paradox but must be understood—must constantly be borne in mind in reading the text. It is not an incoherent mysticism, but it is a logical tightrope act at the very limits of language and metaphysics.{{sfn|Garfield|1995|p=102}}}}


===Liberation===
The [[Sarvastivadin]] school's Abhidharma texts like the Dharmaskandhapāda Śāstra, and the later Mahāvibhāṣa also take up the theme of emptiness vis a vis dependent origination as found in the Agamas.<ref name="ReferenceA">Shì hùifēng, “Dependent Origination = Emptiness”—Nāgārjuna’s Innovation? An Examination of the Early and Mainstream Sectarian Textual Sources</ref> Likewise, the [[Sarvastivada|Sarvāstivādin]] biography of the Buddha known as the [[Lalitavistara Sūtra|Lalitavistara]] also contains various metaphors for the hollow, dependently originated nature of phenomena, like the following:<blockquote>Complexes have no inner might, are empty in themselves; </blockquote><blockquote>Rather like the stem of the plantain tree, when one reflects on them,</blockquote><blockquote>Like an illusion (''māyopama'') which deludes the mind (''citta''), </blockquote><blockquote>Like an empty fist with which a child is teased.<ref name=":1" /> </blockquote>Schools such as the [[Mahāsāṃghika]] Prajñaptivādins as well as many of the Sthavira schools (except the [[Pudgalavada]]) held that all dharmas were empty (dharma śūnyatā).<ref name="ReferenceA" /> This can be seen in the early [[Theravada]] [[Abhidhamma]] texts such as the [[Patisambhidamagga]] which also speak of the emptiness of the five aggregates and of [[svabhava]] as being "empty of essential nature".<ref>Potter, Karl H; Abhidharma Buddhism to 150 A.D., page 98</ref> The Theravada [[Kathavatthu]] also argues against the idea that emptiness is unconditioned.<ref>Shì hùifēng, “Dependent Origination = Emptiness”—Nāgārjuna’s Innovation? An Examination of the Early and Mainstream Sectarian Textual Sources, page 36.</ref> The [[Mahāvastu]], an influential [[Mahāsāṃghika]] work, states that the Buddha<blockquote>"has shown that the aggregates are like a lightning flash, as a bubble, or as the white foam on a wave."<ref name=":2" /></blockquote>One of the main themes of Harivarman's [[Tattvasiddhi]]-Śāstra (3rd-4th century) is ''[[Dharma (Buddhism)|dharma]]-śūnyatā'', the emptiness of phenomena.<ref name=":2">Skilton, Andrew. ''A Concise History of Buddhism.'' 2004. pp. 91-92</ref>
The ultimate aim of understanding emptiness is not philosophical insight as such, but to gain a [[Enlightenment in Buddhism|liberated mind]] which does not dwell upon concepts. To realize this, meditation on emptiness may proceed in stages, starting with the emptiness of both [[Fetter (Buddhism)#Identity view (sakkāya-diṭṭhi)|self]], objects and mental states,{{sfn|Brunholzl|2004|p=295-310}} culminating in a "natural state of nonreferential freedom."{{sfn|Brunholzl|2004|p=310}}{{refn|group=note|See also [[Atthakavagga and Parayanavagga]], for early, Madhyamaka-like texts from the Buddhist canon on freedom from views.}}


==Origins and development==
Shi Huifeng states that the sectarian [[Salistamba Sutra|Śālistamba Sūtra]] "describes dharma's without self as being mutually conditioning and thus “characterized as illusory”; with a connection between origination from causes and conditions and their illusory and deceptive nature, their lack of substantiality."<ref name=":1" />
[[File:Nagarjuna.gif|thumb|right|Nagarjuna]]
The Madhyamaka school is usually considered to have been founded by [[Nāgārjuna]], though it may have existed earlier. {{sfn|Warder|2000|p=358}} The name of the school is perhaps related to its close adherence to
Nāgārjuna’s main work, the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā. The term Madhyamaka is related to 'madhya' ('the middle').


Madhyamaka-thought had a major influence on the subsequent development of the Mahayana Buddhist tradition, although often in interaction with, and also in opposition to, the other two major streams of Mahayana Buddhist thought, namely Yogacara and Buddha-nature. It had a major impact on [[Tibetan Buddhism]], where it became the orthodox standard in the Gelugpa tradition, in opposition to Jonangpa's "Mahā-Mādhyamaka". Lama [[Je Tsongkhapa]], of the [[Gelug|Gelugpa]], claimed there were two division in Indian Madhyamika, creating the [[Svatantrika-Prasaṅgika distinction]].<ref>Tsongkhapa, Lamrim Chenmo V3 P116</ref> It also influenced the [[Zen]] tradition,{{sfn|Cheng|1981}} although this influence is less often discerned in comparison to the Buddha-nature thought. The present day schools of [[Tiantai]], [[Tendai]], [[Sanron]],{{sfn|Ng|1990|p=1}} are also influenced by the Mādhyamaka tradition, forming an [[East Asian Mādhyamaka]] tradition. Contemporary western Buddhism is less acquainted with Madhyamaka thought, although some implications have been recognized by western teachers.
== Theravāda ==
[[Theravada|Theravāda]] Buddhists generally take the view that emptiness is merely the [[Anatta|not-self]] nature of the [[five aggregates]]. Emptiness is an important door to liberation in the [[Theravada|Theravāda]] tradition just as it is in Mahayana, according to Insight meditation teacher [[Gil Fronsdal]].<ref>[http://www.insightmeditationcenter.org/books-articles/articles/emptiness-in-theravada-buddhism/ Emptiness in Theravada Buddhism]</ref> The classic [[Theravada|Theravāda]] text known as the ''[[Patisambhidamagga]]'' (c. 3rd century BCE) describes the [[five aggregates]] as empty ([[Shunyata|''suññam'']]):<blockquote>"Born materiality is empty of sabhava (''sabhavena suññam''); disappeared materiality is both changed and empty. Born feeling is empty of sabhava; disappeared feeling is both changed and empty...Born conceptualization...Born volitions...Born consciousness...Born becoming is empty of sabhava; disappeared becoming is both changed and empty. This is ‘empty in terms of change’."<ref>Ronkin, Noa; Early Buddhist Metaphysics, page 91</ref></blockquote>The ''Patisambhidamagga'' also equates [[Anatta|not-self]] with the emptiness liberation in a passage also cited by [[Buddhaghoṣa|Buddhaghosa]] in the ''[[Visuddhimagga]]'' (Vism XXI 70): <blockquote>"When one who has great wisdom brings [volitional formations] to mind as not-self, he acquires the emptiness liberation" -Patis. II 58.<ref>Fuller, Paul. The Notion of Ditthi in Theravada Buddhism: The Point of View, p. 143.</ref></blockquote>The ''[[Visuddhimagga]]'' (c. 5th century CE)'','' the most influential classical Theravāda treatise, states that not-self does not become apparent because it is concealed by "compactness" when one does not give attention to the various elements which make up the person. <ref name=":5">Ñāṇamoli Bhikkhu (trans), Buddhaghosa, The Path of Purification: Visuddhimagga, Buddhist Publication Society, 1991, p 668.</ref> The ''Paramatthamañjusa Visuddhimaggatika'' of [[Dhammapala|Acariya Dhammapala]], a 5th century Theravāda commentary on the ''[[Visuddhimagga]]'', comments on this passage by referring to the fact that we often assume unity and compactness in phenomena and functions which are instead made up of various elements, but when one sees that these are merely empty dhammas, one can understand the not-self characteristic:<blockquote>"when they are seen after resolving them by means of knowledge into these elements, they disintegrate like froth subjected to compression by the hand. They are mere states (''dhamma'') occurring due to conditions and void. In this way the characteristic of not-self becomes more evident."<ref name=":5" /></blockquote>According to Peter Harvey, the Theravāda view of dhammas and sabhava is not one of essences, but merely descriptive characteristics and hence is not the subject of [[Madhyamaka]] critique developed by Nagarjuna (see below).<ref>Harvey, Peter. INTRODUCTION TO BUDDHISM, page 87.</ref>


===Origins===
The modern Thai teacher [[Buddhadasa]] referred to emptiness as the "innermost heart" of the Buddhist teachings and the cure for the disease of suffering. He stated that emptiness, as it relates to the practice of Dhamma, can be seen both "as the absence of [[Dukkha]] and the defilements that are the cause of Dukkha and as the absence of the feeling that there is a self or that there are things which are the possessions of a self."<ref name=":6">Ajahn Buddhadasa, EMPTINESS; From: 'Heart-wood from the Bo Tree', a collection of three talks given by Venerable Ajahn Buddhadasa to the Dhamma study group at Siriraj Hospital in Bangkok, in 1961, https://www.budsas.org/ebud/ebdha196.htm


====Sutta Nipata====
</ref> He also equated [[Nirvana (Buddhism)|nibbana]] with emptiness, writing that "Nibbana, the remainderless extinction of Dukkha, means the same as supreme emptiness."<ref name=":6" />
The '''{{IAST|Aṭṭhakavagga}}''' (Pali, "Octet Chapter") and the '''Pārāyanavagga''' (Pali, "Way to the Far Shore Chapter") are two small collections of suttas within the [[Pali Canon|Pāli Canon]] of [[Theravada]] [[Buddhism]].{{refn|group=note|In the Pali canon, these chapters are the fourth and fifth chapters of the [[Khuddaka Nikaya]]'s [[Sutta Nipata]], respectively.}} They are among the earliest existing Buddhist literature, and place considerable emphasis on the rejection of, or non-attachment to, all [[View (Buddhism)|views]].


Gomez compared them to later Madhyamaka philosophy, which in its [[Prasangika|{{IAST|Prasaṅgika}}]] form especially makes a method of rejecting others' views rather than proposing its own.{{sfn|Gomez|1976}}
Emptiness is also seen as mode of perception which lacks all the usual conceptual elaborations we usually add on top of our experiences, such as the sense of "I" and "Mine". According to [[Thanissaro Bhikku]], emptiness is not so much a metaphysical view, as it is a strategic mode of acting and of seeing the world which leads to liberation:<ref name="Thanissaro Bhikkhu 2010">[http://www.accesstoinsight.org/lib/authors/thanissaro/integrityofemptiness.html Thanissaro Bhikkhu. "The Integrity of Emptiness" Access to Insight, 5 June 2010, Retrieved on 30 July 2013]</ref><blockquote>Emptiness is a mode of perception, a way of looking at experience. It adds nothing to and takes nothing away from the raw data of physical and mental events. You look at events in the mind and the senses with no thought of whether there's anything lying behind them.</blockquote><blockquote>This mode is called emptiness because it's empty of the presuppositions we usually add to experience to make sense of it: the stories and world-views we fashion to explain who we are and the world we live in. Although these stories and views have their uses, the Buddha found that some of the more abstract questions they raise — of our true identity and the reality of the world outside — pull attention away from a direct experience of how events influence one another in the immediate present. Thus they get in the way when we try to understand and solve the problem of suffering.<ref>Thanissaro Bhikkhu, Emptiness, 1997, https://www.accesstoinsight.org/lib/authors/thanissaro/emptiness.html</ref></blockquote>Some Theravādins such as [[David Kalupahana]], see [[Nagarjuna]]'s view of emptiness as compatible with the [[Pali Canon]]. In his analysis of the ''[[Mulamadhyamikakarika]]'', Kalupahana sees Nagarjuna's argument as rooted in the [[Kaccānagotta Sutta]] (which Nagarjuna cites by name). Kalupahana states that Nagarjuna's major goal was to discredit heterodox views of [[Svabhava]] (own-nature) held by the [[Sarvastivadins]] and establish the non-substantiality of all dharmas.<ref>Kalupahana, D. Mulamadhyamakakarika of nagarjuna, page 26.</ref>


Tillman Vetter, although agreeing overall with Gomez's observations, suggests some refinements on historical and doctrinal grounds.{{sfn|Vetter|1988}} First, he notes that neither of these short collections of suttas are homogeneous and hence are not all amenable to Gomez' proposals. According to Vetter, those suttas which do lend support to Gomez probably originated with a heterodox ascetic group that pre-dated the Buddha, and were integrated into the Buddhist Sangha at an early date, bringing with them some suttas that were already in existence and also composing further suttas in which they tried to combine their own teachings with those of the Buddha.{{sfn|Vetter|1988}}
In Theravāda, emptiness as an approach to meditation is also seen as a state in which one is "empty of disturbance." This form of meditation is one in which the meditator becomes concentrated and focuses on the absence or presence of disturbances in their mind, if they find a disturbance they notice it and allow it drop away, this leads to deeper states of calmness.<ref name="Thanissaro Bhikkhu 2010" /> Emptiness is also seen as a way to look at sense experience that does not identify with the "I-making" and "my-making" process of the mind. As a form of meditation, this is developed by perceiving the [[ayatana|six sense spheres]] and their objects as empty of any self, this leads to a [[Arupajhana|formless jhana]] of nothingness and a state of equanimity.<ref name="Thanissaro Bhikkhu 2010" />


Paul Fuller has rejected the arguments of Gomez and Vetter.{{sfn|Fuller|2005}} He finds that
Mathew Kosuta sees the Abhidhamma teachings of the modern Thai teacher Ajaan Sujin Boriharnwanaket as being very similar to the Mahayana emptiness view.<ref>[http://www.ahandfulofleaves.org/documents/Articles/Theravada%20Emptiness_The%20Abhidhammic%20theory%20of%20Ajaan%20Sujin%20Boriharnwanaket_Kosuta_2007.pdf Kosuta, Theravada emptiness, The abhidhammic theory of Ajaan Sujin Boriharnwanaket]</ref>
{{quote|... the Nikayas and the Atthakavagga present the same cognitive attitude toward [[View (Buddhism)|views]], wrong or right.{{sfn|Fuller|2005|p=151}}}}


Alexander Wynne also rejects both of Vetter's claims that the Parayanavagga shows a chronological stratification, and a different attitude toward mindfulness and liberating insight than do other works.{{sfn|Wynne|2007|p=75}}{{refn|group=note|Wynne devotes a chapter to the Parayanavagga.}}
==Indian Mahayana==
{{MahayanaBuddhism}}There are two main sources of Indian Buddhist discussions of emptiness, the [[Mahayana sutras|Mahayana sutra literature]], which is traditionally believed to be the word of the Buddha in Mahayana Buddhism and the shastra literature, which was composed by Buddhist scholars and philosophers.


====Abhidharma====
=== Prajñāpāramitā sūtras ===
The Madhyamaka school has been perhaps simplistically regarded as a reaction against the development of the [[Abhidharma]], especially the [[Sarvāstivādin]]. In the Abhidharma, dharmas are characterized by defining traits (lakṣaṇa) or own-existence (svabhāva), whose ontological status is not dependent upon concepts. The problem with the Abhidharma is not that things are 'independently existent' (a position that most Abhidharma schools would not accept), but rather (from a Madhyamaka perspective) that they are independent from notions. For the Madhyamaka, dharmas are notionally dependent, and further more, their notional dependence entails existential dependence and hence lack of ultimate, true existence.
[[File:Dew on grass Luc Viatour.jpg|thumb|In the Prajñaparamita sutras, the emptiness of phenomena is often illustrated by metaphors like drops of [[dew]].]]
{{Main|Mahayana sutras}}
The [[Prajnaparamita|Prajñāpāramitā]] (Perfection of Wisdom) Sutras taught that all entities, including ''dharmas'', are empty of self or essential core, empty of any intrinsic nature (''[[svabhava]]''), being only conceptual existents or constructs.<ref>Williams, Paul. ''Buddhist Thought.'' Routledge, 2000, pages 68, 134-5.</ref><ref>Williams, Paul. ''Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations 2nd edition.'' Routledge, 2009, pages 52-3.</ref> The notion of [[Prajñā (Buddhism)|prajña]] (wisdom, knowledge) presented in these sutras is a deep non-conceptual understanding of this emptiness, the lack of self or intrinsic nature in all dharmas.<ref name=":0">Williams, Paul. ''Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations 2nd edition.'' Routledge, 2009, pages 50.</ref> The Prajñāpāramitā sutras also use various metaphors to explain the nature of things as emptiness, stating that things are like “illusions” (''māyā'') and “dreams” (''svapna''). The ''Astasahasrika [[Prajnaparamita|Prajñaparamita]],'' possibly the earliest of these sutras'','' states:<blockquote>If he knows the five aggregates as like an illusion, But makes not illusion one thing, and the aggregates another; If, freed from the notion of multiple things, he courses in peace— Then that is his practice of wisdom, the highest perfection.<ref name=":1" /></blockquote>Perceiving dharmas and beings like an illusion (''māyādharmatām'') is termed the "great armor" (''mahāsaṃnaha'') of the [[Bodhisattva]], who is also termed the 'illusory man' (''māyāpuruṣa'').<ref>Orsborn, Matthew Bryan. “Chiasmus in the Early Prajñāpāramitā: Literary Parallelism Connecting Criticism & Hermeneutics in an Early Mahāyāna Sūtra”, University of Hong Kong , 2012, page 165-66.</ref> The [[Diamond Sutra|''Vajracchedikā Prajñāpāramitā Sūtra'']] adds the following similes to describe how all conditioned things are to be contemplated: like a bubble, a shadow, like dew or a flash of lightning.<ref>"The Diamond of Perfect Wisdom Sutra". Chung Tai Translation Committee. </ref> In the worldview of these sutras, though we perceive a world of concrete and discrete objects, these objects are "empty" of the identity imputed by their designated labels.{{sfn|Kalupahan|1994|p=160-169}} In that sense, they are deceptive and like an illusion. The Perfection of Wisdom texts constantly repeat that nothing can be found to ultimately exist in some fundamental way. This applies even to the highest Buddhist concepts:<blockquote>No wisdom can we get hold of, no highest perfection, No Bodhisattva, no thought of enlightenment either. When told of this, if not bewildered and in no way anxious, A Bodhisattva courses in the Well-Gone’s [Sugata’s] wisdom.<ref name=":0" /> (Conze 1973a: 9)</blockquote>Even [[nirvana]] itself is said to be empty and like a dream, as the ''Astasahasrika [[Prajnaparamita|Prajñāpāramitā]]'' says:<blockquote>Even Nirvana, I say, is like a magical illusion, is like a dream. How much more so anything else! …Even if perchance there could be anything more distinguished, of that too I would say that it is like an illusion, like a dream. (trans. Conze: 99).<ref>Williams, Paul, and Anthony J. Tribe. ''Buddhist Thought: A Complete Introduction to the Indian Tradition''. London: Routledge, 2000, p 135.</ref></blockquote>In a famous passage, the [[Heart sutra]], a later but influential [[Prajnaparamita|prajñaparamita]] text, directly states that the [[Skandha|five skandhas]] (along with the five senses, the mind, and the four noble truths) are said to be "empty" (''sunya''):{{quote|Form is emptiness, emptiness is form<br>Emptiness is not separate from form, form is not separate from emptiness<br>Whatever is form is emptiness, whatever is emptiness is form.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.buddhanet.net/e-learning/heartstr.htm |title=The Heart Sutra Prajna Paramita Hrydaya Sutra |publisher=Buddhanet.net |date= |accessdate=2013-02-04}}</ref>{{refn|group=note|Original: "Rupan śūnyatā śūnyatāiva rupan. Rupan na prithak śūnyatā śūnyatā na prithag rupan. Yad rupan sa śūnyatā ya śūnyatā tad rupan."}}{{refn|group=note|The [[Five Skandhas]] are: Form, Feeling, Perceptions, Mental Formations and Consciousness.}}}}In the Prajñāpāramitā sutras the knowledge of emptiness, i.e. [[Prajnaparamita|prajñāpāramitā]] is said to be the fundamental virtue of the bodhisattva, who is said to stand on emptiness by not standing (-stha) on any other dharma (phenomena). Bodhisattvas who practice this perfection of wisdom are said to have several qualities such as the "not taking up" (''aparigṛhīta'') and non-apprehension (''anupalabdhi'') of anything, non-attainment (''aprapti''), not-settling down (''anabhinivesa'') and not relying on any signs (''nimitta,'' mental impressions).<ref>Conze, Edward; The Ontology of the Prajnaparamita, Philosophy East and West Vol.3 (1953) PP.117-129, University of Hawaii Press</ref><ref>Orsborn, Matthew Bryan. “Chiasmus in the Early Prajñāpāramitā: Literary Parallelism Connecting Criticism & Hermeneutics in an Early Mahāyāna Sūtra”, University of Hong Kong , 2012, page 180-81.</ref> Bodhisattvas are also said to be free of fear in the face of the ontological groundlessness of the emptiness doctrine which can easily shock others.<ref>Orsborn, Matthew Bryan. “Chiasmus in the Early Prajñāpāramitā: Literary Parallelism Connecting Criticism & Hermeneutics in an Early Mahāyāna Sūtra”, University of Hong Kong , 2012, page 139-40.</ref>


The relationship between Madhyamaka and Abhidharma is complex; Abhidharmic analysis figures prominently in most Madhyamaka treatises, and authoritative commentators like Candrakīrti emphasize that Abhidharmic categories function as a viable (and favored) system of conventional truths - they are more refined than ordinary categories, and they are not dependent on either the extreme of eternalism or on the extreme view of the discontinuity of karma, as the non-Buddhist categories of the time did. It may be therefore important to understand that Madhyamaka constitutes a continuation of the Abhidharma type of analysis, extending the range of dependent arising to entail (and focus upon) notional dependence. The dependent arising of concepts based on other concepts, rather than the true arising of really existent causes and effects, becomes here the matrix of any possible convention.
=== Other Mahāyāna sutras ===
The '[[Lotus Sutra|''Saddharma Puṇḍarīka Sūtra'']]'''<nowiki/>'''' states:<blockquote>“Furthermore, the bodhisattva mahāsattvas perceive the emptiness of all dharmas in their true aspect. All things are unerring, unmoving, nonreturning, irreversible, and like empty space which lacks substance. They are beyond all language. They are not produced, nor do they emerge, nor do they arise. They do not have any name or mark, and in reality they have no substance. They are immeasurable, limitless, without obstacles or obstructions. They exist only through dependent origination, arising through error. That is why I teach the permanent joy of perceiving the aspects of all existent things in this way.”<ref>Tsugunari Kubo, Akira Yuyama (trans.), THE LOTUS SUTRA (Taishō Volume 9, Number 262) Translated from the Chinese of Kumārajiva, BDK, p. 194.</ref></blockquote>


====Prajñāpāramitā====
In the ''[[Śūraṅgama Samādhi Sūtra]]'' sutra, the Buddha says:<blockquote>"All the dharmas are empty, like phantasms, and only exist in conjunction with each other. They have no creator, but arise entirely due to the discrimination of conceptual thought. Because there is no master [of consciousness, the myriad dharmas] appear according to one's thoughts."<ref>Harrison, Paul (trans) BDK English Tripitaka 25-11, 25-111, The Pratyutpanna Samadhi Sutra Translated by Lokaksema Translated from the Chinese (Taisho Volume 13, Number 418).</ref></blockquote>In the ''[[Pratyutpanna Samādhi Sūtra]]'' the Buddha says the following verses''''':'''''<blockquote>Mind does not know mind; With mind one cannot see mind. Mind giving rise to conceptions is stupidity; </blockquote><blockquote>Free of conceptions it is nirvana. There is nothing fixed or firm in these dharmas; They are forever located in thinking. </blockquote><blockquote>When one understands emptiness, One is altogether free of conceptual thinking.<ref>McRae, John, BDK English Tripitaka 25-11, 25-111 The Surangama Samadhi Sutra Translated by Kumarajiva Translated from the Chinese (Taisho Volume 15, Number 642) p. 21.</ref></blockquote>The [[Avatamsaka Sutra|''Avataṃsaka Sūtra'']] states:
Madhyamaka thought is also closely related to a number of Mahāyāna sources; traditionally, the Prajñāpāramitāsūtras are the literature most closely associated with Madhyamaka – understood, at least in part, as an exegetical complement to those Sūtras. Traditional accounts also depict Nāgārjuna as retrieving some of the larger Prajñāpāramitāsūtras from the world of the Nāgas (explaining in part the etymology of his name).
'''<nowiki/><nowiki/>'''<blockquote>The nature of things is fundamentally empty and null, with no grasping and no vision. The emptiness of inherent nature is Buddha; It cannot be assessed in thought. If one knows the inherent nature of all things is like this, This person will not be affected by any afflictions.<ref>Cleary, Thomas, The Flower Ornament Scripture: A Translation of the Avatamsaka Sutra, 1993, p. 373.</ref></blockquote>The ''Avataṃsaka'' also elaborates on how a [[bodhisattva]] contemplates emptiness in their practice:
Prajñā or ‘higher cognition’ is a recurrent term in Buddhist texts, explained as a synonym of Abhidharma, ‘insight’ (vipaśyanā) and ‘analysis of the dharmas’ (dharmapravicaya). Within a specifically Mahāyāna context, Prajñā figures as the most prominent in a list of Six Pāramitās (‘perfections’ or ‘perfect masteries’) that a Bodhisattva needs to cultivate in order to eventually achieve Buddhahood. Madhyamaka offers conceptual tools to analyze all possible elements of existence, allowing the practitioner to elicit through reasoning and contemplation the type of view that the Sūtras express more authoritatively (being considered word of the Buddha) but less explicitly (not offering corroborative arguments).
<nowiki/>'''<nowiki/><nowiki/>'''<blockquote>"Thus do enlightening beings benefit the living, yet without any concept of self or any concept of sentient beings, or any concept of existence, or any concept of life, without various concepts-no concept of personality, no concept of person, no concept of human being, no concept of doer or receiver-they only observe the infinity of the realm of reality and the realm of sentient beings, their emptiness, absence of existents, signlessness, insubstantiality, indeterminacy, non-dependence, and noncreation.</blockquote><blockquote>When they perform this contemplation, they do not see themselves, they do not see anything given , they do not see a receiver, they do not see a field of blessings, they do not see a deed, they do not see any reward, they do not see any result, they do not see a great result, they do not see a small result."<ref>Cleary, Thomas, The Flower Ornament Scripture: A Translation of the Avatamsaka Sutra, 1993, p. 456.</ref></blockquote>
The vast Prajñāpāramitā literature emphasizes the development of higher cognition in the context of the Bodhisattva path; thematically, its focus on the emptiness of all dharmas is closely related to the Madhyamaka approach.


===Mādhyamaka school===
====Pyrrhonism====
Because of the high degree of similarity between Madhyamaka and [[Pyrrhonism]],<ref>Adrian Kuzminski, ''Pyrrhonism: How the Ancient Greeks Reinvented Buddhism'' 2008</ref> [[Thomas McEvilley]]<ref>Thomas McEvilley, ''The Shape of Ancient Thought'' 2002 pp499-505</ref> and Matthew Neale<ref>https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=NMZwyPdY7eg&t=52s</ref> suspect that Nāgārjuna was influenced by Greek Pyrrhonist texts imported into India. [[Pyrrho]] of Elis (c. 360-c. 270 BCE), who is credited with founding this school of [[Philosophical skepticism|skeptical philosophy]], was himself influenced by Buddhist philosophy during his stay in India with [[Alexander the Great]]'s army.
[[File:Nagarjuna and Aryadeva as Two Great Indian Buddhist Scholastics - Google Art Project.jpg|thumb|[[Nagarjuna|Nāgārjuna]] and [[Aryadeva|Āryadeva]], two classic [[Indian philosophy|Indian philosophers]] of the Buddhist emptiness doctrine.]]
{{Main|Madhyamaka}}
Mādhyamaka is a [[Mahayana|Mahāyāna]] [[Buddhist philosophy|Buddhist school of philosophy]] established by the Indian Buddhist philosopher [[Nagarjuna|Nāgārjuna]] which focuses on the analysis of emptiness, and was thus also known as ''Śūnyatavāda''.<ref name="Buddhist Thought">[[Paul Williams (British professor)|Williams, Paul]] (2000). ''Buddhist Thought'' Routledge, p140.</ref><ref>Wynne, Alexander, Early Buddhist Teaching as Proto-sunyavada.</ref>


===Indian Madhyamaka===
[[Nāgārjuna]] goal was to refute the essentialism of certain [[Abhidharma]] schools and the Hindu [[Nyaya]] school.<ref>Wasler, Joseph. ''Nagarjuna in Context.'' New York: Columibia University Press. 2005, pgs. 225-263.</ref> His best-known work is the ''[[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]]'' (MMK), in which he used the ''[[Prasaṅgika|reductio ad absurdum]]'' to show the non-substantiality of everything. [[Nāgārjuna]] equated the emptiness of [[Dhamma theory|dharmas]] with their [[dependent origination]], and thus with their being devoid any permanent substance or primary, substantial existence (''[[Svabhāva|svabhava]]'').{{sfn|Kalupahana|1992|p=120}}<ref>Tsondru, Mabja. ''Ornament of Reason.'' Snow Lion Publications. 2011, pages 66-71, 447-477.</ref><ref>Williams, Paul, Buddhist Thought: A Complete Introduction to the Indian Tradition, 2002, p 142.</ref>{{refn|group=note|[[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]] 24:18}} As [[Nagarjuna|Nāgārjuna]] writes in the MMK: <blockquote>We state that conditioned origination is emptiness. It is mere designation depending on something, and it is the middle path. (24.18) </blockquote><blockquote>Since nothing has arisen without depending on something, there is nothing that is not empty. (24.19) <ref>Bronkhorst (2009), p. 146.</ref></blockquote>Nāgārjuna's Mādhyamaka states that since things have the nature of lacking true existence or own being (''niḥsvabhāva''), all things are mere conceptual constructs (''prajñaptimatra'') because they are just impermanent collections of causes and conditions.<ref>Williams, Paul, Buddhist Thought: A Complete Introduction to the Indian Tradition, 2002, p 141.</ref> Because of this, Mādhyamaka is also known as ''Niḥsvabhāvavāda''. This also applies to the principle of causality itself, since ''everything'' is dependently originated.<ref>Williams, Paul. ''Buddhist Thought.'' Routledge 2000, page 142.</ref> If one is unaware of this, things may seem to arise as existents, remain for a time and then subsequently perish. In reality, dependently originated phenomena do not arise or remain as inherently existent phenomena and yet they still appear as a flow of conceptual constructs.<ref name="Tsondru, Mabja 2011, pages 56-58">Tsondru, Mabja. ''Ornament of Reason.'' Snow Lion Publications. 2011, pages 56-58, 405-417.</ref><ref>Williams, Paul, Buddhist Thought: A Complete Introduction to the Indian Tradition, 2002, p 151-152.</ref>{{refn|group=note|Chapter 21 of the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā goes into the reasoning behind this.<ref name="Tsondru, Mabja 2011, pages 56-58"/>}} Thus both existence and nihilism are ruled out.<ref>Tsondru, Mabja. ''Ornament of Reason.'' Snow Lion Publications. 2011, pages 56-58, 405-417</ref><ref>unclear</ref> Any enduring [[Svabhāva|essential nature]] would prevent the process of dependent origination, or any kind of origination at all. For things would simply always have been, and will always continue to be, without any change.<ref>Tsondru, Mabja. ''Ornament of Reason.'' Snow Lion Publications. 2011, pages 40-41, 322-333.</ref>{{refn|group=note|Nāgārjuna equates svabhāva (essence) with bhāva (existence) in Chapter 15 of the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā}} Like with other Buddhists, for Nāgārjuna, the realization of emptiness is a key understanding which allows one to reach liberation:<blockquote>Liberation (moksa) results from the cessation of actions (karman) and defilements (klesa). Actions and defilements result from representations {vikalpa). These from false imagining (prapañca). False imagining stops in emptiness (sunyata). (18.5)<ref>Bronkhorst (2009), p. 148.</ref></blockquote>As noted by Roger Jackson, non-Buddhist and Buddhist writers have argued that the Mādhyamaka philosophy is nihilistic.<ref>{{cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=oyJjCx_tEiMC&pg=PA4|title=The Essentials of Buddhist Philosophy|author=Junjirō Takakusu|publisher=Motilal Banarsidass|year=1998|isbn=978-81-208-1592-6|pages=4, 105–107}}</ref><ref>{{cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=i9gm9CzNd5EC|title=Ways of Thinking of Eastern Peoples: India, China, Tibet, Japan|author=Hajime Nakamura|publisher=Motilal Banarsidass|year=1991|isbn=978-81-208-0764-8|pages=590–591 footnote 20}}, Quote: "Already in India, 'sunyata' was liable to be misunderstood as nothingness or nihil'. (...) The [[Sarvastivada|Sarvastivadins]] of Hinayana Buddhism viewed the Madhyamika school as 'one that argues that everything is nothing. (...) It is only natural that most of the Western scholars call the ''prajnaparamita sutra'' or the doctrine of the Madhyamika school nihilism since criticisms were already expressed in India. Against such criticisms, however, Nagarjuna, founder of the Madhyamika school says, 'you are ignorant of the function of sunyata, the meaning of the sunyata and sunyata itself'."</ref><ref>[[User:Javierfv1212/sandbox#CITEREFJackson1993|Jackson 1993]], p. 57.</ref> This view has been challenged by other writers, who state that Mādhyamaka is not nihilistic but it is a middle way between nihilism and eternalism.<ref>{{cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=CjkRAQAAIAAJ|title=Mādhyamika Śūnyatā, a Reappraisal: A Reappraisal of Mādhyamika Philosophical Enterprise with Special Reference to Nāgārjuna and Chandrakīrti|author=G. C. Nayak|date=2001|publisher=Indian Council of Philosophical Research|isbn=978-81-85636-47-4|pages=9–12}}</ref> Some scholars interpret emptiness as described by Nāgārjuna as a Buddhist transcendental [[Absolute (philosophy)|absolute]], while other scholars consider it a mistake.<ref name="ferrer102">Jorge Noguera Ferrer, ''Revisioning Transpersonal Theory: A Participatory Vision of Human Spirituality.'' SUNY Press, 2002, page 102-103.</ref> David Kalupahana states that this topic has been debated by ancient and medieval Buddhist metaphysicians, with a divergence of views; emptiness is a view, adds Kalupahana, but "holding up emptiness as an absolute or ultimate truth without reference to that which is empty is the last thing either the Buddha or Nāgārjuna would advocate".<ref>[[David J. Kalupahana]], ''Mulamadhyamakakarika of Nagarjuna: The Philosophy of the Middle Way.'' SUNY Press, 1986, pages 48-50.</ref>


====Nāgārjuna====
According to Paul Williams, Nāgārjuna associates emptiness with the [[Two truths doctrine|ultimate truth]] but his conception of emptiness is not some kind of [[Absolute (philosophy)|Absolute]], but rather it is the very absence of true existence with regards to the conventional reality of things and events in the world.<ref>Williams, Paul, Buddhist Thought: A Complete Introduction to the Indian Tradition, 2002, p 147.</ref> For him the phenomenal world is the limited truth (''samvrtisatya'') and does not really exist in the highest reality (''paramarthasatya'') and yet it has a kind of conventional reality which has its uses for reaching liberation. This limited truth includes everything, including the Buddha himself, the teachings (Dharma), liberation and even Nāgārjuna's own arguments.<ref>Bronkhorst (2009), p. 149.</ref> This [[Two truths doctrine|two truth schema]] which did not deny the importance of convention allowed him to defend himself against charges of [[nihilism]], understanding both correctly meant seeing the middle way:<blockquote>"Without relying upon convention, the ultimate fruit is not taught. Without understanding the ultimate, nirvana is not attained."<ref>Bronkhorst (2009), p. 150.</ref></blockquote>Because of his philosophical work, Nāgārjuna is seen by some modern interpreters as restoring the [[Middle way]] of the Buddha, which had become influenced by absolutist metaphysical tendencies of schools like the [[Sarvastivada|Sarvastivadins]].{{sfn|Kalupahana|1994}}{{sfn|Kalupahana|1992|p=120}}
Kalupahana has argued that Nāgārjuna's intention was not to establish an [[ontology]] or [[epistemology]], but to free the Buddhist [[soteriology]] from essentialist notions which obscured the [[Middle way|Buddhist Middle Way]]:{{sfn|Kalupahana|1994|p=169}}


====Āryadeva====
Nāgārjuna is also famous for arguing that his philosophy of emptiness was not a view, and that he in fact did not take any position or thesis whatsoever since this would just be another form of clinging. In his ''Vigrahavyavartani'' Nāgārjuna outright states that he has no thesis (''pratijña'') to prove.<ref>Williams, Paul, Buddhist Thought: A Complete Introduction to the Indian Tradition, 2002, p 146.</ref> Likewise in his ''Sixty Stanzas on Reasoning'', Nāgārjuna says:<blockquote>"By taking any standpoint whatsoever, you will be snatched by the cunning snakes of the afflictions. Those whose minds have no standpoint, will not be caught."<ref>Brunnholzl, Karl, The Center of the Sunlit Sky: Madhyamaka in the Kagyu Tradition, Shambhala, 2004, page 34.</ref></blockquote>Randall Collins states that for Nāgārjuna, ultimate reality was emptiness, which is not a negation, but the premise that "no concepts are intelligible".<ref name="collins221">Randall Collins, ''The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change.'' Harvard University Press, 2000, pages 221-222.</ref> According to Ferrer, Nāgārjuna criticized those whose mind held any "positions and beliefs", suggesting liberation is "avoidance of all views", and explaining emptiness as follows:<ref>Jorge Noguera Ferrer, ''Revisioning Transpersonal Theory: A Participatory Vision of Human Spirituality.'' SUNY Press, 2002, pages 102. The quote is from the [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]].</ref>{{quote|The Victorious Ones have announced that emptiness is the relinquishing of all [[View (Buddhism)|views]]. Those who are possessed of the view of emptiness are said to be incorrigible.}}
Nāgārjuna's pupil [[Āryadeva]] (3rd century CE) emphasized the [[Bodhisattva|Bodhisattva-ideal]]. His works are regarded as a supplement to Nāgārjuna's,{{sfn|Warder|2000|p=368}} on which he commented.{{sfn|Rizzi|1988|p=2}} Āryadeva also refuted the theories of non-Buddhist Indian philosophical schools.{{sfn|Rizzi|1988|p=2}}


====Buddhapālita and Bhāvaviveka====
This idea would become a central point of debate for later Madhyamika philosophers. After Nāgārjuna, other Madhyamikas like [[Aryadeva|Āryadeva]] (3rd century CE) commented and expanded Nāgārjuna's system. An influential commentator on Nāgārjuna was [[Buddhapālita]] (470–550) who has been interpreted as developing the '[[Svatantrika–Prasaṅgika distinction|prāsaṅgika]]' approach to Nāgārjuna's works, which argues that Madhyamaka critiques of essentialism are done only through [[reductio ad absurdum]] arguments. Like Nāgārjuna, instead of putting forth any positive position of his own, [[Buddhapālita]] merely seeks to show how all philosophical positions are untenable and self contradictory without putting forth a positive thesis.<ref name=":3">Hayes, Richard, "Madhyamaka", ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (Spring 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <<nowiki>https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/madhyamaka/</nowiki>>.</ref>
[[Buddhapālita]] (470–550) has been understood as the origin of the prāsaṅgika approach.{{sfn|Rizzi|1988|p=3}} He was criticized by [[Bhāvaviveka]] (ca.500–ca.578), who argued for the use of syllogisms "to set one's own doctrinal stance".{{sfn|Rizzi|1988|p=4}} Bhāvya/Bhāvaviveka was influenced by the [[Yogācāra|Yogācāra school]].


The opposing approaches of Buddhapālita and Bhāvya are explained by later Tibetan doxographers as the origin of a subdivision of Madhyamaka into two schools, the [[Prasaṅgika|{{IAST|Prāsaṅgika}}]] and the [[Svātantrika]].
He is often contrasted with the works of [[Bhāviveka|Bhāvaviveka]] (c. 500 – c. 578), who argued for the use of logical arguments using the [[pramana]] based epistemology of Indian logicians like [[Dignāga]]. [[Bhāviveka|Bhāvaviveka]] argued that Madhyamika's could put forth positive arguments of one's own, instead of just criticizing other's arguments, a tactic called ''vitaṇḍā'' (attacking) which was seen in bad form in Indian philosophical circles. He argued that the position of a Madhyamaka was simply that phenomena are devoid of an inherent nature.<ref name=":3" /> This approach has been labeled the [[Svatantrika–Prasaṅgika distinction|svātantrika]] style of Madhyamaka by Tibetan philosophers and commentators. Another influential commentator, [[Chandrakirti|Candrakīrti]] (<abbr>c.</abbr> 600–650), critiqued Bhāvaviveka's adoption of the [[pramana]] tradition on the grounds that it contained a subtle essentialism and argued that Madhyamikas must make no positive assertions and need not construct formal arguments.<ref>Garfield, Jay; Edelglass, William; The Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy, p. 213</ref>
===Yogacara school===
{{Main|Yogacara}}
The central text of the [[Yogachara|Yogacara]] school, the [[Sandhinirmocana Sutra|''Saṃdhinirmocana-sūtra'']], explains emptiness in terms of the three natures theory, stating that its purpose is to "establish the doctrine of the three-own-beings (''trisvabhāva'') in terms of their lack of own-nature (''niḥsvabhāvatā'')."<ref name=":4">King, Richard, Early Yogācāra and its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School, Philosophy East & West Volume 44, Number 4 October 1994 PP.659-683.</ref> According to Andrew Skilton, in Yogacara, emptiness is the "absence of duality between perceiving subject [''grāhaka, 'dzin-pa''] and the perceived object [''grāhya, bzhung-ba'']."<ref>Skilton, Andrew (1994). ''A Concise History of Buddhism''. Windhorse Publications, London:. pg 124</ref> This is seen in the following quote from the [[Madhyanta-vibhaga-karika|Madhyāntavibhāga]]: <blockquote>There exists the imagination of the unreal, there is no duality, but there is emptiness, even in this there is that.<ref name=":4" /></blockquote>In his commentary, the Yogacara philosopher [[Vasubandhu]] explains that imagination of the unreal (''abhūta-parikalpa'') is the "discrimination between the duality of grasped and grasper." Emptiness is said to be "the imagination of the unreal that is lacking in the form of being graspable or grasper." Thus in Yogacara, it can be said that emptiness is mainly that subject and object and all experiences which are seen in the subject object modality are empty.<ref name=":4" />


====Candrakīrti====
Everything we conceive of is the result of the working of the [[Eight Consciousnesses]].{{refn|group=note|Translations do differ, which makes a difference. [[Vijñāna]] can be translated as "consciousness", but also as "discernement".{{sfn|Kalupahana|1992}}}} The "things" we are conscious of are "mere concepts" (vijñapti), not 'the thing in itself'.{{sfn|Kalupahana|1992}} In this sense, our experiences are empty and false, they do not reveal the true nature of things as an enlightened person would see them, which would be [[Nondualism|non-dual]], without the imputed subject object distinction.
[[Candrakīrti]] (600–c. 650) wrote the Prasannapadā (Clear Words), a highly influential commentary on the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā. This commentary is central in the understanding of Madhyamaka in Tibetan Buddhism.


====Śāntideva====
The Yogacara school philosophers Asaṅga and Vasubandhu criticized those in the Madhymamika school who "adhere to non-existence" (''nāstikas, vaināśkas'') and sought to move away from their negative interpretation of emptiness because they feared any philosophy of 'universal denial' (''sarva-vaināśika'') would stray into '[[nihilism]]' (''ucchedavāda''), an extreme which was not the [[Middle Way|middle way]].<ref name=":4" /> Yogacarins differed from Madhyamikas in positing that there really was something which could be said to 'exist' in experience, namely some kind of nonobjective and empty perception. This Yogacara conception of emptiness, which states that there is ''something'' that exists (mainly, ''vijñapti'', mental construction), and that it is empty, can be seen in the following statement of Vasubandhu:<blockquote>Thus, when something is absent [in a receptacle], then one, seeing that [receptacle] as devoid of that thing, perceives that [receptacle] as it is, and recognises that [receptacle], which is left over, as it is, namely as something truly existing there.<ref name=":4" /></blockquote>This tendency can also be seen in [[Asanga]], which argues in his ''Bodhisattvabhūmi'' that there must be something that exists which is described as empty:<blockquote>Emptiness is logical when one thing is devoid of another because of that [other's] absence and because of the presence of the empty thing itself.<ref name=":4" /></blockquote>Asanga also states:<blockquote>The nonexistence of duality is indeed the existence of nonexistence; this is the definition of emptiness. It is neither existence, nor nonexistence, neither different nor identical.<ref name=":4" /></blockquote>This "existence of nonexistence" definition of emptiness can also be seen in Asanga's [[Abhidharma-samuccaya|''Abhidharmasamuccaya'']] where he states that emptiness is "the non-existence of the self, and the existence of the no-self."<ref name=":4" />
[[Shantideva|Śāntideva]] (end 7th century – first half 8th century) is well known for his [[Bodhisattvacaryāvatāra]], ''A Guide to the [[Bodhisattva]]'s Way of Life''. He united "a deep religiousness and joy of exposure together with the unquestioned Madhyamaka orthodoxy".{{sfn|Rizzi|1988|p=5}}


====Shantarakshita====
In the sixth century, scholarly debates between Yogacarins and Madhyamikas centered on the status and reality of the ''paratantra-svabhāva'' (the "dependent nature"), with Madhyamika's like Bhāvaviveka criticizing the views of Yogacarins like [[Dharmapala of Nalanda|Dharmapāla]] of Nalanda as reifying of [[Pratītyasamutpāda|dependent origination]].<ref name=":4" />
A [[Yogacara|Yogācāra]] and Mādhyamaka synthesis was posited by [[Shantarakshita]] in the 8th century{{refn|group=note|Alex Trisoglio: "In the 8th century, Shantarakshita went to Tibet and founded the monastery at Samyé. He was not a direct disciple of Bhavaviveka, but the disciple of one of his disciples. He combined the Madhyamika-Svatantrika and Cittamatra schools, and created a new school of Madhyamika called Svatantrika-Yogachara-Madhyamika. His disciple Kamalashila, who wrote The Stages of Meditation upon Madhyamika (uma’i sgom rim), developed his ideas further, and together they were very influential in Tibet."{{cite book|last=Khyentse Rinpoche|first=Dzongsar Jamyang|title=Introduction to the Middle Way: Chandrakirti's Madhyamakavatara with Commentary|year=2003|publisher=Khyentse Foundation|location=Dordogne, France|pages=8|url=http://www.siddharthasintent.org/|edition=1st|editor=Alex Trisoglio|accessdate=7 January 2013|format=PDF|chapter=Introduction}}}} and may have been common at [[Nalanda]] University at that time. Like the Prāsaṅgika, this view approaches ultimate truth through the prasaṅga method, yet when speaking of conventional reality they may make autonomous statements like the earlier Svātantrika and Yogācāra approaches.


This was different from the earlier Svatantrika in that the conventional truth was described in terms of the theory of [[consciousness-only]] instead of the tenets of Svatantrika, though neither was used to analyze for ultimate truth.
=== Yogacara-Madhyamaka synthesis ===
The eighth century saw a synthesis of the two schools, beginning with the work of the Buddhist philosopher [[Jñānagarbha]] who, like Bhāvaviveka, also adopted some of the terminology of the Buddhist pramana tradition, in his time best represented by [[Dharmakirti|Dharmakīrti]].<ref name=":3" /> [[Jñānagarbha]] and his student [[Śāntarakṣita]] were mainly Madhyamikas however, and regarded Yogacara and pramana theories as useful doctrines which could prepare one for the ultimate truth of Madhyamaka emptiness.<ref name=":3" />


For example, they may assert that all phenomena are nothing but the "play of mind" and hence empty of concrete existence—and that mind is in turn empty of defining characteristics. But in doing so, they're careful to point out that any such example would be an approximate ultimate and not the true ultimate. By making such autonomous statements, Yogācāra-Svatantrika-Madhyamaka is often mistaken as a Svātantrika or Yogācāra view, even though a Prāsaṅgika approach was used in analysis.{{sfn|Shantarakshita|2005|p=117-122}} This view is thus a synthesis of Madhyamaka and [[Yogacara|Yogācāra]].
===Buddha-nature===
{{Main|Buddha-nature|Tathāgatagarbha Sutras}}


===Tibetan Buddhism===
An influential division of 1st-millennium CE Buddhist texts develop the notion of ''Tathāgatagarbha'' or Buddha-nature.<ref name="PW_103_109">{{cite book|author=Paul Williams|title=Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=GMN-AgAAQBAJ|year=2008|publisher=Routledge|isbn=978-1-134-25056-1|pages=103–109}}</ref><ref>{{cite book|author=S. K. Hookham|title=The Buddha Within: Tathagatagarbha Doctrine According to the Shentong Interpretation of the Ratnagotravibhaga|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=JqLa4xWot-YC&pg=PA96|year=1991|publisher=State University of New York Press|isbn=978-0-7914-0357-0|pages=100–104}}</ref> The ''Tathāgatagarbha'' doctrine, at its earliest probably appeared about the later part of the 3rd century CE, and is verifiable in Chinese translations of 1st millennium CE.<ref name="paulwilliamsp104">{{cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=GMN-AgAAQBAJ|title=Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations|author=Paul Williams|publisher=Routledge|year=2008|isbn=978-1-134-25056-1|page=104}}</ref> The Tathāgatagarbha is the topic of the ''[[Tathāgatagarbha sūtras]]'', where the title itself means a ''garbha'' (womb, matrix, seed) containing ''Tathāgata'' (Buddha). In the ''Tathāgatagarbha sūtras'' sutras the perfection of the wisdom of not-self is stated to be the true self. The ultimate goal of the path is characterized using a range of positive language that had been used in Indian philosophy previously by [[Essentialism|essentialist]] philosophers, but which was now transmuted into a new Buddhist vocabulary to describe a being who has successfully completed the Buddhist path.<ref>Sallie B. King (1997),[https://web.archive.org/web/20070927131119/http://www.nanzan-u.ac.jp/SHUBUNKEN/publications/nlarc/pdf/Pruning%20the%20bodhi%20tree/Pruning%209.pdf ''The Doctrine of Buddha Nature is Impeccably Buddhist'']. In: Jamie Hubbard (ed.), Pruning the Bodhi Tree: The Storm Over Critical Buddhism, Univ of Hawaii Press 1997, pp. 174-192. {{ISBN|0824819497}}</ref> These [[Sutra]]s suggest, states Paul Williams, that 'all sentient beings contain a ''Tathāgata'' as their 'essence, core or essential inner nature'.<ref name="paulwilliamsp104" /> The ''Tathāgatagarbha'' sutras presents a further developed understanding of emptiness, wherein the Buddha Nature, the Buddha and Liberation are seen as transcending the realm of emptiness, i.e. of the conditioned and dependently originated phenomena.{{sfn|Hopkins|2006}}


====Tibetan classification of schools====
One of these texts, the ''[[Angulimaliya Sutra]],'' contrasts between empty phenomena such as the moral and emotional afflictions (''[[Kleshas (Buddhism)|kleshas]]''), which are like ephemeral hailstones, and the enduring, eternal Buddha, which is like a precious gem:
{{main article|Svatantrika-Prasaṅgika_distinction}}
Madhyamaka thought has been categorized variously in India and Tibet.{{refn|group=note|In his Tattvaratnāvalī, the Indian scholar Advayavajra classified Madhyamaka into "those who uphold non-duality from the simile of illusion" (''māyopamādvayavādin'') and "those who uphold non-placement into any dharma" (''sarvadharmāpratiṣṭhānavādin''); furthermore, in the Madhyamakaṣaṭka he envisaged a specifically Vajrayāna type of Madhyamaka.{{citation needed|date=May 2015}}}} In Tibetan Buddhism a major difference is being made between "Svātantrika-Madhyamaka" and "Prasaṅgika-Madhyamaka." Yet, the classification is more complicated, and is described by Guy Newman as follows:
* [[Rangtong]], a term introduced by [[Dolpopa]], which rejects any inherent existing self or nature.{{sfn|Cornu|2001|p=146-147}} This includes:
:* [[Svātantrika]]
::* Sautrantika Svātantrika Madhyamaka - [[Bhāviveka]]
::* Yogācāra Svātantrika Madhyamaka - [[Śāntarakṣita]] and [[Kamalaśīla]], the oldest Buddhist teachings to be introduced in Tibet{{sfn|Cornu|2001|p=138}}
:* [[Prasaṅgika]], based on [[Buddhapālita]] and [[Candrakīrti]]. Within prasangika, a further division can be made:
::* Intellectual emptiness, which is realized by mere negation. This is the view of Tsong Khapa and the Gelugpa school, which rejects any statements on an absolute reality beyond mere emptiness.{{sfn|Cornu|2001|p=145}}
::* Experiential emptiness, which is realized when the understanding of intellectual emptiness gives way to the recognition of the true [[nature of mind]], c.q. [[rigpa]]. This is the view of Nyingma (Dzogchen) and Sakya.{{sfn|Cornu|2001|p=145}}
* [[Shentong]], systematised by Dolpopa, and based on [[Buddha-nature]] teachings and influenced by Śāntarakṣita's Yogacara-Madhyamaka. It states that the [[nature of mind]] shines through when emptiness has been realized. This approach is dominant in the Jonang school, and can also be found in the Kagyu (Mahamudra) tradition.{{sfn|Hookam|1991}}{{sfn|Brunnhölzl|2004}}{{sfn|Cornu|2001}}


The Madhyamika philosophy obtained a central position in all the Tibetan schools, but with two distinct variations, namely [[shentong]], and the later Gelugpa emphasis on a strict [[Prasangika]] interpretation of emptiness. Shentong is a further developed Yogacara-Madhyamaka which incorporates Buddha-nature teachings, and states that the reality which is laid bare by understanding emptiness is [[Nature of mind (Buddhism)|luminous awareness]] and truly existing. Shentong teachings are still transmitted in the [[Nyingma]], [[Kagyu]], and [[Jonang|Jonang school]]. Tsongkhapa, and the subsequent Gelugpa tradition, opposes this notion of self-luminous awareness, and sees its own interpretation as the final truth on ''sunyata''.
{{quote|The tens of millions of afflictive emotions like hail-stones are empty. The phenomena in the class of non-virtues, like hail-stones, quickly disintegrate. Buddha, like a vaidurya jewel, is permanent ... The liberation of a buddha also is form ... do not make a discrimination of non-division, saying, "The character of liberation is empty".'{{sfn|Hopkins|2006|p=210}}|sign=|source=}}


Although presented as a divide in doctrines, the major difference between svātantrika and prasangika may be between two style of reasoning and arguing, while the division itself is exclusively Tibetan. Tibetan scholars were aware of alternative Madhyamaka sub-classifications, but later Tibetan doxography emphasizes the nomenclature of prāsaṅgika versus svātantrika. No conclusive evidence can show the existence of an Indian antecedent, and it is not certain to what degree individual writers in Indian and Tibetan discussion held each of these views and if they held a view generally or only in particular instances. Both Prāsaṅgikas and Svātantrikas cited material in the āgamas in support of their arguments.{{sfn|Gombrich|1996|p=27-28}}
The notion of Buddha-nature and its interpretation was and continues to be widely debated in all schools of Mahayana Buddhism. Some traditions interpret the doctrine to be equivalent to emptiness (like the Tibetan [[Gelug]] schools), the positive language of the texts ''Tathagatagarbha sutras'' are then interpreted as being provisional, not ultimate. Other schools however, see buddha nature as being an ultimate teaching and see it as an eternal, true self (the [[Jonang]] school).


====Svātantrika====
Likewise, western scholars have been divided in their interpretation of the ''Tathāgatagarbha,'' since the doctrine of an 'essential nature' in every living being appears to be confusing, since it seems to be equivalent to a 'Self',{{refn|group=note|Paul Williams: "Some texts of the ''tathagatagarbha'' literature, such as the ''Mahaparinirvana Sutra'' actually refer to an ''atman'', though other texts are careful to avoid the term. This would be in direct opposition to the general teachings of Buddhism on ''anatta''. Indeed, the distinctions between the general Indian concept of ''atman'' and the popular Buddhist concept of Buddha-nature are often blurred to the point that writers consider them to be synonymous."<ref>{{cite book|author=Paul Williams|title=Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=GMN-AgAAQBAJ|year=2008|publisher=Routledge|isbn=978-1-134-25056-1|pages=104–105, 108}}</ref>}}<ref>{{cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=A7UKjtA0QDwC|title=Buddhism: Beliefs and Practices|author=Merv Fowler|publisher=Sussex Academic Press|year=1999|isbn=978-1-898723-66-0|pages=101–102}}</ref> which seems to contradict the doctrines in a vast majority of Buddhist texts. Some scholars, however, view such teachings as metaphorical, not to be taken literally.{{sfn|Hopkins|2006}} According to some scholars, the Buddha nature which these sutras discuss, does not represent a substantial self ([[Ātman (Hinduism)|ātman]]). Rather, it is a positive expression of emptiness, and represents the potentiality to realize Buddhahood through Buddhist practices. In this view, the intention of the teaching of Buddha nature is soteriological rather than theoretical.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://budsas.org/ebud/ebdha191.htm|title=The Significance Of 'Tathagatagarbha' —- A Positive Expression Of Sunyata|author=Heng-Ching Shih|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20130807082256/http://budsas.org/ebud/ebdha191.htm|archivedate=2013-08-07}}</ref><ref name="nanzan-u.ac.jp">{{cite web|url=http://www.nanzan-u.ac.jp/SHUBUNKEN/publications/nlarc/pdf/Pruning%20the%20bodhi%20tree/Pruning%209.pdf|title=The Doctrine of Buddha Nature is Impeccably Buddhist. In: Jamie Hubbard (ed.), Pruning the Bodhi Tree: The Storm Over Critical Buddhism, Univ of Hawaii Press 1997, pp. 174-192. ISBN 0824819497|last=King|first=Sallie B.|format=PDF|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20070927131119/http://www.nanzan-u.ac.jp/SHUBUNKEN/publications/nlarc/pdf/Pruning%20the%20bodhi%20tree/Pruning%209.pdf|archivedate=2007-09-27}}</ref> According to others, the potential of salvation depends on the ontological reality of a salvific, abiding core reality — the Buddha-nature, empty of all mutability and error, fully present within all beings.<ref>Yamamoto, Kosho (1975). ''Mahayanism'', Tokyo: Karin Bunko, p.56</ref>
{{main article|Svatantrika}}


[[Bhavaviveka]] (c. 500 – c. 578) is the first person to whom this view is attributed, as they are laid out in his commentaries on Nāgārjuna and his critiques of Buddhapalita. ''Svātantrika'' in Sanskrit refers to autonomy and was translated back into Sanskrit from the equivalent Tibetan term.{{sfn|Shantarakshita|2005|p=131-141}}
==Tibetan Buddhism==
[[File:Appearance of sky for weather forecast, Dhaka, Bangladesh.JPG|thumb|In Tibetan Buddhism, emptiness is often symbolized by and compared to the open sky<ref>Vessantara; Meeting the Buddhas: A Guide to Buddhas, Bodhisattvas, and Tantric Deities. "They [conditioned things] are sky-like, and un-graspable, like clouds."</ref> which is associated with [[openness]] and [[freedom]].<ref>The Collected Works of Chogyam Trungpa: Volume Four, Dawn of tantra, page 366</ref>]]


The Svātantrika states that conventional phenomena are understood to have a conventional essential existence, but without an ultimately existing essence. In this way they believe they are able to make positive or "autonomous" assertions using syllogistic logic because they are able to share a subject that is established as appearing in common - the proponent and opponent use the same kind of valid cognition to establish it. The name comes from this quality of being able to use autonomous arguments in debate.{{sfn|Shantarakshita|2005|p=131-141}}
Madhyamaka philosophy obtained a central position in all the main [[Tibetan Buddhism|Tibetan Buddhist]] schools, all whom consider themselves to be Madhyamikas. In Tibet, a distinction also began to be made between the Autonomist (''[[Svatantrika–Prasaṅgika distinction|Svātantrika]], rang rgyud pa'') and Consequentialist (''[[Svatantrika–Prasaṅgika distinction|Prāsaṅgika]], Thal ’gyur pa'') approaches to Madhyamaka reasoning about emptiness. The distinction was one invented by Tibetan scholarship, and not one made by classical Indian Madhyamikas.<ref>Brunnholzl, 2004, page 333.</ref> Tibetans mainly use the terms to refer to the logical procedures used by [[Bhavaviveka]] (who argued for the use of ''[[Svatantrika|svatantra-anumana]]'' or autonomous syllogisms) and [[Buddhapalita]] (who held that one should only use ''[[Prasaṅgika|prasanga]]'', or ''[[reductio ad absurdum]]'').


[[Jamgon Ju Mipham Gyatso|Ju Mipham]] explained that using positive assertions in logical debate may serve a useful purpose, either while debating with non-Buddhist schools or to move a student from a coarser to a more subtle view. Similarly, discussing an approximate ultimate helps students who have difficulty using only ''{{IAST|prasaṅga}}'' methods move closer to the understanding of the true ultimate. Ju Mipham felt that the ultimate non-enumerated truth of the Svatantrika was no different from the ultimate truth of the Prāsaṅgika. He felt the only difference between them was with respect to how they discussed conventional truth and their approach to presenting a path.{{sfn|Shantarakshita|2005|p=131-141}}
Influential early figures who are important in the transmission of Madhyamaka to Tibet include the Yogacara-Madhyamika [[Śāntarakṣita]], and his students [[Haribhadra (Buddhist philosopher)|Haribhadra]] and [[Kamalaśīla|Kamalashila]] (740-795) as well as the later figures of [[Atiśa|Atisha]] (982–1054) and his pupil [[Dromtön]] (1005–1064) who practiced mainly a prasangika style influenced by Candrakirti.<ref>Brunnholzl, 2004, page 51.</ref>


====Prāsaṅgika====
The early transmission of Buddhism to Tibet saw these two main strands of philosophical views on emptiness face off. The first was the camp which defended the Yogacara-Madhyamaka interpretation centered on the works of the scholars of the Sangphu monastery founded by Ngog Loden Sherab (1059-1109) and also includes Chapa Chokyi Senge (1109-1169).<ref name=":7">Dunne, John D. (2011). "Madhyamaka in India and Tibet." In Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy.” Edited by J. Garfield and W. Edelglass. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 206-221.</ref> The second camp was those who championed the work of [[Chandrakirti|Candrakirti]] over the Yogacara-Madhyamaka interpretation, and included [[Patsab Nyima Drakpa|Patsab Nyima Drag]] (b. 1055) and Jayananda (fl 12th century).<ref name=":7" /> According to John Dunne, it was the Madhyamaka interpretation and the works of Candrakirti which became dominant over time in Tibet.<ref name=":7" />
{{main article| Prasaṅgika}}
The central technique avowed by [[Prasaṅgika|{{IAST|Prasaṅgika}}]] Mādhyamaka is to show by ''{{IAST|prasaṅga}}'' (or [[reductio ad absurdum]]) that any positive assertion (such as "asti" or "nāsti", "it is", or "it is not") or [[View (Buddhism)|view]] regarding phenomena must be regarded as merely conventional ({{IAST|saṃvṛti}} or lokavyavahāra).


The Prāsaṅgika hold that it is not necessary for the proponent and opponent to use the same kind of valid cognition to establish a common subject; indeed it is possible to change the view of an opponent through a reductio argument.
Further Tibetan philosophical developments began in response to the works of [[Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen|Dolpopa]] and led to two distinctly opposed Tibetan Madhyamaka views on the nature of ultimate reality:{{sfn|Cornu|2001|p=145, 150}}<ref>Stearns, Cyrus (2010). ''The Buddha from Dölpo: A Study of the Life and Thought of the Tibetan Master Dölpopa Sherab Gyaltsen''(Rev. and enl. ed.). Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion Publications. [[International Standard Book Number|ISBN]] [[Special%3ABookSources/9781559393430|9781559393430]]. Retrieved 2 May 2015.</ref>


[[Buddhapalita]] and [[Candrakirti]] are noted as the main proponents of this approach. Tibetan teacher [[Longchen Rabjam]] noted in the 14th century that Candrakirti favored the {{IAST|prasaṅga}} approach when specifically discussing the analysis for ultimacy, but otherwise he made positive assertions. His central text, ''Madhyamakavatāra'', is structured as a description of the paths and results of practice, which is made up of positive assertions. Therefore, even those most attributed to the {{IAST|Prāsaṅgika}} view make positive assertions when discussing a path of practice but use {{IAST|prasaṅga}} specifically when analyzing for ultimate truth.{{sfn|Shantarakshita|2005|p=131-141}}
*[[Rangtong-Shentong|Rangtong]] (self-empty), which is taught by the [[Gelug]] who follow the interpretation of [[Tsongkhapa]] (1357–1419), but also by the [[Nyingma]] and [[Sakya]] schools. It states that ultimate reality is that which is empty of self nature in a relative and absolute sense, it is empty of everything, including itself. It is thus not a transcendental ground or metaphysical absolute.


=====Tsongkhapa=====
*[[Rangtong-Shentong|Shentong]] (other empty), which is a further development of Indian Yogacara-Madhyamaka and the Buddha-nature teachings by [[Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen|Dolpopa]], and is primarily taught in [[Jonang]] but also by some [[Kagyu]] figures like [[Jamgon Kongtrul]], it states that ultimate reality is empty of conventional reality, but it is not itself empty of being ultimate Buddhahood and the luminous nature of mind.<ref>Brunnholzl, Karl, Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and Buddha Nature, p 108.</ref> In [[Jonang]], this ultimate reality is a "ground or substratum" which is "uncreated and indestructible, noncomposite and beyond the chain of dependent origination."<ref>Stearns, Cyrus (1999), The Buddha from Dolpo: A Study of the Life and Thought of the Tibetan Master Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen, State University of New York Press, p. 82.</ref>
{{Seealso|Prasaṅgika according to Tsongkhapa}}
The [[Gelug]] school was founded by [[Je Tsongkhapa]]'s reforms to [[Atisha]]'s [[Kadampa|Kadam]] tradition in the 14th century.{{refn|group=note|Alexander Berzin: There was a very famous Nyingma lama at the time called Lhodrag Namka-gyeltsen, and this Nyingma lama had, continually, visions of Vajrapani. And he invited Tsongkhapa, and they became mutual teacher and disciple. It is from this Nyingma lama that Tsongkhapa got his main lam-rim transmissions from the Kadam tradition — two of the main Kadam lineages. There are three Kadampa lineages that had split. He got two of them from this Nyingma lama and one from a Kagyu lama. The Kadampa was divided into three: One was the lam-rim teachings, one was the textual teachings, and one was the oral guideline teachings. So he got the lam-rim and the oral guideline lineages from this Nyingma lama, and the textual tradition from a Kagyu lama. This I find very interesting. One always thinks that he got them from Kadampa lamas; he didn’t. And that Gelugpa was so separate from all these other traditions; it wasn’t. Look at this Kagyu lama, Lama Umapa, that Tsongkhapa studied Madhyamaka with; he had studied Madhyamaka with Sakya. The Sakyas were the main Madhyamaka people of those days.{{cite web|last=Berzin|first=Alexander|title=The Life of Tsongkhapa|url=http://studybuddhism.com/en/tibetan-buddhism/spiritual-teachers/tsongkhapa/the-life-of-tsongkhapa|accessdate=20 June 2016|location=Munich, Germany|date=December 2003}}}} Tsongkhapa emphasized [[Karuṇā|compassion]] and [[sunyata|insight into emptiness]].


In his ''Ocean of Reasoning'', Tsongkhapa comments on the Mulamadhyamakakarika.{{sfn|rJe Tsong Kha Pa|2006}} According to Tsongkhapa, Nagarjuna uses the term svabhava to refer to [[sunyata]] as the nature of reality:{{sfn|Magee|1999|p=125-127}}
===Jonang===
{{quote|Their nature of emptiness is their reality nature.{{sfn|Magee|1999|p=32}}}}
In the [[Jonang]] school, only the Buddha and the Buddha Nature are viewed as ''not'' intrinsically empty, but as truly real, unconditioned, and replete with eternal, changeless virtues.{{sfn|Hopkins|2006|p=8-16}} The Buddha Nature ([[tathagatagarbha]]) is only empty of what is impermanent and conditioned, not of its own self. The Buddha Nature is truly real, and primordially present in all beings. An important Tibetan treatise on Emptiness and the Buddha Nature is found in the scholar-monk [[Dolpopa|Dolpopa's]] voluminous study, ''Mountain Doctrine''.{{sfn|Hopkins|2006}} Basing himself on the Indian ''[[Tathāgatagarbha sūtras]]'' as his main sources, [[Dolpopa]] described the Buddha Nature as:{{quote|[N]on-material emptiness, emptiness that is far from an annihilatory emptiness, great emptiness that is the ultimate pristine wisdom of superiors ...buddha earlier than all buddhas, ... causeless original buddha.{{sfn|Hopkins|2006|p=14}}}}


This is in line with the ''Eight Thousand Stanza Perfection of Wisdom Sutra:
This "great emptiness" i.e. the ''tathāgatagarbha'' is said to be filled with eternal powers and virtues:
{{quote|Subhuti, since the [[five aggregates]] are without nature, they have a nature of emptiness.{{sfn|Magee|1999|p=32}}}}


Although Tsongkhapa argued in favour of [[Yogacara]] views early in his career{{sfn|Tsongkhapa|1993}} his later understanding is derived from Candrakirti,{{sfn|Magee|1999}} who states that conventionally there are entities with distinguishing characteristics, but ultimately those qualities are not independent essences. But since this emptiness is true for everything that exists, this emptiness may also be regarded as an essence, though not in the sense of an independent essence. Candrakirti formulates a final negation by stating that even the denial of ''svabhava'' implies ...
{{quote|[P]ermanent, stable, eternal, everlasting. Not compounded by causes and conditions, the matrix-of-one-gone-thus is intrinsically endowed with ultimate buddha qualities of body, speech, and mind such as the ten powers; it is not something that did not exist before and is newly produced; it is self-arisen.'{{sfn|Hopkins|2006|p=8}}}}
{{quote|...that either oneself or one's audience is not entirely free from the belief in ''svabhava''. Therefore, ultimate truth, truth as it is for those who are free from misknowledge, cannot be expressed by asserting either the existence or nonexistence of ''svahbava''.{{sfn|Rizzi|1988|p=19}}}}


====Shentong - Jonangpa====
The Jonang position came to be known as "emptiness of other" (''gzhan stong, shentong),'' because it held that the ultimate truth was positive reality that was not empty of its own nature, only empty of what it was other than itself.<ref name=":8">Cabezón, José Ignacio; Lobsang Dargyay, ''Freedom from Extremes Gorampa's "Distinguishing the Views" and the Polemics of Emptiness (Part of Studies in Indian and Tibetan Buddhism)'', p. 29.
[[Dolpopa]], the founder of the [[Jonangpa|Jonangpa school]], called his synthesis the '' Mahā-Mādhyamaka'', the "Great Middle Way".{{sfn|Magee|1999|p=103}} He regarded the [[tathagatagarbha]] to be the true emptiness. This view was opposed by Tsongkhapa. {{sfn|Magee|1999|p=103-115}}


===Chán/Zen===
</ref> Dolpopa considered his view a form of Madhyamaka, and called his system "Great Madhyamaka".<ref>Brunnholzl, 2004, page 502.</ref>
{{See also|Sengzhao}}


The [[Zen|Chán/Zen-tradition]] emulated Madhyamaka-thought via the San-lun Buddhists, influencing its supposedly "illogical" way of communicating "absolute truth."{{sfn|Cheng|1981}}
===Gelug===
The [[Gelug|Gelug school]] was founded in the beginning of the 15th century by [[Je Tsongkhapa|Tsongkhapa]] (1357–1419).{{sfn|Snelling|1987|p=207}} Tsongkhapa's conception of emptiness draws mainly from the works of [[Svatantrika–Prasaṅgika distinction|"prāsaṅgika"]] Indian thinkers like Buddhapalita, Candrakirti, and Shantideva and he argued that only their interpretation of Nagarjuna was ultimately correct. According to José I. Cabezón, Tsongkhapa also argued that the ultimate truth or emptiness was "an absolute negation (''med dgag'')—the negation of inherent existence—and that nothing was exempt from being empty, including emptiness itself."<ref name=":8" /> He also maintained that the ultimate truth could be understood conceptually, an understanding which could later be transformed into a non-conceptual one. However, this could only be done through the use of Madhyamika reasoning, which he also sought to unify with the logical theories of [[Dharmakirti]].<ref name=":8" /> Because of Tsongkhapa's view of emptiness as an absolute negation, the strongly attacked the other empty views of [[Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen|Dolpopa]] in his works.


===Western Buddhism===
The [[14th Dalai Lama]], who generally speaks from the Gelug version of the ''[[Prasangika|Prasaṅgika-Mādhyamaka]]'', states:
{{quote|According to the theory of emptiness, any belief in an objective reality grounded in the assumption of intrinsic, independent existence is simply untenable.<br>All things and events, whether 'material', mental or even abstract concepts like time, are devoid of objective, independent existence ... [T]hings and events are 'empty' in that they can never possess any immutable essence, intrinsic reality or absolute 'being' that affords independence.<ref>Dalai Lama (2005). ''The Universe in a Single Atom: The Convergence of Science and Spirituality'' (Hardcover). Broadway. {{ISBN|0-7679-2066-X}} & {{ISBN|978-0-7679-2066-7}}</ref>}}


===Sakya===
====Thich Nhat Hanh====
[[Thich Nhat Hanh]] explains the Madhyamaka concept of emptiness through the related concept of interdependence. In this analogy, there is no first or ultimate cause for anything that occurs. Instead, all things are dependent on innumerable causes and conditions that are themselves dependent on innumerable causes and conditions. The interdependence of all phenomena, including the self, is a helpful way to undermine mistaken views about inherence, or that one's self is inherently existent. It is also a helpful way to discuss Mahayana teachings on motivation, compassion, and ethics. The comparison to interdependence has produced recent discussion comparing Mahayana ethics to environmental ethics.{{sfn|Thich Nhat Hanh|1988}}
The Sakya school has generally held a classic [[Svatantrika–Prasaṅgika distinction|prāsaṅgika]] position following [[Chandrakirti|Candrakirti]] closely, though with significant differences from the Gelug. Sakya scholars of Madhyamika, such as Rendawa Shyönnu Lodrö (1349–1412) and Rongtön Sheja Kunrig (1367–1450) were early critics of the "other empty" view.<ref>Cabezón, José Ignacio; Lobsang Dargyay, ''Freedom from Extremes Gorampa's "Distinguishing the Views" and the Polemics of Emptiness (Part of Studies in Indian and Tibetan Buddhism)'', p. 30.</ref>


====Modern Madhyamaka====
[[Gorampa|Gorampa Sonam Senge]] (1429-1489) was an important philosopher which defended the orthodox [[Sakya]] Madhyamika position, critiquing both Dolpopa and Tsongkhapa's interpretations. According to Cabezón, Gorampa called his version of Madhyamaka "the Middle Way ''qua'' freedom from extremes" (''mtha’ bral dbu ma'') or "Middle Way ''qua'' freedom from proliferations" (''spros bral kyi dbu ma'') and claimed that the ultimate truth was ineffable, beyond predication or concept.<ref>Cabezón, José Ignacio; Lobsang Dargyay, ''Freedom from Extremes Gorampa's "Distinguishing the Views" and the Polemics of Emptiness (Part of Studies in Indian and Tibetan Buddhism)'', p. 46-48.</ref> Cabezón states that Gorampa's interpretation of Madhyamaka is "committed to a more literal reading of the Indian sources than either Dolpopa’s or Tsongkhapa’s, which is to say that it tends to take the Indian texts at face value."<ref>Cabezón, José Ignacio; Lobsang Dargyay, ''Freedom from Extremes Gorampa's "Distinguishing the Views" and the Polemics of Emptiness (Part of Studies in Indian and Tibetan Buddhism)'', p. 49.</ref> For Gorampa, emptiness is not just the absence of inherent existence, but it is the absence of the four extremes in all phenomena i.e. existence, nonexistence, both and neither (see: [[Catuṣkoṭi|''catuskoti'']]), ''without any further qualification''.<ref name=":9">Cabezón, José Ignacio; Lobsang Dargyay, ''Freedom from Extremes Gorampa's "Distinguishing the Views" and the Polemics of Emptiness (Part of Studies in Indian and Tibetan Buddhism)'', p. 50.</ref> Hence, in contrast to the view of Tsongkhapa for example, Gorampa's Madhyamaka negates ''existence'' ''itself'', instead of (as in Tsongkhapa), merely negating "ultimate existence" or "inherent existence".<ref name=":9" /> Gorampa also saw the ultimate truth of emptiness as being divided into two parts:<ref name=":9" />
Madhyamaka forms an alternative to the Perennialist and essentialist (neo-)Advaita understanding of [[nondualism]] or modern spirituality.<ref group=web>[http://www.emptiness.co/ Emptiness. Buddhist and Beyond]</ref><ref group=web>[http://thenonbuddhist.com/ The Non-Buddhist]</ref><ref group=web>[http://emptinessteachings.com/ Emptiness teachings]</ref> The classical Madhyamaka-teachings are complemented with western ([[Postmodern philosophy|post-modern]]) philosophy,<ref group=web>[http://www.emptiness.co/5westernbooks2 ''Review of Richard Rorty's "Philosophy and Social Hope"'']</ref> [[critical sociology]],<ref group=web>[http://thenonbuddhist.com/2014/01/12/tsongkhapa-in-praise-of-relativity-the-essence-of-eloquence/ Patrick jennings (2014), ''Tsongkhapa: In Praise of Relativity; The Essence of Eloquence''] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150518074106/http://thenonbuddhist.com/2014/01/12/tsongkhapa-in-praise-of-relativity-the-essence-of-eloquence/ |date=2015-05-18 }}</ref> and [[social constructionism]].<ref group=web>[http://www.emptiness.co/5westernbooks1 emptiness.co, ''Review of Kenneth J. Gergen's "An Invitation to Social Construction"'']</ref> These approaches stress that there is no transcendental reality beyond this phenomenal world,<ref group=web>[http://emptinessteachings.com/2014/09/11/the-two-truths-of-buddhism-and-the-emptiness-of-emptiness/ Susan Kahn, ''The Two Truths of Buddhism and The Emptiness of Emptiness.'']</ref> and in some cases even explicitly distinguish themselves from (neo-)Advaita approaches.<ref group=web>[http://www.emptiness.co/adv_to_empt emptiness.co, ''Coming from the Advaitic/Awareness Teachings? Special Pointers'']</ref>


==Influence on Advaita Vedanta==
# The emptiness that is reached by rational analysis (this is actually only an analogue, and not the real thing).
{{Main article|Advaita Vedanta|Ajativada}}
# The emptiness that yogis fathom by means of their own individual gnosis, the real ultimate truth, which is reached by negating the previous rational understanding of emptiness.


[[Gaudapada]], who was strongly influenced by Buddhism, borrowed the concept of "ajāta" from Nagajurna's Madhyamaka philosophy,{{sfn|Renard|2010|p=157}}{{sfn|Comans|2000|p=35-36}} which uses the term "anutpāda":{{sfn|Bhattacharya|1943|p=49}}
Unlike most orthodox Sakyas, the philosopher [[Sakya Chokden]], a contemporary of Gorampa, also promoted a form of shentong as being complementary to rangtong. He saw shentong as useful for meditative practice, while rangtong as useful for cutting through views. <ref>Brunnholzl, Karl; Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and Buddha Nature, p. 107.</ref>

===Kagyu===
In the [[Kagyu]] tradition, there is a broad field of opinion on the nature of emptiness, with some holding the other empty view while others holding different positions. One influential Kagyu thinker was [[Rangjung Dorje, 3rd Karmapa Lama|Rangjung Dorje, 3rd Karmapa Lama.]] His view synthesized Madhyamaka and Yogacara perspectives. According to Brunnholzl, regarding his position in the rangtong shentong debate he "can be said to regard these two as not being mutually exclusive and to combine them in a creative synthesis."<ref>Brunnholzl, Karl, Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and Buddha Nature, p 99.</ref> However, [[Rangjung Dorje, 3rd Karmapa Lama|Rangjung Dorje]] never uses these terms in any of his works and thus any claims to him being a promoter of shentong or otherwise is a later interpretation.<ref>Brunnholzl, Karl, Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and Buddha Nature, p 114.</ref>

Several Kagyu figures disagree with the view that shentong is a form of Madhyamaka. According to Brunnholzl, [[Mikyö Dorje, 8th Karmapa Lama]] (1507–1554) and [[Pawo Rinpoche|Second Pawo Rinpoche Tsugla Trengwa]] see the term "Shentong Madhyamaka" as a misnomer, for them the Yogacara of Asanga and Vasubandhu and the system of Nagarjuna are "two clearly distinguished systems". They also refute the idea that there is "a permanent, intrinsically existing Buddha nature".<ref>Brunnholzl, 2004, page 446..</ref>

[[Mikyö Dorje, 8th Karmapa Lama|Mikyö Dorje]] also argues that the language of other emptiness does not appear in any of the sutras or the treatises of the Indian masters. He attacks the view of [[Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen|Dolpopa]] as being against the sutras of ultimate meaning which state that all phenomena are emptiness as well as being against the treatises of the Indian masters.<ref>Brunnholzl, 2004, page 447.</ref> The 8th Karmapa rejects both perspectives of rangtong and shentong as true descriptions of ultimate reality, which he sees as being "the utter peace of all discursiveness regarding being empty and not being empty".<ref>Brunnholzl, 2004, page 448.</ref>

One of the most influential Kagyu philosophers in recent times is [[Jamgon Kongtrul|Jamgön Kongtrul Lodrö Taye]] (1813–1899) who advocated a system of Shentong Madhyamaka and held that primordial wisdom was "never empty of its own nature and it is there all the time".<ref>Brunnholzl, 2004, page 501.</ref><ref>Ringu Tulku, The Ri-me Philosophy of Jamgon Kongtrul the Great: A Study of the Buddhist Lineages of Tibet 2007, p 219.</ref>

The modern Kagyu teacher [[Khenpo Tsultrim Gyamtso Rinpoche|Khenpo Tsultrim]] (1934–), in his ''Progressive Stages of Meditation on Emptiness'', presents five stages of meditation, which he relates to five tenet systems.{{sfn|Hookham|1991|p=19-26}}{{sfn|Khenpo Tsultrim Gyamtso|1994}} He holds the "Shentong Madhyamaka" as the highest view, above prasangika. He sees this as a meditation on ''Paramarthasatya'' ("Absolute Reality"),{{sfn|Hookham|1991|p=21}}{{refn|group=note|name="Absolute"|According to Hookham, non-dual experience is Ultimate Reality.{{sfn|Hookham|1991|p=37}}}} ''Buddhajnana'',{{refn|group=note|name="Buddhajnana"|According to Hookham, "The Chinese Tathagarba schools describe Buddhajnana as the totality of all that is, which pervades every part of all that is in its totality."{{sfn|Hookham|1991|p=37}} According to Hookham, for Shentong Buddhajnana is "the non-dual nature of Mind completely unobscured and endowed with its countless Buddha Qualities (''Buddhagunas'').{{sfn|Hookham|1991|p=37}}}} which is beyond concepts, and described by terms as "truly existing."{{sfn|Hookham|1991|p=22}} This approach helps "to overcome certain residual subtle concepts,"{{sfn|Hookham|1991|p=22}} and "the habit – fosterd on the earlier stages of the path – of negating whatever experience arises in his/her mind."{{sfn|Hookham|1991|p=23}} It destroys false concepts, as does prasangika, but it also alerts the practitioner "to the presence of a dynamic, positive Reality that is to be experienced once the conceptual mind is defeated."{{sfn|Hookham|1991|p=23}}

===Nyingma===

In the [[Nyingma]] school, like in Kagyu, there is a variety of views. Some Nyingma thinkers promoted shentong, like [[Katok Tsewang Norbu]], but the most influential Nyingma thinkers like [[Longchenpa]] and [[Jamgon Ju Mipham Gyatso|Ju Mipham]] held a more classical [[Svatantrika–Prasaṅgika distinction|prāsaṅgika]] interpretation while at the same time seeking to harmonize it with the view of [[Dzogchen]] tantras which are traditionally seen as the pinnacle of the Nyingma view.

According to [[Sonam Thakchoe]], the Ultimate truth in the Nyingma tradition, following [[Longchenpa]], is mainly seen as being that "reality which transcends any mode of thinking and speech, one that unmistakenly appears to the nonerroneous cognitive processes of the exalted and awakened beings" and this is said to be "inexpressible beyond words and thoughts" as well as the reality that is the "transcendence of all elaborations.<ref name=":13">Thakchoe, Sonam, "The Theory of Two Truths in Tibet", ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (Spring 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <<nowiki>https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/twotruths-tibet/</nowiki>>.</ref>

The most influential modern Nyingma scholar is [[Jamgon Ju Mipham Gyatso]] (1846–1912). He developed a unique theory of Madhyamaka, with two models of the two truths. While the adopts the traditional Madhyamaka model of two truths, in which the ultimate truth is emptiness, he also developed a second model, in which the ultimate truth is "Reality as it is" (''de bzhin nyid'') which is "established as ultimately real" (''bden par grub pa'').<ref name=":13" /> This ultimate truth is associated with the Dzogchen concept of [[Rigpa]]. While it might seem that this system conflicts with the traditional Madhyamaka interpretation, for Mipham this is not so. For while the traditional model which sees emptiness and ultimate truth as a negation is referring to the analysis of experience, the second Dzogchen influenced model refers to the experience of unity in meditation.<ref>Duckworth; Jamgon Mipam, His life and teachings, Pg 81.</ref> Douglas Duckworth sees Mipham's work as an attempt to bring together the two main Mahayana philosophical systems of yogacara and madhyamaka, as well as shentong and rangtong into a coherent system in which both are seen as being of definitive meaning.<ref>Duckworth, Jamgon Mipam, His life and teachings, 82.</ref>

===Bon===
The Tibetan [[Bon#Yungdrung Bon|Yungdrung Bon-tradition]] regards the Ma Gyu, or [[Anuttarayoga Tantra#Mother Tantras|Mother Tantra]], as the highest tantra. Its views are close to [[Dzogchen]].<ref>[https://www.ligmincha.org/store/vmchk/by-practice/sadhanas-of-the-ma-gyu-mother-tantra/view-all-products.html Ligmincha Institute: Sadhanas of the Ma Gyu (Mother Tantra)]</ref><ref>{{cite web|url=http://bon-encyclopedia.wikispaces.com/ma+gyud|title=Ma Gyud - The Mother Tantras|date=|publisher=Bon-encyclopedia.wikispaces.com|accessdate=2013-02-04}}</ref> It sees waking life as an illusion, from which we have to wake up, just as we recognize dreams to be illusions.{{sfn|Wangyal Rinpoche|2004|p=53}} Sunyata is the lack of inherent existence.{{sfn|Wangyal Rinpoche|2004|p=55}} The Mother Tantra uses ...

{{quote|...examples, similes and metaphors that we can ponder in order to better understand this illusory nature of both dream and waking life".{{sfn|Wangyal Rinpoche|2004|p=54}}}}

These "examples, similes and metaphors" ...
{{quote|...stress the lack of inherent existence and the unity of experience and experiencer. In the sutra teachings we call this "emptiness," in tantra "illusion," and in Dzogchen "the single sphere."{{sfn|Wangyal Rinpoche|2004|p=55}}}}

==East Asian Buddhism==

=== Sānlùn school ===
When Buddhism was introduced in China it was initially understood in terms of indigenous Chinese philosophical culture. Because of this, emptiness (Ch., ''kong'', 空;) was at first understood as pointing to a kind of transcendental reality similar to the [[Tao]].{{sfn|Lai|Year unknown}} It took several centuries to realize that [[sunyata]] does not refer to an essential transcendental reality underneath or behind the world of appearances.{{sfn|Lai|Year unknown}}

[[East Asian Mādhyamaka|Chinese Madhyamaka]] (known as ''Sānlùn,'' or the three treatise school) began with the work of [[Kumārajīva]] (344–413 CE) who translated the works of Nāgārjuna (including the MMK, also known in China as the ''Chung lun'', “''Madhyamakaśāstra''”; [[Taishō Tripiṭaka|Taishō]] 1564) to Chinese. Another influential text in Chinese Madhyamaka which was said to have been translated by Kumārajīva was the ''Ta-chih-tu lun'', or *''Mahāprajñāpāramitopadeśa Śāstra'' (“Treatise which is a Teaching on the Great Perfection of Wisdom [Sūtra]”). According to Dan Arnold, this text is only extant in Kumārajīva's translation and has material that differs from the work of Nāgārjuna. In spite of this, the ''Ta-chih-tu lun'' became a central text for Chinese interpretations of Madhyamaka emptiness.<ref>Arnold, Dan, ''Madhyamaka Buddhist Philosophy'', Internet Encyclopedia of philosophy.</ref> ''Sānlùn'' figures like Kumārajīva's pupil [[Sengzhao]] (384–414), and the later [[Jizang]] (549–623) were influential in restoring a more orthodox and non-essentialist interpretation of emptiness to Chinese Buddhism. [[Yin Shun]] (1906–2005) is one modern figure aligned with ''Sānlùn.''

Sengzhao is often seen as the founder of ''Sānlùn.'' He was influenced not just by Indian Madhyamaka and [[Mahayana sutras]] like the [[Vimalakirti Sutra|Vimalakirti]], but also by [[Taoism|Taoist]] works and he widely quotes the [[Tao Te Ching|Lao-tzu]] and the [[Zhuangzi (book)|Chuang-tzu]] and uses terminology of the Neo-Daoist "Mystery Learning" ([[Xuanxue|''xuanxue'']] 玄学) tradition while maintaining a uniquely Buddhist philosophical view.<ref>Liebenthal, Walter, Chao-Lun The Treatises of Seng Chao, 1968, p. 8.</ref><ref name=":11">Cuma Ozkan, A comparative analysis: Buddhist Madhyamaka and Daoist Chongxuan (twofold mystery) in the early Tang (618-720) University of Iowa, 2013.</ref> In his essay "The Emptiness of the Non-Absolute" (''buzhenkong'', 不眞空), Sengzhao points out that the nature of phenomena cannot be taken as being either existent or inexistent:<blockquote>Hence, there are indeed reasons why myriad dharmas are inexistent and cannot be taken as existent; there are reasons why [myriad dharmas] are not inexistent and cannot be taken as inexistent. Why? If we would say that they exist, their existent is not real; if we would say that they don’t exist, their phenomenal forms have taken shape. Having forms and shapes, they are not inexistent. Being not real, they are not truly existent. Hence the meaning of bu zhen kong [not really empty, 不眞空] is made manifest.<ref name=":11" /> </blockquote>Sengzhao saw the central problem in understanding emptiness as the discriminatory activity of ''[[Conceptual proliferation|prapañca]].'' According to Sengzhao, delusion arises through a dependent relationship between phenomenal things, naming, thought and reification and correct understanding lies outside of words and concepts. Thus, while emptiness is the lack of intrinsic self in all things, this emptiness is not itself an absolute and cannot be grasped by the conceptual mind, it can be only be realized through non-conceptual wisdom (''[[Prajñā (Buddhism)|prajña]]'').<ref>Dippmann, Jeffrey, Sengzhao (Seng-Chao c. 378—413 C.E.), Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.</ref>


[[Jizang]] (549–623) was another central figure in Chinese Madhyamaka who wrote numerous commentaries on Nagarjuna and Aryadeva and is considered to be the leading representative of the school.<ref name=":10">Fox, Alan, Self-reflection in the Sanlun Tradition: Madhyamika as the "Deconstructive Conscience" of Buddhism, Journal of Chinese Philosophy V. 19 (1992) pp. 1-24.</ref> [[Jizang]] called his method "deconstructing what is misleading and revealing what is corrective". He insisted that one must never settle on any particular viewpoint or perspective but constantly reexamine one's formulations to avoid reifications of thought and behavior.<ref name=":10" /> In his commentary on the MMK, Jizang's method and understanding of emptiness can be seen:<blockquote>The Abhidharma thinkers regard the four holy truths as true. The Satyasiddhi regards merely the truth of cessation of suffering, i.e., the principle of emptiness and equality, as true. The southern Mahāyāna tradition regards the principle that refutes truths as true, and the northern [Mahāyāna tradition] regards thatness [suchness] and prajñā as as true… Examining these all together, if there is a single [true] principle, it is an eternal view, which is false. If there is no principle at all, it is an evil view, which is also false. Being both existent and non-existent consists of the eternal and nihilistic views altogether. Being neither existent nor nonexistent is a foolish view. One replete with these four phrases has all [wrong] views. One without these four phrases has a severe nihilistic view. Now that [one] does not know how to name what a mind has nothing to rely upon and is free from conceptual construction, [he] foists “thatness” [suchness] upon it, one attains sainthood of the three vehicles… Being deluded in regard to thatness [suchness], one falls into the six realms of disturbed life and death.<ref name=":11" /> </blockquote>

In one of his early treatises called "The Meaning of the two Truths" (''Erdiyi''), Jizang, expounds the steps to realize the nature of the ultimate truth of emptiness as follows: <blockquote>In the first step, one recognises reality of the phenomena on the conventional level, but assumes their non-reality on the ultimate level. In the second step, one becomes aware of Being or Non-Being on the conventional level and negates both at the ultimate level. In the third step, one either asserts or negates Being and Non-Being on the conventional level, neither confi rming nor rejecting them on the ultimate level. Hence, there is ultimately no assertion or negation anymore; therefore, on the conventional level, one becomes free to accept or reject anything.<ref>Scherer, Burkhard, Review of ''The Two Truths in Chinese Buddhism,'' Chang-Qing Shih (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 2004) (Buddhist Tradition Series. 55). Buddhist studies review.</ref></blockquote>

=== Tiantai and Huayan ===
[[File:Indrasnet.jpg|thumb|right|250px|A 3D rendering of Indra's net.]]
Later Chinese philosophers developed their own unique interpretations of emptiness. One of these was [[Zhiyi]], the intellectual founder of the [[Tiantai]] school who was strongly influenced by the [[Lotus Sutra|Lotus sutra]]. The Tiantai view of emptiness and dependent origination is inseparable from their view of the "interfusion of phenomena" and the idea that the ultimate reality is an absolute totality of all particular things which are "Neither-Same-Nor-Different" from each other.<ref>Ziporyn, Brook, "Tiantai Buddhism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <<nowiki>http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/buddhism-tiantai/</nowiki>>.</ref> According to Brook Ziporyn, in Tiantai:
<blockquote>every event, function, or characteristic occurring in experience is the action of all sentient and insentient beings working together. Every instant of experience is the whole of existential reality, manifesting in this particular form, as this particular entity or experience. But this “whole” is irreducibly multiple and irreducibly unified at once in the following way: all possible conflicting, contrasted, and axiologically varied aspects are irrevocably present—in the sense of “findable”—in each of these totality effects. Good and evil, delusion and enlightenment, Buddhahood and deviltry, are all “inherently entailed” in each and every event.<ref>Ziporyn, Brook A. Emptiness and Omnipresence: An Essential Introduction to Tiantai Buddhism, 144-145.</ref></blockquote>The [[Huayan]] school understood emptiness and ultimate reality through the similar concept of [[Interpenetration (Buddhism)|interpenetration]] or "coalescence" (Wylie: ''zung-'jug''; Sanskrit: ''yuganaddha''), using the metaphor of [[Indra's net]] to illustrate this concept.<ref>Neville, Robert C. (1987).New metaphysics for eternal experience, Journal of Chinese Philosophy 14, 357-370</ref>

=== Chan ===
[[Chan Buddhism]] was influenced by all the previous Chinese Buddhist currents. The Madhyamika of Sengzhao for example, influenced the views of the Chan patriarch [[Shenhui|Shen Hui]] (670-762), a critical figure in the development of Chan, as can be seen by his "Illuminating the Essential Doctrine" (''Hsie Tsung Chi''). This text emphasizes that true emptiness or [[Tathātā|Suchness]] cannot be known through thought since it is free from thought (''wu-nien''): <ref name=":12">Zeuschner, Robert B., ''The Hsie Tsung Chi (An Early Ch'an (Zen) Buddhist Text)'' Journal of Chinese Philosophy V. 3 (1976) pp. 253-268.</ref><blockquote>Thus we come to realize that both selves and things are, in their essence, empty, and existence and non-existence both disappear.</blockquote><blockquote>Mind is fundamentally non-action; the way is truly no-thought (''wu-nien'').</blockquote><blockquote>There is no thought, no reflection, no seeking, no attainment, no this, no that, no coming, no going.</blockquote>Shen Hui also states that true emptiness is not nothing, but it is a "Subtle Existence" (''miao-yu''), which is just "Great Prajña." <ref name=":12" />

The Chan presentation of emptiness, influenced by Yogacara and the tathagathagarbha sutras, also used more positive language and poetic metaphors to describe the nature of emptiness. [[Hongzhi Zhengjue]] (1091–1157), the founder of the [[Caodong school|Caodong]] lineage, wrote:<blockquote>"The field of boundless emptiness is what exists from the very beginning. You must purify, cure, grind down, or brush away all the tendencies you have fabricated into apparent habits. [Those tendencies are the clouds in our eyes.] Then you can reside in a clear circle of brightness. Utter emptiness has no image. Upright independence does not rely on anything. Just expand and illuminate the original truth unconcerned by external conditions. Accordingly, we are told to realize that not a single thing exists. In this field birth and death do not appear. The deep source, transparent down to the bottom, can radiantly shine and can respond unencumbered to each speck of dust [each object] without becoming its partner. The subtlety of seeing and hearing transcends mere colors and sounds. The whole affair functions without leaving traces and mirrors without obscurations. Very naturally, mind and Dharmas emerge and harmonize."<ref>Taigen Dan Leighton, with Yi Wu. ''Cultivating the Empty Field: The Silent Illumination of Zen Master Hongzhi'' (Boston: Tuttle Publishing, 2000, revised and expanded edition; original edition published by North Point Press, 1991), p. 45.</ref></blockquote>The Tiantai and Huayan views of emptiness as interpenetration and interconnection also influenced the views of the [[Chan Buddhism|Chan school]], and is still discernible in modern [[Zen]]. One modern figure who has adopted an interpretation of emptiness influenced by these two schools is [[Thích Nhất Hạnh|Thich Nhat Hanh]], who explains emptiness through the similar idea of "Interbeing".<ref>McMahan, David L. ''The Making of Buddhist Modernism''. Oxford University Press: 2008 [[International Standard Book Number|ISBN]] [[Special:BookSources/978-0-19-518327-6|978-0-19-518327-6]] pg 158</ref>

==Western Buddhism==
Various western Buddhists note that ''sunyata'' refers to the emptiness of inherent existence, as in Madhyamaka; but also to the emptiness of mind or awareness, as open space and the "ground of being," as in meditation-orientated traditions and approaches such as Dzogchen and [[Shentong]].{{sfn|Snelling|1987|p=101-102}}{{sfn|Knibbe|2014|p=46}}<ref group=web name="Wellings">Nigel Wellings (2009), ''[http://www.contemplativeforum.co.uk/wordpress/?p=204 Is there anything there? – the Tibetan Rangtong Shentong debate] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150518063508/http://www.contemplativeforum.co.uk/wordpress/?p=204 |date=2015-05-18 }}''</ref>{{refn|group=note|Quotes:<br>* John Snelling: "At the core of Mahayana philosophy lies the notion of Emptiness: ''Shunyata''. This is very much in the spirit of ''anatta'' (Skt. ''anatman'') as first taught by the Buddha. It is often used to imply, not mere or sheer nothingness (that would be the nihilistic view), but 'emptiness of ''inherent existence'''; that is, the absence of any kind of enduring or self-sustaining essence. There is also a sense in which it has connotations of 'conceptual emptiness': absence of thoughts. It could be regarded too as a non-term signifying the ineffable understanding arising within the practice of meditation. Although seemingly negative, it also has its positive uses - and of course ultimately points beyond the positive negative dichotomy."{{sfn|Snelling|1987|p=101-102}}<br>* Hans Knibbe: "There are at least to important meanings of this concept of emptiness, namely:<br> - empty of independent existence;<br> - openness and space as grounf of being.{{sfn|Knibbe|2014|p=46}}<br>* Nigel Wellings:<ref group=web name ="Wellings"/> "Thus we have two types of emptiness, the emptiness of self in the skandhas that reveals the absence of an empirical and metaphysical self. And the emptiness of the self in Nirvâ.na that reveals nothing of the empirical self existing within the Nirvâ.na consciousness.<br>Harvey seems to confirm this view when he tells us that all conditioned dharmas are empty of self because they are impermanent and a source of suffering, while the unconditioned dharma, Nirvâ.na, is empty because it does not “support the feeling of ‘I-ness’”, that is, the impermanent skandhas. (1990:52). This is very similar to the teaching of the modern Kagyu Nyingma Lama, Tulku Urgyen Rinpoche, a Shentong exponent:
{{quote|All appearances are empty, in that they can be destroyed or extinguished in some way [...] The whole universe vanishes at some point, destroyed by the seven fires and one immense deluge. In this way, all appearances are empty.<br>Mind is also ultimately empty, but its way of being empty is not the same as appearances. [My italics] Mind can experience anything but it cannot be destroyed. Its original nature is the dharmakaya of all Buddhas. You cannot actually do anything to mind – you can’t change it, wash it away, bury it or burn it. What is truly empty, though, is all the appearances that appear in the mind. (Tulku Urgyen (1999), ''As It Is vol.1'' Rangjang Yeshe, Boudhanath, Hong Kong & Nasby. p.53)}}}}

==Hinduism==

===Influence on Advaita Vedanta===
Gaudapada is considered by some scholars to have been strongly influenced by Buddhism, as he developed his concept of [[Ajativada|"ajāta"]] from Nagajurna's Madhyamaka philosophy,{{sfn|Renard|2010|p=157}}{{sfn|Comans|2000|p=35-36}} which uses the term "anutpāda":{{sfn|Bhattacharya|1943|p=49}}
* "An" means "not", or "non"
* "An" means "not", or "non"
* "Utpāda" means "genesis", "coming forth", "birth"<ref>[http://spokensanskrit.de/index.php?tinput=utpAda&script=&direction=SE&link=yes Sanskrit Dictionary for Spoken Sanskrit, ''Utpāda'']</ref>
* "Utpāda" means "genesis", "coming forth", "birth"<ref group=web>[http://spokensanskrit.de/index.php?tinput=utpAda&script=&direction=SE&link=yes Sanskrit Dictionary for Spoken Sanskrit, ''Utpāda'']</ref>


Taken together "anutpāda" means "having no origin", "not coming into existence", "not taking effect", "non-production".<ref>[http://spokensanskrit.de/index.php?script=HK&beginning=0+&tinput=anutpAda+&trans=Translate&direction=AU Sanskrit Dictionary for Spoken Sanskrit, ''Anutpāda'']</ref>
Taken together "anutpāda" means "having no origin", "not coming into existence", "not taking effect", "non-production".<ref group=web>[http://spokensanskrit.de/index.php?script=HK&beginning=0+&tinput=anutpAda+&trans=Translate&direction=AU Sanskrit Dictionary for Spoken Sanskrit, ''Anutpāda'']</ref>


According to Gaudapada, the Absolute is not subject to [[Saṃsāra|birth, change and death]]. The Absolute is ''aja'', the unborn eternal.{{sfn|Sarma|1996|p=127}} The [[Empiricism|empirical world]] of [[phenomenon|appearances]] is considered [[Maya (illusion)|Maya]] (unreal as it is transitory), and not [[Philosophical realism|absolutely existent]].{{sfn|Sarma|1996|p=127}} Thus, Gaudapada's concept of ''ajativada'' is similar to Buddhist term "anutpāda" for the absence of an origin{{sfn|Renard|2010|p=157}}{{sfn|Bhattacharya|1943|p=49}} or śūnyatā.{{sfn|Renard|2010|p=160}}{{refn|group=note|The term is also used in the ''[[Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra]]''.{{sfn|Suzuki|1999}} According to D.T Suzuki, "anutpada" is not the opposite of "utpada", but transcends opposites. It is [[kenshō]], seeing into the true nature of existence,{{sfn|Suzuki|1999|p=123-124}} the seeing that "all objects are without self-substance [Sunyata]".{{sfn|Suzuki|1999|p=168}}}}
The Buddhist tradition usually uses the term "anutpāda" for the absence of an origin{{sfn|Renard|2010|p=157}}{{sfn|Bhattacharya|1943|p=49}} or [[sunyata]].{{sfn|Renard|2010|p=160}}{{refn|group=note|The term is also used in the [[Lankavatara Sutra]].{{sfn|Suzuki|1999}} According to D.T Suzuki, "anutpada" is not the opposite of "utpada", but transcends opposites. It is the [[Kensho|seeing into the true nature of existence]],{{sfn|Suzuki|1999|p=123-124}} the seeing that "all objects are without self-substance".{{sfn|Suzuki|1999|p=168}}}}


"Ajātivāda" is the fundamental philosophical doctrine of [[Gaudapada]].{{sfn|Sarma|1996|p=127}} According to Gaudapada, the Absolute is not subject to birth, change and death. The Absolute is ''aja'', the unborn eternal.{{sfn|Sarma|1996|p=127}} The empirical [[world]] of [[phenomenon|appearances]] is considered unreal, and not [[Existence|absolutely existent]].{{sfn|Sarma|1996|p=127}}
But Gaudapada's perspective is quite different from Nagarjuna.{{sfn|Comans|2000|p=36}} Gaudapada's perspective found in ''Mandukya Karika'' is based on the ''[[Mandukya Upanishad]]''.{{sfn|Comans|2000|p=36}} According to Gaudapada, the metaphysical absolute called [[Brahman]] never changes, while the phenomenal world changes continuously, so the phenomenal world cannot arise independently from Brahman. If the world cannot arise, yet is an empirical fact, than the perceived world has to be a transitory (unreal) appearance of Brahman. And if the phenomenal world is a transitory appearance, then there is no real origination or destruction, only apparent origination or destruction. From the level of ultimate truth (''paramārthatā'') the phenomenal world is ''[[Maya (illusion)|māyā]]'', "illusion",{{sfn|Comans|2000|p=36}} apparently existing but ultimately not metaphysically real.{{sfn|Hiriyanna|2000|p=25, 160-161}}


Gaudapada's perspective is quite different from Nagarjuna.{{sfn|Comans|2000|p=36}} Gaudapada's perspective is based on the [[Mandukya Upanishad]].{{sfn|Comans|2000|p=36}} In the ''Mandukya Karika'', Gaudapada's commentary on the Mandukya Upanishad, Gaudapada sets forth his perspective. According to Gaudapada, Brahman cannot undergo alteration, so the phenomenal world cannot arise from Brahman. If the world cannot arise, yet is an empirical fact, then the world has to be an unreal{{refn|group=note|C.q. "transitory"}} appearance of Brahman. And if the phenomenal world is an unreal appearance, then there is no real origination or destruction, only apparent origination or destruction. From the level of ultimate truth (''paramārthatā'') the phenomenal world is ''[[Maya (illusion)|Maya]]''.{{sfn|Comans|2000|p=36}}
In ''Gaudapada-Karika'', chapter III, verses 46-48, he states that [[Brahman]] never arises, is never born, is never unborn, it rests in itself:
{{quote|
When the mind does not lie low, and is not again tossed about, then that being without movement, and not presenting any appearance, culminates into [[Brahman]]. Resting in itself, calm, with Nirvana, indescribable, highest happiness, unborn and one with the unborn knowable, omniscient they say. No creature whatever is born, no origination of it exists or takes place. This is that highest truth where nothing whatever is born.
|Gaudapada Karika|3.46-48, Translated by RD Karmarkar<ref>RD Karmarkar, [https://archive.org/stream/Gaudapada-Karika.English/Gaudapada-Karika#page/n83/mode/2up Gaudapada's Karika], Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute</ref>}}


As stated in Gaudapada’s Karika Chapter II Verse 48:<ref group=web>[http://www.advaita.org.uk/discourses/teachers/wheeler_ramesam.htm Dr. Vemuri Ramesam, ''A Critique Of John Wheeler’s “You Were Never Born”'']</ref>
In contrast to Renard's view,{{sfn|Renard|2010|p=157}} Karmarkar states the Ajativada of Gaudapada has nothing in common with the ''Śūnyatā'' concept in Buddhism.<ref>RD Karmarkar, [https://archive.org/stream/Gaudapada-Karika.English/Gaudapada-Karika#page/n45/mode/2up/search/ajativada Gaudapada's Karika], Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute, pages xxxix-xl</ref> While the language of Gaudapada is undeniably similar to those found in Mahayana Buddhism, states Comans, their perspective is different because unlike Buddhism, Gaudapada is relying on the premise of "Brahman, [[Atman (Hinduism)|Atman]] or Turiya" exist and are the nature of absolute reality.{{sfn|Comans|2000|p=36}}
{{quote|No jiva ever comes into existence. There exists no cause that can produce it. The supreme truth is that nothing ever is born.<ref group=web>[http://www.swamij.com/upanishad-mandukya-karika.htm Mandukya Upanishad with Gaudapada's Karika]</ref>}}


==Understanding in modern scholarship==
===In Shaivism===
Western scholarship has given a broad variety of interpretations of Madhyamaka:
''Sunya'' and ''Sunyatisunya'' are concepts which appear in some [[Shaivism|Shaiva]] texts, such as the [[Vijñāna Bhairava Tantra]], which contains several verses mentioning voidness as a feature of ultimate reality - [[Shiva]]:
{{quote|Over the past half-century the doctrine of the Madhyamaka school, and in particular that of Nāgārjuna has been variously described as nihilism, monism, irrationalism, misology, agnosticism, scepticism, criticism, dialectic, mysticism, acosmism, absolutism, relativism, nominalism, and linguistic analysis with therapeutic value.{{sfn|Ruegg|1981|p=2}}}}


[[Jay L. Garfield]] likewise rephrases Ruegg: {{quote|"Modern interpreters differ among themselves about the correct way to read it as least as much as canonical interpreters. Nagarjuna has been read as an idealist (Murti 1960), a nihilist (Wood 1994), a skeptic (Garfield 1995), a pragmatist (Kalupahana 1986), and as a mystic (Streng 1967). He has been regarded as a critic of logic (Inada 1970), as a defender of classical logic (Hayes 1994), and as a pioneer of paraconsistent logic (Garfield and Priest 2003)".{{sfn|Garfield and Samten|2006|p=xx}}}}
<blockquote>"The Absolute void is Bhairava who is beyond the senses and the mind, beyond all the categories of these instruments. From the point of view of the human mins, He is most void. from the point of view of Reality, He is most full, for He is the source of all manifestation."<ref>Jaideva Singh, Vijnanabhairava or Divine Consciousness: A Treasury of 112 Types of Yoga, page 29</ref></blockquote>


These interpretations "reflect almost as much about the viewpoints of the scholars involved as do they reflect the content of Nāgārjuna's concepts".{{sfn|Daye|1971|p=77}}
<blockquote>"The yogi should concentrate intensely on the idea (and also feel) that this universe is totally void. In that void, his mind would become absorbed. Then he becomes highly qualified for absorption i.e. his mind is absorbed in the absolute void (sunyatisunya)."<ref>Jaideva Singh, Vijnanabhairava or Divine Consciousness: A Treasury of 112 Types of Yoga, page 55</ref></blockquote>


Most recent western scholarship (Garfield,{{sfn|Garfield|1995}} Napper,{{sfn|Napper|1989}} Hopkins,{{sfn|Hopkins|1996}} Huntington, and others) have, after investigation, tended to adopt one or another of the Gelugpa collegiate interpretations of Madhyamaka.
In a series of Kannada language texts of [[Lingayatism]], a Shaivism tradition, ''shunya'' is equated to the concept of the Supreme. In particular, the ''Shunya Sampadane'' texts present the ideas of [[Allama Prabhu]] in a form of dialogue, where ''shunya'' is that void and distinctions which a spiritual journey seeks to fill and eliminate. It is the described as a state of union of one's soul with the infinite Shiva, the state of blissful moksha.<ref name="Dalal2010p388"/><ref>{{cite book|author=Stephan Schuhmacher|title=The Encyclopedia of Eastern Philosophy and Religion: Buddhism, Hinduism, Taoism, Zen |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vpP8770qVakC |year=1994|publisher=Shambhala|isbn=978-0-87773-980-7|page=202}}</ref>


===In Vaishnavism===
===Kalupahana===
Kalupahana's interpretation sees Madhyamaka, along with Yogacara, as an antidote against essentialist biases in Mahayana Buddhist thought.{{sfn|Kalupahana|1992}}{{sfn|Kalupahana|1994}}
''Shunya Brahma'' is a concept found in certain texts of [[Vaishnavism]], particularly in [[Odia language|Odiya]], such as the poetic ''Panchasakhas''. It explains the ''Nirguna Brahman'' idea of Vedanta, that is the eternal unchanging metaphysical reality as "personified void". Alternate names for this concept of Hinduism, include ''shunya purusha'' and ''Jagannatha'' (Vishnu) in certain text.<ref name="Dalal2010p388"/><ref>{{cite book|author=Chittaranjan Das|title=Bhakta Charana Das (Medieval Oriya Writer)|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2QowAAAAMAAJ |year=1994|publisher=Sahitya Akademi|isbn=978-81-7201-716-3|pages=9, 101–112}}</ref> However, both in Lingayatism and various flavors of Vaishnavism such as ''Mahima Dharma'', the idea of ''Shunya'' is closer to the Hindu concept of metaphysical ''[[Brahman]]'', rather than to the ''Śūnyatā'' concept of Buddhism.<ref name="Dalal2010p388"/> However, there is some overlap, such as in the works of Bhima Bhoi.<ref name="Dalal2010p388">{{cite book|author=Roshen Dalal|title=Hinduism: An Alphabetical Guide|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=DH0vmD8ghdMC&pg=PA388 |year=2010|publisher=Penguin |isbn=978-0-14-341421-6|pages=388–389}}</ref><ref name="Bhoi2010">{{cite book|author=Bettina Bäumer (Translator)|title=Bhima Bhoi, Verses from the Void: Mystic Poetry of an Oriya Saint|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=nNnhSAAACAAJ|year=2010|publisher=Manohar Publishers |isbn=978-81-7304-813-5}}</ref>


===Hayes===
In the [[Vaishnavism]] of [[Orissa, India|Orissa]], the idea of Shunya [[Brahman]] or Shunya [[Purusha]] is found in the poetry of the Orissan [[Oriya literature#Age of the Panchasakhas|Panchasakhas]] (Five Friends), such as in the compositions of 16th-century [[Acyutananda]]. Acyutananda's ''Shunya Samhita'' extols the nature of Shunya Brahman:
Richard P. Hayes is critical of the works of Nagarjuna:
<blockquote>
{{quote|Nagarjuna’s writings had relatively little effect on the course of subsequent Indian Buddhist philosophy. Despite his apparent attempts to discredit some of the most fundamental concepts of abhidharma, abhidharma continued to flourish for centuries,
''nāhi tāhāra rūpa varṇa, adṛsha avarṇa tā cinha.''<br />
without any appreciable attempt on the part of abhidharmikas to defend their methods of analysis against Nagarjuna’s criticisms.{{sfn|Hayes|2003|p=2}}}}
''tāhāku brahmā boli kahi, śūnya brahmhati se bolāi.''


According to Hayes, Nagarjuna makes use of two different possible meanings of the word ''svabhava'', and uses those two meanings to make statements which are not logical.{{sfn|Hayes|2003|p=3-5}} In doing so, Hayes regards Nagarjuna...
It has no shape, no colour, <br />
{{quote|[A] relatively primitive thinker whose mistakes in reasoning were eventually uncovered as the knowledge of logic in India became more sophisticated in subsequent centuries.{{sfn|Hayes|2003|p=7}}}}
It is invisible and without a name<br />
This Brahman is called Shunya Brahman.<ref>Acyutānanda, ''Brahma Saṃhitā'', translated by Patnaik, p.117</ref>{{full citation needed|date=January 2017}}
</blockquote>


===Magee===
The [[Oriya literature#Age of the Panchasakhas|Panchasakhas]] practiced a form of [[Bhakti]] called Jnana-mishrita Bhakti-marga, which saw the necessity of knowledge ([[Jnana]]) and devotion - [[Bhakti]].{{citation needed|date=January 2017}}
William Magee strongly disagrees with Hayes. He points out the influence of Nagarjuna in Tibetan Buddhism, and refers to Tsonghkhapa's interpretation of Nagarjuna to argue that

{{quote|Hayes is misidentifying Nagarjuna's intended meaning of ''svabhava''. In contradistinction to Hayes' belief that Nagarjuna speaks equivocably of an identity nature and a causally independent, non-existent nature, Dzong-ka-ba feels that in chapter XV.1-2 Nagarjuna uses the term ''svabhava'' to refer to an existent emptiness nature.{{sfn|Magee|1999|p=126}}}}
==Alternate translations==
According to Magee, both Candrakirti and Dzong-ka-ba "see Nagarjuna as consistently referring to emptiness with the word ''svabhava''".{{sfn|Magee|1999|p=127}}
* Emptiness
* Interdependence (Ringu Tulku){{sfn|Ringu Tulku|2005|p=39}}
* Openness
* Transparency (Cohen)
* Spaciousness
* Thusness<ref>[https://books.google.com/books?id=UsIKAAAAYAAJ&q=thusness#search_anchor Inada, Kenneth (Sri Satguru Publications, 1993) ''Nāgārjuna, a translation of his Mūlamadhyamakakārikā with an introductory essay'': pg. 182.]</ref>


==See also==
==See also==
{{div col|colwidth=20em}}
{{div col|colwidth=30em}}
*[[Buddha-nature]]
*[[Acosmism]] (belief that the world is illusory)
*[[Apophatic theology]]
*[[Candrakīrti]]
<!-- **[[Madhyamaka-avatara]] (Entering the Middle Way)
*[[Buddha Nature]]
**[[Prasannapada]] (Clear Words) : A commentary on Nagarjuna's -->
*[[Buddhist philosophy]]
*[[Depersonalization]]
*[[Consciousness-only]]
*[[Derealization]]
*[[Materialism]]
*[[Mentalism (philosophy)|Mentalism]]
*[[Determinism]]
*[[Kenosis]]
*[[Nagarjuna]]
**[[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā|Mulamadhyamakakarika]]
*[[Maya (illusion)]] (Cosmic illusion)
*[[Nihilism]]
*[[Schools of Buddhism]]
**[[Prasangika]]
*[[Performative contradiction]]
*[[Vacuous truth]]
**[[Svatantrika]]
**[[Yogacara]]
**[[East Asian Mādhyamaka]]
<!-- **[[Yogacara-Madhyamaka]] {{Clarify|date=August 2009}} -->
*[[Śūnyatā]]
*[[Tathagata]]
*[[Two Truths Doctrine]]
{{div col end}}
{{div col end}}


==Notes==
==Notes==
{{reflist|group=note|2}}
{{reflist|group=note|35em}}

{{reflist|group=web}}
==References==


===Published references===
== References ==
{{Reflist|30em}}
{{reflist|30em}}

===Web references===
{{Reflist|group=web}}


==Sources==
==Sources==

===Primary===
{{refbegin}}
{{refbegin}}
* {{Citation | last =Arena| first =Leonardo Vittorio| year =2012| title = Nonsense as the Meaning| publisher=ebook}}
* {{Citation|last1=Bhikkhu |first1=Thanissaro (trans.) |title=Cula-suñña Sutta, Majjhima Nikaya 121, The Lesser Discourse on Emptiness |publisher=Access to Insight |url=http://www.accesstoinsight.org/canon/sutta/majjhima/mn121.html |year=1997a |deadurl=yes |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20041214171512/http://accesstoinsight.org/canon/sutta/majjhima/mn121.html |archivedate=December 14, 2004 }}.
*Arnold, Dan (2010). Nāgārjuna’s ‘Middle Way’: A Non-Eliminative Understanding of Selflessness. In:Revue Internationale de Philosophie vol. 64, no.253: 367-395
* {{Citation | last1 = Bhikkhu | first1 = Thanissaro (trans.) | title = Maha-suññata Sutta, Majjhima Nikaya 122, The Greater Discourse on Emptiness | publisher = Access to Insight | url = http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/mn/mn.122.than.html | year = 1997b}}.
* {{Citation | last =Bhattacharya | first =Vidhushekhara | year =1943 | title =Gauḍapādakārikā | place =Delhi | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass}}
* {{Citation |last1=Bhikkhu |first1=Thanissaro (trans.) |title=Phena Sutta, Samyutta Nikaya XXII.95, Foam |publisher=Access to Insight |url=http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sn/sn22/sn22.095.than.html |year=1997c |deadurl=yes |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20171013023839/http://accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sn/sn22/sn22.095.than.html |archivedate=October 13, 2017 |df= }}.
* {{Citation | last =Brunnholzl | first =Karl | year =2004 | title =Center of the Sunlit Sky: Madhyamaka in the Kagyu Tradition | publisher =Snow Lion Publications}}
* {{Citation | last1 = Bhikkhu | first1 = Thanissaro (trans.) | title = SN 35.85, Suñña Sutta, Empty | publisher = Access to Insight | url = http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sn/sn35/sn35.085.than.html | year = 1997d}}
* {{Citation | last =Cheng | first =Hsueh-Li | year =1981 | title =The Roots of Zen Buddhism | journal =Journal of Chinese Philosophy |volume=8 |pages=451–478 | url =http://www.thezensite.com/ZenEssays/Nagarjuna/roots_of_zen.htm | doi=10.1111/j.1540-6253.1981.tb00267.x}}
* {{Citation | last1 = Hurvitz | first1 = Leon (trans.) | title = Scripture of the Lotus Blossom of the Fine Dharma (The Lotus Sutra) | publisher = Columbia University Press | year = 1976}}
* {{Citation | last =Knibbe | first =Hans | year =2014 | title =Zie, je bent al vrij! Schets van een non-duaal pad | publisher =Asoka}}
* {{Citation|last1=Yamamoto |first1=Kosho (trans.) |last2=Page |first2=Tony, editor |title=The Mahayana Mahaparinirvana Sutra |publisher=Nirvana Publications |url=http://webzoom.freewebs.com/nirvana-sutra/convenient/Mahaparinirvana_Sutra_Yamamoto_Page_2007.pdf |year=1999–2000 |deadurl=yes |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20131019072030/http://webzoom.freewebs.com/nirvana-sutra/convenient/Mahaparinirvana_Sutra_Yamamoto_Page_2007.pdf |archivedate=October 19, 2013 }}.

===Secondary===
* {{Citation | last =Bhattacharya | first =Vidhushekhara | year =1943 | title =Gauḍapādakārikā | place =Delhi | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass}}
*{{Citation | last1 = Boruah | first1 = Bijoy H. | title = Atman in Śūnyatā and the Śūnyatā of Atman | publisher = South Asia Seminar, University of Texas at Austin | url = http://www.katinkahesselink.net/tibet/atmsun.htm | year = 2000}}.
* {{Citation| last =Bronkhorst | first =Johannes | authorlink = Johannes Bronkhorst | year =2009 | title =Buddhist Teaching in India | publisher =Wisdom Publications}}

* Brunnholzl, Karl, The Center of the Sunlit Sky: Madhyamaka in the Kagyu Tradition, Shambhala, 2004.

* {{Citation | last =Comans | first =Michael | year =2000 | title =The Method of Early Advaita Vedānta: A Study of Gauḍapāda, Śaṅkara, Sureśvara, and Padmapāda | place =Delhi | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass}}
* {{Citation | last =Comans | first =Michael | year =2000 | title =The Method of Early Advaita Vedānta: A Study of Gauḍapāda, Śaṅkara, Sureśvara, and Padmapāda | place =Delhi | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass}}
* {{Citation | last =Cornu | first =Philippe | year =2001 | chapter =Nawoord | title =Schijn en werkelijkheid. De twee waarheden in de vier boeddhistische leerstelsels | publisher =KunchabPublicaties}}
* {{Citation | last =Cornu | first =Philippe | year =2001 | chapter =Nawoord | title =Schijn en werkelijkheid. De twee waarheden in de vier boeddhistische leerstelsels | publisher =KunchabPublicaties}}
*{{Citation | last1 = Jackson | first1 = Roger R. | title = Is Enlightenment Possible? | publisher = Snow Lion Publications | year = 1993 | isbn = 1-55939-010-7}}
* {{Citation | last =Daye | first =Douglas D. | year =1971 | title =Major Schools of the Mahayana: Madhyamaka. In:Charles S. Prebisch, Buddhism, A Modern Perspective. Pages 76-96. | isbn =978-0-271-01195-0}}
* {{Citation | last =Fuller | first =Paul | year =2005 | title =The Notion of Diṭṭhi in Theravāda Buddhism: The Point of View | publisher =Routledge | url =http://www.misterdanger.net/books/Buddhism%20Books/The%20notion%20of%20Ditthi.pdf | deadurl =yes | archiveurl =https://web.archive.org/web/20141202094809/http://www.misterdanger.net/books/Buddhism%20Books/The%20notion%20of%20Ditthi.pdf | archivedate =2014-12-02 | df = }}

* {{Citation | last =Garfield | first =Jay L. | year =1994 | title =Dependent Arising and the Emptiness of Emptiness: Why did Nagarjuana start with causation? | journal =Philosophy East & West |volume=44 |issue=2 |pages= | url =http://www.thezensite.com/ZenEssays/Nagarjuna/Dependent_Arising.htm}}
* {{Citation | last =Garfield | first =Jay L. | year =1995 | title =The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way | place =Oxford | publisher =Oxford University Press}}
* {{Citation | last =Garfield | first =Jay L. | year =2012 | title =Madhyamaka is not emptiness | publisher =smith College, University of melbourne | url =http://www.smith.edu/philosophy/docs/garfield_nihilism.pdf}}
* {{Citation | last =Gomez | first =Luis O. | year =1976 | title =Proto-Mādhyamika in the Pāli canon | journal =Philosophy East and West |volume=26 |issue=2 |pages=137–165 | url =http://ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-PHIL/gomez.htm | doi=10.2307/1398186}}
* {{Citation | last =Harvey | first =Peter | year =1995 | title =An introduction to Buddhism. Teachings, history and practices | publisher =Cambridge University Press}}
* {{Citation | last =Hayes | first =Richard P. | year =1994 | title =Nagarjuna's appeal. In: Journal of Indian Philosophy 22: 299-378}}
* {{Citation | last =Hayes | first =Richard P. | year =2003 | title =Nagarjuna: Master of Paradox,Mystic or Perpetrator of Fallacies? | url =http://www.thezensite.com/ZenEssays/Nagarjuna/Master_of_Paradox.pdf}}
* {{Citation | last1 =Hookham | first1 =S.K.| authorlink1 =Shenpen Hookham | year=1991 | title=The Buddha within : Tathagatagarbha doctrine according to the Shentong interpretation of the Ratnagotravibhaga | publisher =State University of New York Press | location=Albany, NY | isbn=978-0791403587}}
* {{Citation | last1 =Hookham | first1 =S.K.| authorlink1 =Shenpen Hookham | year=1991 | title=The Buddha within : Tathagatagarbha doctrine according to the Shentong interpretation of the Ratnagotravibhaga | publisher =State University of New York Press | location=Albany, NY | isbn=978-0791403587}}
* {{Citation | last =Hopkins | first =Jeffrey | year =2006 | title =Mountain Doctrine: Tibet's Fundamental Treatise on Other-Emptiness and the Buddha Matrix | place =London | publisher =Snow Lion}}
* {{Citation | last =Hopkins | first =Jeffrey | last2 =Napper | first2 =Elizabeth | year =1996 | title =Meditation on Emptiness}}
* {{Citation | last =Kalupahana | first =David J. | author-link = | year =1992 | title =The Principles of Buddhist Psychology | place =Delhi | publisher =ri Satguru Publications }}
* {{Citation | last =Kalupahana | first =David J. | author-link = | year =1992 | title =The Principles of Buddhist Psychology | place =Delhi | publisher =ri Satguru Publications }}
* {{Citation | last =Kalupahana | first =David J. | year =1994 | title =A history of Buddhist philosophy | place =Delhi | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass Publishers Private Limited}}
* {{Citation | last =Kalupahana | first =David J. | year =1994 | title =A History of Buddhist philosophy | place =Delhi | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass Publishers Private Limited}}
* {{Citation | last =Loy | first =David | year =2006 | title =Second Buddha : Nagarjuna - Buddhism's Greatest Philosopher. In: Winter 2006 edition of Tricycle : The Buddhist Review | url =http://www.thezensite.com/ZenEssays/Nagarjuna/SecondBuddha_Nagarjuna_Loy.html}}
* Ven. Khenpo Tsultrim Gyamtso, Rimpoche. ''Progressive Stages Of Meditation On Emptiness'', {{ISBN|0-9511477-0-6}}
* {{Citation | last =Magee | first =William | year =1999 | title =The Nature of Things. Emptiness and Essence in the Geluk World | place =Ithaca, New York | publisher =Snow Lion}}
* {{Citation|last=Lai |first=Whalen |year=2003 |title=Buddhism in China: A Historical Survey. In Antonio S. Cua (ed.): Encyclopedia of Chinese Philosophy |publisher=New York: Routledge |url=http://cw.routledge.com/ref/chinesephil/Buddhism.pdf |deadurl=yes |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20141112205228/http://cw.routledge.com/ref/chinesephil/Buddhism.pdf |archivedate=November 12, 2014 }}
*{{Citation | last1 = Rawson | first1 = Philip | title = Sacred Tibet | publisher = London, Thames and Hudson | year = 1991 | isbn = 0-500-81032-X}}
* {{Citation| last =Napper | first =Elizabeth | year =1989 | title =Dependent-Arising and Emptiness | isbn =0-86171-057-6}}
* {{Citation|last=Ng |first=Yu-kwan |title=Chih-i and Madhyamika |date=1990 |publisher=dissertation, McMaster University |location=Hamilton, Ontario |page=1 |url=http://digitalcommons.mcmaster.ca/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=9558&context=opendissertations |deadurl=yes |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20140203140705/http://digitalcommons.mcmaster.ca/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=9558&context=opendissertations |archivedate=February 3, 2014 }}
* {{Citation | last =Renard | first =Philip | year =2010 | title =Non-Dualisme. De directe bevrijdingsweg | place =Cothen | publisher =Uitgeverij Juwelenschip}}
* {{Citation | last =Renard | first =Philip | year =2010 | title =Non-Dualisme. De directe bevrijdingsweg | place =Cothen | publisher =Uitgeverij Juwelenschip}}
* {{Citation | last =Rizzi | first =Cesare | year =1988 | title =Candrakirti | place =Delhi | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass Publishers Private Limited}}
* {{Citation | last =Ruegg | first =D. Seyfort | year =1981 | title =The literature of the Madhyamaka school of philosophy in India (A History of Indian literature) | publisher =Harrassowitz | isbn =978-3-447-02204-0}}
* {{Citation | last =Sarma | first =Chandradhar | year =1996 | title =The Advaita Tradition in Indian Philosophy | place =Delhi | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass}}
* {{Citation | last =Sarma | first =Chandradhar | year =1996 | title =The Advaita Tradition in Indian Philosophy | place =Delhi | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass}}
* {{Citation | last =Snelling | first=John | year= 1987 |title =The Buddhist handbook. A Complete Guide to Buddhist Teaching and Practice | place =London | publisher =Century Paperbacks}}
* {{Citation | last1 =[[Shantarakshita]] | last2 =[[Ju Mipham]] | year =2005 | title =The Adornment of the Middle Way |publisher =Padmakara Translation | isbn =1-59030-241-9}}
* {{Citation | last =Suzuki | first =Daisetz Teitarō | authorlink =D.T. Suzuki | year =1999 | title =Studies in the Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra | place =Delhi | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass}}
* {{Citation | last =Suzuki | first =Daisetz Teitarō | authorlink =D.T. Suzuki | year =1999 | title =Studies in the Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra | place =Delhi | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass}}
* {{Citation | last =Wangyal Rinpoche | first =Tenzin | year =2004 | title =The Tibetan Yogas Of Dream And Sleep | place =Delhi | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass}}
* {{Citation | last =Thich Nhat Hanh | year =1988 | title =The Heart of Understanding: Commentaries on the Prajnaparamita Heart Sutra}}
* {{cite book|last1=Tsongkhapa|first1=Lobsang Dragpa|title=Ocean of Eloquence: Tsong kha pa's Commentary on the Yogacara Doctrine of Mind|year=1993|publisher=State University of New York|location=Albany, NY|isbn=0791414795|url=https://books.google.com/books?isbn=0791414795/ |edition=1་|last2=Sparham|first2= Gareth, trans.; in collaboration with Shotaro Iida|editor=Kapstein, Matthew|accessdate=18 December 2012|language=Tibetan, English}}
* {{Citation | last =Tsong Khapa | year =2002 | title =The great treatise on the stages of the path to enlightenment: Volume 3| publisher =Snow Lion Publications | isbn =1-55939-166-9}}
* {{Citation | last1 =rJe Tsong Kha Pa | last2 =Garfield (tr.)| first2 =Jay L. | last3 =Samten (tr.)| first3 =Ngawang | year =2006 | title =Ocean of Reasoning | place =Oxford | publisher =Oxford University Press | isbn = 978-0-19-514733-9}}
* {{Citation | last =Vetter | first =Tilmann | year =1988 | title =The Ideas and Meditative Practices of Early Buddhism | publisher =BRILL | isbn =90-04-08959-4 | url =http://ahandfulofleaves.files.wordpress.com/2012/08/the-ideas-and-meditative-practices-of-early-buddhism_vetter.pdf}}
* {{Citation | last =Warder | first =A. K. | year =2000 | title=Indian Buddhism | place=Delhi | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass Publishers}}
* {{Citation | last =Williams | first =Paul | year =2000 | title =Buddhist Thought | publisher =Routledge}}
* {{Citation | last =Wynne | first =Alexander | year =2007 | title =The Origin of Buddhist Meditation | publisher =Routledge}}
{{refend}}
{{refend}}

==Further reading==
* {{Citation | last =Brunnholzl | first =Karl | year =2004 | title =Center of the Sunlit Sky: Madhyamaka in the Kagyu Tradition | publisher =Snow Lion Publications}}
* {{Citation | last =Della Santina | first =Peter | year =1986 | title =Madhyamaka Schools in India | place =New Delhi | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass}}
* {{Citation | last =Harris | first =Ian Charles | year =1991 | title =The Continuity of Madhyamaka and Yogacara in Indian Mahayana Buddhism | place =New York | publisher =E. J.Brill}}
* {{Citation | last =His Holiness the Fourteenth Dalai Lama (Tenzin Gyatso) | year =2009 | title =The Middle Way: Faith Grounded in Reason | place =Boston | publisher =Wisdom Publications}}
* Huntington, C. W., Jr. (1989). The Emptiness of Emptiness: An Introduction to Early Madhyamika. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press
* {{Citation | last =Jones | first =Richard H. | year =2014 | title =Nagarjuna: Buddhism's Most Important Philosopher | place =New York | publisher =Jackson Square Books}}
* {{Citation | last =Jones | first =Richard H. | year =2012| title =Indian Madhyamaka Buddhist Philosophy After Nagarjuna, 2 vols.| place =New York | publisher =Jackson Square Books}}
* Narain, Harsh. The Mādhyamika mind. Motilal Banarsidass Publishers, 1997.
* {{Citation | last =Newland | first =Guy | year =2008 | title =Introduction to Emptiness: As Taught in Tsong-kha-pa's Great Treatise on the Stages of the Path | place =Boston| publisher =Snow Lion}}
* {{Citation | last =Ruegg | first =David S. | year =1981 | title =The Literature of the Madhyamaka School in India | place =Wiesbaden| publisher =Otto Harrassowitz}}
* {{Citation | last =Westeroff | first =Jan. | year =2009 | title =Nāgārjuna's Madhyamaka. A Philosophical Introduction| place =Oxford | publisher =Oxford University Press}}


==External links==
==External links==
{{commons category}}
*Zach Dorfman, [http://www.themontrealreview.com/2009/Toward-a-Buddhist-politics-of-freedom.php ''Toward a Buddhist Politics of Freedom''] (The Montreal Review, September 2011)
* [https://www.wisdomlib.org/hinduism/book/a-history-of-indian-philosophy-volume-1/d/doc209753.html The Mādhyamika or the Śūnyavāda school], Surendranath Dasgupta, 1940
* {{cite IEP |url-id=b-madhya |title=Madhyamaka Buddhism}}
* {{cite IEP |url-id=nagarjun |title=Nagarjuna}}
* [http://bahai-library.com/winters_nagarjuna Thinking in Buddhism: Nagarjuna's Middle Way]
* [http://www.thezensite.com/MainPages/nagarjuna.html thezensite: articles on Nagarjuna]
* [http://www.madhyamaka.com Introduction to the Middle Way] A contemporary commentary based on the teachings of Dzongsar Khyentse Rinpoche
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/madhyamaka/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Madhyamaka]
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/nagarjuna/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Nagarjuna]


{{Navboxes
|title = Articles related to Śūnyatā
|list =
{{Buddhism topics}}
{{Buddhism topics}}
{{Indian Philosophy}}
{{Meditation}}
}}


{{Authority control}}
{{Authority control}}


[[Category:Madhyamaka| ]]
{{DEFAULTSORT:Sunyata}}
[[Category:Buddhist philosophical concepts]]
[[Category:Buddhist terminology]]
[[Category:Madhyamaka]]
[[Category:Nondualism]]
[[Category:Nondualism]]
[[Category:Rangtong]]
[[Category:Rangtong]]

Revision as of 21:11, 3 September 2018

Madhyamaka (Template:Lang-sa, Chinese: 中觀见; pinyin: Zhōngguān Jìan; also known as Śūnyavāda) refers primarily to the later schools of Buddhist philosophy[1] founded by Nagarjuna (150 CE to 250 CE). According to Madhyamaka, all phenomena (dharmas) are empty (śūnya) of "nature,"[2] a "substance" or "essence" (svabhāva) which gives them "solid and independent existence,"[3] because they are dependently co-arisen. But this "emptiness" itself is also "empty": it does not have an existence on its own, nor does it refer to a transcendental reality beyond or above phenomenal reality.[4][5][6]

Etymology

Madhya is a Sanskrit word meaning "middle". It is cognate with Latin med-iu-s and English mid. The -ma suffix is a superlative, giving madhyama the meaning of "mid-most" or "medium". The -ka suffix is used to form adjectives, thus madhyamaka means "middleling". The -ika suffix is used to form possessives, with a collective sense, thus mādhyamika mean "belonging to the mid-most" (the -ika suffix regularly causes a lengthening of the first vowel and elision of the final -a).

In a Buddhist context these terms refer to the "middle path" (madhyama pratipada) between the extremes of annihilationism (ucchedavāda) and eternalism (śassatavāda), for example:

ity etāv ubhāv antāv anupagamya madhyamayā pratipadā tathāgato dharmaṃ deśayati | - Kātyāyana Sūtra.

Thus, the Tathāgata teaches the Dharma by a middle path avoiding both these extremes.

  • Madhyamaka refers to the school of thought associated with Nāgārjuna and his commentators.
  • Mādhyamika refers to adherents of the Madhyamaka school.

Note that in both words the stress is on the first syllable.

Emptiness

Central to Madhyamaka philosophy is śūnyatā, "emptiness." The term refers to the "emptiness" of inherent existence: all phenomena are empty of "substance" or "essence" (Template:Lang-sa) or inherent existence, because they are dependently co-arisen. At a conventional level, "things" do exist, but ultimately they are "empty" of inherent existence. But this "emptiness" itself is also "empty": it does not have an existence on its own, nor does it refer to a transcendental reality beyond or above phenomenal reality.[4][5][6]

Dependent Origination

Nagarjuna further develops the notion of dependent arising, arguing that every dharma, or every "thing", does not exist on its own, but depending on other "things" and causes:

Whatever is dependent arising
We declared that to be emptiness.
That is dependent designation,
And is itself the middle way.

— Nāgārjuna, Mūlamadhyamakakārikā 24:18

Svabhava - essence

Nagarjuna follows his own logic to its end, wondering what the subsequent consequences are of his propositions. Since all "things" are dependently arisen, how then can a non-existing "thing" cause another "thing" to come into being? In Chapter 15 of the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā Nagarjuna centers on the words svabhava [note 1] parabhava[note 2] bhava [note 3] and abhava:[note 4]

Nagarjuna's critique of the notion of own-nature[note 5] (Mk. ch. 15) argues that anything which arises according to conditions, as all phenomena do, can have no inherent nature, for what is depends on what conditions it. Moreover, if there is nothing with own-nature, there can be nothing with 'other-nature' (para-bhava), i.e. something which is dependent for its existence and nature on something else which has own-nature. Furthermore, if there is neither own-nature nor other-nature, there cannot be anything with a true, substantial existent nature (bhava). If there is no true existent, then there can be no non-existent (abhava).[13]

In chapter 15 of the Mulamadhyamakakarika, "Nagarjuna is playing on the word 'thing'".[web 1][note 6] Nagarjuna uses the ambivalence inherent in the term svabhava:

[T]he word "svabhava" can be interpreted in two different ways. It can be rendered either as identity [...] or as causal independence.[14]

This ambiguity is easily lost in translation:

When one reads Nagarjuna's argument in Sanskrit, it is not immediately obvious that the argument has taken advantage of an ambiguity in the key term. But when one tries to translate his argument into some other language, such as English or Tibetan, one finds that it is almost impossible to translate his argument in a way that makes sense in translation. This is because the terms in the language of translation do not have precisely the same range of ambiguities as the words in the original Sanskrit. In English, we are forced to disambiguate, and in disambiguating, we end up spoiling the apparent integrity of the argument.[14]

The doctrine of dependent arising cannot be reconciled with "a conception of self-nature or substance".[11] Nagarjuna refutes "the commentarial doctrine of the 'own-being' of principles as contrary to the Tripitaka":[7]

Nagarjuna had no objection to the Abhidhamma formulation of causal relations so long as the relata are not regarded as having a unique nature or substance (svabhava).[8]

The rejection of inherent existence does not imply that there is no existence at all.[10] What it does mean is that there is no "unique nature or substance (svabhava)"[8] in the "things" we perceive. This may not necessarily be in contrast to the Abhidhamma point of view, given the ambivalence in the terms used by Nagarjuna:

What Nagarjuna is saying is that no being has a fixed and permanent nature. What the abhidarmikas maintained was that every thing has features that distinguish it from other things.[15][note 7]

Two truths

Madhyamaka discerns two levels of truth, conventional truth and ultimate truth,[4] to make clear that it does make sense to speak of existence. Ultimately, we realize that all phenomena are sunyata, empty of concrete existence. Conventionally, we do perceive concrete objects which we are aware of.[17] Yet, this perceived reality is an experiential reality, not an ontological reality with substantial or independent existence.[17]

The ultimate truth of sunyata does not refer to "nothingness" or "non-existence"; it refers to the absence of inherent existence.[18]

According to Hayes, the two truths may also refer to two different goals in life: the highest goal of nirvana, and the lower goal of "commercial good". The highest goal is the liberation from attachment, both material and intellectual.[19]

Insight into the emptiness of "things' is part of developing wisdom, seeing things as they are. Conceiving of concrete and unchanging objects leads to clinging and suffering. Buddhapalita says:

What is the reality of things just as it is? It is the absence of essence. Unskilled persons whose eye of intelligence is obscured by the darkness of delusion conceive of an essence of things and then generate attachment and hostility with regard to them.

— Buddhapālita-mula-madhyamaka-vrtti P5242,73.5.6-74.1.2[20]

The emptiness of emptiness

Ultimate truth also does not refer to "absolute truth," some absolute reality above or beyond the "relative reality."[4] On the contrary, emptiness itself is "empty" of inherent existence:[5]

Ultimate truth does not point to a transcendent reality, but to the transcendence of deception. It is critical to emphasize that the ultimate truth of emptiness is a negational truth. In looking for inherently existent phenomena it is revealed that it cannot be found. This absence is not findable because it is not an entity, just as a room without an elephant in it does not contain an elephantless substance. Even conventionally, elephantlessness does not exist. Ultimate truth or emptiness does not point to an essence or nature, however subtle, that everything is made of.[web 2][note 8]

Essentialism and nihilism

What remains is the middle way between eternalism and annihilationism:[11]

The object of the critique is to show that the eternalist view is untenable and further to show that the 'own-being' theory adopted by some Buddhists did not really differ, when its implications were strictly worked out, from the eternalist theory of Brahmanism (the theory of an eternal 'soul' and other eternal 'substances').[10]

These two views are considered to be the two extreme views:

  1. Essentialism[21] or eternalism (sastavadava)[10] - a belief that things inherently exist and are therefore efficacious objects of craving and clinging;[21]
  2. Nihilism[21] or annihilationism (ucchedavada)[10] - views that lead one to believe that there is no need to be responsible for one's actions. Nagarjuna argues that we naively and innately perceive things as substantial, and it is this predisposition which is the root delusion that lies at the basis of all suffering.[21]

Madhyamaka represents the Middle way between them.

The limits of language

Madhyamaka uses language to make clear the limits of our concepts. Ultimately, reality cannot be depicted by concepts.[4][22] This creates a tension, since it does have to use concepts to convey its teachings:

This dynamic philosophical tension—a tension between the Madhyamika accounts of the limits of what can be coherently said and its analytical ostension of what cannot be said without paradox but must be understood—must constantly be borne in mind in reading the text. It is not an incoherent mysticism, but it is a logical tightrope act at the very limits of language and metaphysics.[22]

Liberation

The ultimate aim of understanding emptiness is not philosophical insight as such, but to gain a liberated mind which does not dwell upon concepts. To realize this, meditation on emptiness may proceed in stages, starting with the emptiness of both self, objects and mental states,[23] culminating in a "natural state of nonreferential freedom."[24][note 9]

Origins and development

Nagarjuna

The Madhyamaka school is usually considered to have been founded by Nāgārjuna, though it may have existed earlier. [25] The name of the school is perhaps related to its close adherence to Nāgārjuna’s main work, the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā. The term Madhyamaka is related to 'madhya' ('the middle').

Madhyamaka-thought had a major influence on the subsequent development of the Mahayana Buddhist tradition, although often in interaction with, and also in opposition to, the other two major streams of Mahayana Buddhist thought, namely Yogacara and Buddha-nature. It had a major impact on Tibetan Buddhism, where it became the orthodox standard in the Gelugpa tradition, in opposition to Jonangpa's "Mahā-Mādhyamaka". Lama Je Tsongkhapa, of the Gelugpa, claimed there were two division in Indian Madhyamika, creating the Svatantrika-Prasaṅgika distinction.[26] It also influenced the Zen tradition,[4] although this influence is less often discerned in comparison to the Buddha-nature thought. The present day schools of Tiantai, Tendai, Sanron,[27] are also influenced by the Mādhyamaka tradition, forming an East Asian Mādhyamaka tradition. Contemporary western Buddhism is less acquainted with Madhyamaka thought, although some implications have been recognized by western teachers.

Origins

Sutta Nipata

The Aṭṭhakavagga (Pali, "Octet Chapter") and the Pārāyanavagga (Pali, "Way to the Far Shore Chapter") are two small collections of suttas within the Pāli Canon of Theravada Buddhism.[note 10] They are among the earliest existing Buddhist literature, and place considerable emphasis on the rejection of, or non-attachment to, all views.

Gomez compared them to later Madhyamaka philosophy, which in its Prasaṅgika form especially makes a method of rejecting others' views rather than proposing its own.[28]

Tillman Vetter, although agreeing overall with Gomez's observations, suggests some refinements on historical and doctrinal grounds.[29] First, he notes that neither of these short collections of suttas are homogeneous and hence are not all amenable to Gomez' proposals. According to Vetter, those suttas which do lend support to Gomez probably originated with a heterodox ascetic group that pre-dated the Buddha, and were integrated into the Buddhist Sangha at an early date, bringing with them some suttas that were already in existence and also composing further suttas in which they tried to combine their own teachings with those of the Buddha.[29]

Paul Fuller has rejected the arguments of Gomez and Vetter.[30] He finds that

... the Nikayas and the Atthakavagga present the same cognitive attitude toward views, wrong or right.[31]

Alexander Wynne also rejects both of Vetter's claims that the Parayanavagga shows a chronological stratification, and a different attitude toward mindfulness and liberating insight than do other works.[32][note 11]

Abhidharma

The Madhyamaka school has been perhaps simplistically regarded as a reaction against the development of the Abhidharma, especially the Sarvāstivādin. In the Abhidharma, dharmas are characterized by defining traits (lakṣaṇa) or own-existence (svabhāva), whose ontological status is not dependent upon concepts. The problem with the Abhidharma is not that things are 'independently existent' (a position that most Abhidharma schools would not accept), but rather (from a Madhyamaka perspective) that they are independent from notions. For the Madhyamaka, dharmas are notionally dependent, and further more, their notional dependence entails existential dependence and hence lack of ultimate, true existence.

The relationship between Madhyamaka and Abhidharma is complex; Abhidharmic analysis figures prominently in most Madhyamaka treatises, and authoritative commentators like Candrakīrti emphasize that Abhidharmic categories function as a viable (and favored) system of conventional truths - they are more refined than ordinary categories, and they are not dependent on either the extreme of eternalism or on the extreme view of the discontinuity of karma, as the non-Buddhist categories of the time did. It may be therefore important to understand that Madhyamaka constitutes a continuation of the Abhidharma type of analysis, extending the range of dependent arising to entail (and focus upon) notional dependence. The dependent arising of concepts based on other concepts, rather than the true arising of really existent causes and effects, becomes here the matrix of any possible convention.

Prajñāpāramitā

Madhyamaka thought is also closely related to a number of Mahāyāna sources; traditionally, the Prajñāpāramitāsūtras are the literature most closely associated with Madhyamaka – understood, at least in part, as an exegetical complement to those Sūtras. Traditional accounts also depict Nāgārjuna as retrieving some of the larger Prajñāpāramitāsūtras from the world of the Nāgas (explaining in part the etymology of his name). Prajñā or ‘higher cognition’ is a recurrent term in Buddhist texts, explained as a synonym of Abhidharma, ‘insight’ (vipaśyanā) and ‘analysis of the dharmas’ (dharmapravicaya). Within a specifically Mahāyāna context, Prajñā figures as the most prominent in a list of Six Pāramitās (‘perfections’ or ‘perfect masteries’) that a Bodhisattva needs to cultivate in order to eventually achieve Buddhahood. Madhyamaka offers conceptual tools to analyze all possible elements of existence, allowing the practitioner to elicit through reasoning and contemplation the type of view that the Sūtras express more authoritatively (being considered word of the Buddha) but less explicitly (not offering corroborative arguments). The vast Prajñāpāramitā literature emphasizes the development of higher cognition in the context of the Bodhisattva path; thematically, its focus on the emptiness of all dharmas is closely related to the Madhyamaka approach.

Pyrrhonism

Because of the high degree of similarity between Madhyamaka and Pyrrhonism,[33] Thomas McEvilley[34] and Matthew Neale[35] suspect that Nāgārjuna was influenced by Greek Pyrrhonist texts imported into India. Pyrrho of Elis (c. 360-c. 270 BCE), who is credited with founding this school of skeptical philosophy, was himself influenced by Buddhist philosophy during his stay in India with Alexander the Great's army.

Indian Madhyamaka

Nāgārjuna

Kalupahana has argued that Nāgārjuna's intention was not to establish an ontology or epistemology, but to free the Buddhist soteriology from essentialist notions which obscured the Buddhist Middle Way:[36]

Āryadeva

Nāgārjuna's pupil Āryadeva (3rd century CE) emphasized the Bodhisattva-ideal. His works are regarded as a supplement to Nāgārjuna's,[37] on which he commented.[38] Āryadeva also refuted the theories of non-Buddhist Indian philosophical schools.[38]

Buddhapālita and Bhāvaviveka

Buddhapālita (470–550) has been understood as the origin of the prāsaṅgika approach.[39] He was criticized by Bhāvaviveka (ca.500–ca.578), who argued for the use of syllogisms "to set one's own doctrinal stance".[40] Bhāvya/Bhāvaviveka was influenced by the Yogācāra school.

The opposing approaches of Buddhapālita and Bhāvya are explained by later Tibetan doxographers as the origin of a subdivision of Madhyamaka into two schools, the Prāsaṅgika and the Svātantrika.

Candrakīrti

Candrakīrti (600–c. 650) wrote the Prasannapadā (Clear Words), a highly influential commentary on the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā. This commentary is central in the understanding of Madhyamaka in Tibetan Buddhism.

Śāntideva

Śāntideva (end 7th century – first half 8th century) is well known for his Bodhisattvacaryāvatāra, A Guide to the Bodhisattva's Way of Life. He united "a deep religiousness and joy of exposure together with the unquestioned Madhyamaka orthodoxy".[41]

Shantarakshita

A Yogācāra and Mādhyamaka synthesis was posited by Shantarakshita in the 8th century[note 12] and may have been common at Nalanda University at that time. Like the Prāsaṅgika, this view approaches ultimate truth through the prasaṅga method, yet when speaking of conventional reality they may make autonomous statements like the earlier Svātantrika and Yogācāra approaches.

This was different from the earlier Svatantrika in that the conventional truth was described in terms of the theory of consciousness-only instead of the tenets of Svatantrika, though neither was used to analyze for ultimate truth.

For example, they may assert that all phenomena are nothing but the "play of mind" and hence empty of concrete existence—and that mind is in turn empty of defining characteristics. But in doing so, they're careful to point out that any such example would be an approximate ultimate and not the true ultimate. By making such autonomous statements, Yogācāra-Svatantrika-Madhyamaka is often mistaken as a Svātantrika or Yogācāra view, even though a Prāsaṅgika approach was used in analysis.[42] This view is thus a synthesis of Madhyamaka and Yogācāra.

Tibetan Buddhism

Tibetan classification of schools

Madhyamaka thought has been categorized variously in India and Tibet.[note 13] In Tibetan Buddhism a major difference is being made between "Svātantrika-Madhyamaka" and "Prasaṅgika-Madhyamaka." Yet, the classification is more complicated, and is described by Guy Newman as follows:

  • Rangtong, a term introduced by Dolpopa, which rejects any inherent existing self or nature.[43] This includes:
  • Intellectual emptiness, which is realized by mere negation. This is the view of Tsong Khapa and the Gelugpa school, which rejects any statements on an absolute reality beyond mere emptiness.[45]
  • Experiential emptiness, which is realized when the understanding of intellectual emptiness gives way to the recognition of the true nature of mind, c.q. rigpa. This is the view of Nyingma (Dzogchen) and Sakya.[45]
  • Shentong, systematised by Dolpopa, and based on Buddha-nature teachings and influenced by Śāntarakṣita's Yogacara-Madhyamaka. It states that the nature of mind shines through when emptiness has been realized. This approach is dominant in the Jonang school, and can also be found in the Kagyu (Mahamudra) tradition.[46][47][48]

The Madhyamika philosophy obtained a central position in all the Tibetan schools, but with two distinct variations, namely shentong, and the later Gelugpa emphasis on a strict Prasangika interpretation of emptiness. Shentong is a further developed Yogacara-Madhyamaka which incorporates Buddha-nature teachings, and states that the reality which is laid bare by understanding emptiness is luminous awareness and truly existing. Shentong teachings are still transmitted in the Nyingma, Kagyu, and Jonang school. Tsongkhapa, and the subsequent Gelugpa tradition, opposes this notion of self-luminous awareness, and sees its own interpretation as the final truth on sunyata.

Although presented as a divide in doctrines, the major difference between svātantrika and prasangika may be between two style of reasoning and arguing, while the division itself is exclusively Tibetan. Tibetan scholars were aware of alternative Madhyamaka sub-classifications, but later Tibetan doxography emphasizes the nomenclature of prāsaṅgika versus svātantrika. No conclusive evidence can show the existence of an Indian antecedent, and it is not certain to what degree individual writers in Indian and Tibetan discussion held each of these views and if they held a view generally or only in particular instances. Both Prāsaṅgikas and Svātantrikas cited material in the āgamas in support of their arguments.[49]

Svātantrika

Bhavaviveka (c. 500 – c. 578) is the first person to whom this view is attributed, as they are laid out in his commentaries on Nāgārjuna and his critiques of Buddhapalita. Svātantrika in Sanskrit refers to autonomy and was translated back into Sanskrit from the equivalent Tibetan term.[50]

The Svātantrika states that conventional phenomena are understood to have a conventional essential existence, but without an ultimately existing essence. In this way they believe they are able to make positive or "autonomous" assertions using syllogistic logic because they are able to share a subject that is established as appearing in common - the proponent and opponent use the same kind of valid cognition to establish it. The name comes from this quality of being able to use autonomous arguments in debate.[50]

Ju Mipham explained that using positive assertions in logical debate may serve a useful purpose, either while debating with non-Buddhist schools or to move a student from a coarser to a more subtle view. Similarly, discussing an approximate ultimate helps students who have difficulty using only prasaṅga methods move closer to the understanding of the true ultimate. Ju Mipham felt that the ultimate non-enumerated truth of the Svatantrika was no different from the ultimate truth of the Prāsaṅgika. He felt the only difference between them was with respect to how they discussed conventional truth and their approach to presenting a path.[50]

Prāsaṅgika

The central technique avowed by Prasaṅgika Mādhyamaka is to show by prasaṅga (or reductio ad absurdum) that any positive assertion (such as "asti" or "nāsti", "it is", or "it is not") or view regarding phenomena must be regarded as merely conventional (saṃvṛti or lokavyavahāra).

The Prāsaṅgika hold that it is not necessary for the proponent and opponent to use the same kind of valid cognition to establish a common subject; indeed it is possible to change the view of an opponent through a reductio argument.

Buddhapalita and Candrakirti are noted as the main proponents of this approach. Tibetan teacher Longchen Rabjam noted in the 14th century that Candrakirti favored the prasaṅga approach when specifically discussing the analysis for ultimacy, but otherwise he made positive assertions. His central text, Madhyamakavatāra, is structured as a description of the paths and results of practice, which is made up of positive assertions. Therefore, even those most attributed to the Prāsaṅgika view make positive assertions when discussing a path of practice but use prasaṅga specifically when analyzing for ultimate truth.[50]

Tsongkhapa

The Gelug school was founded by Je Tsongkhapa's reforms to Atisha's Kadam tradition in the 14th century.[note 14] Tsongkhapa emphasized compassion and insight into emptiness.

In his Ocean of Reasoning, Tsongkhapa comments on the Mulamadhyamakakarika.[51] According to Tsongkhapa, Nagarjuna uses the term svabhava to refer to sunyata as the nature of reality:[52]

Their nature of emptiness is their reality nature.[53]

This is in line with the Eight Thousand Stanza Perfection of Wisdom Sutra:

Subhuti, since the five aggregates are without nature, they have a nature of emptiness.[53]

Although Tsongkhapa argued in favour of Yogacara views early in his career[54] his later understanding is derived from Candrakirti,[55] who states that conventionally there are entities with distinguishing characteristics, but ultimately those qualities are not independent essences. But since this emptiness is true for everything that exists, this emptiness may also be regarded as an essence, though not in the sense of an independent essence. Candrakirti formulates a final negation by stating that even the denial of svabhava implies ...

...that either oneself or one's audience is not entirely free from the belief in svabhava. Therefore, ultimate truth, truth as it is for those who are free from misknowledge, cannot be expressed by asserting either the existence or nonexistence of svahbava.[56]

Shentong - Jonangpa

Dolpopa, the founder of the Jonangpa school, called his synthesis the Mahā-Mādhyamaka, the "Great Middle Way".[57] He regarded the tathagatagarbha to be the true emptiness. This view was opposed by Tsongkhapa. [58]

Chán/Zen

The Chán/Zen-tradition emulated Madhyamaka-thought via the San-lun Buddhists, influencing its supposedly "illogical" way of communicating "absolute truth."[4]

Western Buddhism

Thich Nhat Hanh

Thich Nhat Hanh explains the Madhyamaka concept of emptiness through the related concept of interdependence. In this analogy, there is no first or ultimate cause for anything that occurs. Instead, all things are dependent on innumerable causes and conditions that are themselves dependent on innumerable causes and conditions. The interdependence of all phenomena, including the self, is a helpful way to undermine mistaken views about inherence, or that one's self is inherently existent. It is also a helpful way to discuss Mahayana teachings on motivation, compassion, and ethics. The comparison to interdependence has produced recent discussion comparing Mahayana ethics to environmental ethics.[59]

Modern Madhyamaka

Madhyamaka forms an alternative to the Perennialist and essentialist (neo-)Advaita understanding of nondualism or modern spirituality.[web 3][web 4][web 5] The classical Madhyamaka-teachings are complemented with western (post-modern) philosophy,[web 6] critical sociology,[web 7] and social constructionism.[web 8] These approaches stress that there is no transcendental reality beyond this phenomenal world,[web 9] and in some cases even explicitly distinguish themselves from (neo-)Advaita approaches.[web 10]

Influence on Advaita Vedanta

Gaudapada, who was strongly influenced by Buddhism, borrowed the concept of "ajāta" from Nagajurna's Madhyamaka philosophy,[60][61] which uses the term "anutpāda":[62]

  • "An" means "not", or "non"
  • "Utpāda" means "genesis", "coming forth", "birth"[web 11]

Taken together "anutpāda" means "having no origin", "not coming into existence", "not taking effect", "non-production".[web 12]

The Buddhist tradition usually uses the term "anutpāda" for the absence of an origin[60][62] or sunyata.[63][note 15]

"Ajātivāda" is the fundamental philosophical doctrine of Gaudapada.[67] According to Gaudapada, the Absolute is not subject to birth, change and death. The Absolute is aja, the unborn eternal.[67] The empirical world of appearances is considered unreal, and not absolutely existent.[67]

Gaudapada's perspective is quite different from Nagarjuna.[68] Gaudapada's perspective is based on the Mandukya Upanishad.[68] In the Mandukya Karika, Gaudapada's commentary on the Mandukya Upanishad, Gaudapada sets forth his perspective. According to Gaudapada, Brahman cannot undergo alteration, so the phenomenal world cannot arise from Brahman. If the world cannot arise, yet is an empirical fact, then the world has to be an unreal[note 16] appearance of Brahman. And if the phenomenal world is an unreal appearance, then there is no real origination or destruction, only apparent origination or destruction. From the level of ultimate truth (paramārthatā) the phenomenal world is Maya.[68]

As stated in Gaudapada’s Karika Chapter II Verse 48:[web 13]

No jiva ever comes into existence. There exists no cause that can produce it. The supreme truth is that nothing ever is born.[web 14]

Understanding in modern scholarship

Western scholarship has given a broad variety of interpretations of Madhyamaka:

Over the past half-century the doctrine of the Madhyamaka school, and in particular that of Nāgārjuna has been variously described as nihilism, monism, irrationalism, misology, agnosticism, scepticism, criticism, dialectic, mysticism, acosmism, absolutism, relativism, nominalism, and linguistic analysis with therapeutic value.[69]

Jay L. Garfield likewise rephrases Ruegg:

"Modern interpreters differ among themselves about the correct way to read it as least as much as canonical interpreters. Nagarjuna has been read as an idealist (Murti 1960), a nihilist (Wood 1994), a skeptic (Garfield 1995), a pragmatist (Kalupahana 1986), and as a mystic (Streng 1967). He has been regarded as a critic of logic (Inada 1970), as a defender of classical logic (Hayes 1994), and as a pioneer of paraconsistent logic (Garfield and Priest 2003)".[70]

These interpretations "reflect almost as much about the viewpoints of the scholars involved as do they reflect the content of Nāgārjuna's concepts".[71]

Most recent western scholarship (Garfield,[72] Napper,[73] Hopkins,[74] Huntington, and others) have, after investigation, tended to adopt one or another of the Gelugpa collegiate interpretations of Madhyamaka.

Kalupahana

Kalupahana's interpretation sees Madhyamaka, along with Yogacara, as an antidote against essentialist biases in Mahayana Buddhist thought.[75][76]

Hayes

Richard P. Hayes is critical of the works of Nagarjuna:

Nagarjuna’s writings had relatively little effect on the course of subsequent Indian Buddhist philosophy. Despite his apparent attempts to discredit some of the most fundamental concepts of abhidharma, abhidharma continued to flourish for centuries, without any appreciable attempt on the part of abhidharmikas to defend their methods of analysis against Nagarjuna’s criticisms.[77]

According to Hayes, Nagarjuna makes use of two different possible meanings of the word svabhava, and uses those two meanings to make statements which are not logical.[78] In doing so, Hayes regards Nagarjuna...

[A] relatively primitive thinker whose mistakes in reasoning were eventually uncovered as the knowledge of logic in India became more sophisticated in subsequent centuries.[79]

Magee

William Magee strongly disagrees with Hayes. He points out the influence of Nagarjuna in Tibetan Buddhism, and refers to Tsonghkhapa's interpretation of Nagarjuna to argue that

Hayes is misidentifying Nagarjuna's intended meaning of svabhava. In contradistinction to Hayes' belief that Nagarjuna speaks equivocably of an identity nature and a causally independent, non-existent nature, Dzong-ka-ba feels that in chapter XV.1-2 Nagarjuna uses the term svabhava to refer to an existent emptiness nature.[80]

According to Magee, both Candrakirti and Dzong-ka-ba "see Nagarjuna as consistently referring to emptiness with the word svabhava".[81]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ 'Own-beings',[7] unique nature or substance,[8] an identifying characteristic; an identity; an essence,[9]
  2. ^ A differentiating characteristic,[9] the fact of being dependent,[9]
  3. ^ 'Being',[10] 'self-nature or substance'[11]
  4. ^ Not being present; absence:[12]
  5. ^ svabhava
  6. ^ Stephen Batchelor, Verses from the Centre, Chapter 15 (Investigation of Essences), note for verse 3: "There is a problem here with the Tibetan translation from Sanskrit. Svabhava is translated as rang bzhin, but parabhava rather clumsily as gzhan gyi dngos po [the term first appears in I:3]. A Tibetan reader would thus lose the etymological connection between "own-thing" (svabhava) and "other-thing" (parabhava), which then link up with "thing" (bhava) and no-thing (abhava). Nagarjuna is playing on the word "thing".[web 1]
  7. ^ Warder: "From Nagarjuna's own day onwards his doctrine was subject to being misunderstood as nihilistic: because he rejected 'existence' of beings and spoke of their 'emptiness' (of own-being), careless students (and critics who were either not very careful or not very scrupulous) have concluded that he maintained that ultimately the universe was an utter nothingness. In fact, his rejection of 'non-existence' is as emphatic as his rejection of 'existence', and must therefore lead us to the conclusion that what he is attacking are the notions or assertions themselves as metaphysical concepts imposed on ultimate reality, which is entirely beyond any possible concept or definition.[16]
  8. ^ Susan Kahn further explains: "The emptiness of emptiness refutes ultimate truth as yet another argument for essentialism under the guise of being beyond the conventional or as the foundation of it. To realize emptiness is not to find a transcendent place or truth to land in but to see the conventional as merely conventional. Here lies the key to liberation. For to see the deception is to be free of deception, like a magician who knows the magic trick. When one is no longer fooled by false appearances, phenomena are neither reified nor denied. They are understood interdependently, as ultimately empty and thus, as only conventionally real. This is the Middle Way."[web 2]
  9. ^ See also Atthakavagga and Parayanavagga, for early, Madhyamaka-like texts from the Buddhist canon on freedom from views.
  10. ^ In the Pali canon, these chapters are the fourth and fifth chapters of the Khuddaka Nikaya's Sutta Nipata, respectively.
  11. ^ Wynne devotes a chapter to the Parayanavagga.
  12. ^ Alex Trisoglio: "In the 8th century, Shantarakshita went to Tibet and founded the monastery at Samyé. He was not a direct disciple of Bhavaviveka, but the disciple of one of his disciples. He combined the Madhyamika-Svatantrika and Cittamatra schools, and created a new school of Madhyamika called Svatantrika-Yogachara-Madhyamika. His disciple Kamalashila, who wrote The Stages of Meditation upon Madhyamika (uma’i sgom rim), developed his ideas further, and together they were very influential in Tibet."Khyentse Rinpoche, Dzongsar Jamyang (2003). "Introduction". In Alex Trisoglio (ed.). Introduction to the Middle Way: Chandrakirti's Madhyamakavatara with Commentary (PDF) (1st ed.). Dordogne, France: Khyentse Foundation. p. 8. Retrieved 7 January 2013.
  13. ^ In his Tattvaratnāvalī, the Indian scholar Advayavajra classified Madhyamaka into "those who uphold non-duality from the simile of illusion" (māyopamādvayavādin) and "those who uphold non-placement into any dharma" (sarvadharmāpratiṣṭhānavādin); furthermore, in the Madhyamakaṣaṭka he envisaged a specifically Vajrayāna type of Madhyamaka.[citation needed]
  14. ^ Alexander Berzin: There was a very famous Nyingma lama at the time called Lhodrag Namka-gyeltsen, and this Nyingma lama had, continually, visions of Vajrapani. And he invited Tsongkhapa, and they became mutual teacher and disciple. It is from this Nyingma lama that Tsongkhapa got his main lam-rim transmissions from the Kadam tradition — two of the main Kadam lineages. There are three Kadampa lineages that had split. He got two of them from this Nyingma lama and one from a Kagyu lama. The Kadampa was divided into three: One was the lam-rim teachings, one was the textual teachings, and one was the oral guideline teachings. So he got the lam-rim and the oral guideline lineages from this Nyingma lama, and the textual tradition from a Kagyu lama. This I find very interesting. One always thinks that he got them from Kadampa lamas; he didn’t. And that Gelugpa was so separate from all these other traditions; it wasn’t. Look at this Kagyu lama, Lama Umapa, that Tsongkhapa studied Madhyamaka with; he had studied Madhyamaka with Sakya. The Sakyas were the main Madhyamaka people of those days.Berzin, Alexander (December 2003). "The Life of Tsongkhapa". Munich, Germany. Retrieved 20 June 2016.
  15. ^ The term is also used in the Lankavatara Sutra.[64] According to D.T Suzuki, "anutpada" is not the opposite of "utpada", but transcends opposites. It is the seeing into the true nature of existence,[65] the seeing that "all objects are without self-substance".[66]
  16. ^ C.q. "transitory"

References

Published references

  1. ^ Williams 2000, p. 140.
  2. ^ Brunholzl 2004, p. 70.
  3. ^ Brunholzl 2004, p. 590.
  4. ^ a b c d e f g Cheng 1981.
  5. ^ a b c Garfield 1994.
  6. ^ a b Garfield 2012.
  7. ^ a b Warder 2000, p. 360.
  8. ^ a b c Kalupahana 1994, p. 162.
  9. ^ a b c Hayes 1994, p. 317.
  10. ^ a b c d e Warder 2000, p. 361.
  11. ^ a b c Kalupahana 1994, p. 165.
  12. ^ Hayes 1994, p. 316.
  13. ^ Harvey 1995, p. 97.
  14. ^ a b Hayes 2003, p. 4.
  15. ^ Hayes 2003, p. 10.
  16. ^ Warder 2000, p. 363.
  17. ^ a b Brunholzl 2004, p. 73.
  18. ^ Chenh 1981.
  19. ^ Hayes 2003, p. 8-9.
  20. ^ Tsong Khapa 2002.
  21. ^ a b c d Garfield 1995, p. 88 footnote.
  22. ^ a b Garfield 1995, p. 102.
  23. ^ Brunholzl 2004, p. 295-310.
  24. ^ Brunholzl 2004, p. 310.
  25. ^ Warder 2000, p. 358.
  26. ^ Tsongkhapa, Lamrim Chenmo V3 P116
  27. ^ Ng 1990, p. 1.
  28. ^ Gomez 1976.
  29. ^ a b Vetter 1988.
  30. ^ Fuller 2005.
  31. ^ Fuller 2005, p. 151.
  32. ^ Wynne 2007, p. 75.
  33. ^ Adrian Kuzminski, Pyrrhonism: How the Ancient Greeks Reinvented Buddhism 2008
  34. ^ Thomas McEvilley, The Shape of Ancient Thought 2002 pp499-505
  35. ^ https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=NMZwyPdY7eg&t=52s
  36. ^ Kalupahana 1994, p. 169.
  37. ^ Warder 2000, p. 368.
  38. ^ a b Rizzi 1988, p. 2.
  39. ^ Rizzi 1988, p. 3.
  40. ^ Rizzi 1988, p. 4.
  41. ^ Rizzi 1988, p. 5.
  42. ^ Shantarakshita 2005, p. 117-122.
  43. ^ Cornu 2001, p. 146-147.
  44. ^ Cornu 2001, p. 138.
  45. ^ a b Cornu 2001, p. 145.
  46. ^ Hookam 1991.
  47. ^ Brunnhölzl 2004.
  48. ^ Cornu 2001.
  49. ^ Gombrich 1996, p. 27-28.
  50. ^ a b c d Shantarakshita 2005, p. 131-141.
  51. ^ rJe Tsong Kha Pa 2006.
  52. ^ Magee 1999, p. 125-127.
  53. ^ a b Magee 1999, p. 32.
  54. ^ Tsongkhapa 1993.
  55. ^ Magee 1999.
  56. ^ Rizzi 1988, p. 19.
  57. ^ Magee 1999, p. 103.
  58. ^ Magee 1999, p. 103-115.
  59. ^ Thich Nhat Hanh 1988.
  60. ^ a b Renard 2010, p. 157.
  61. ^ Comans 2000, p. 35-36.
  62. ^ a b Bhattacharya 1943, p. 49.
  63. ^ Renard 2010, p. 160.
  64. ^ Suzuki 1999.
  65. ^ Suzuki 1999, p. 123-124.
  66. ^ Suzuki 1999, p. 168.
  67. ^ a b c Sarma 1996, p. 127.
  68. ^ a b c Comans 2000, p. 36.
  69. ^ Ruegg 1981, p. 2. sfn error: multiple targets (2×): CITEREFRuegg1981 (help)
  70. ^ Garfield and Samten 2006, p. xx.
  71. ^ Daye 1971, p. 77.
  72. ^ Garfield 1995.
  73. ^ Napper 1989.
  74. ^ Hopkins 1996.
  75. ^ Kalupahana 1992.
  76. ^ Kalupahana 1994.
  77. ^ Hayes 2003, p. 2.
  78. ^ Hayes 2003, p. 3-5.
  79. ^ Hayes 2003, p. 7.
  80. ^ Magee 1999, p. 126.
  81. ^ Magee 1999, p. 127.

Web references

Sources

  • Arena, Leonardo Vittorio (2012), Nonsense as the Meaning, ebook
  • Arnold, Dan (2010). Nāgārjuna’s ‘Middle Way’: A Non-Eliminative Understanding of Selflessness. In:Revue Internationale de Philosophie vol. 64, no.253: 367-395
  • Bhattacharya, Vidhushekhara (1943), Gauḍapādakārikā, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass
  • Brunnholzl, Karl (2004), Center of the Sunlit Sky: Madhyamaka in the Kagyu Tradition, Snow Lion Publications
  • Cheng, Hsueh-Li (1981), "The Roots of Zen Buddhism", Journal of Chinese Philosophy, 8: 451–478, doi:10.1111/j.1540-6253.1981.tb00267.x
  • Comans, Michael (2000), The Method of Early Advaita Vedānta: A Study of Gauḍapāda, Śaṅkara, Sureśvara, and Padmapāda, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass
  • Cornu, Philippe (2001), "Nawoord", Schijn en werkelijkheid. De twee waarheden in de vier boeddhistische leerstelsels, KunchabPublicaties
  • Daye, Douglas D. (1971), Major Schools of the Mahayana: Madhyamaka. In:Charles S. Prebisch, Buddhism, A Modern Perspective. Pages 76-96., ISBN 978-0-271-01195-0
  • Fuller, Paul (2005), The Notion of Diṭṭhi in Theravāda Buddhism: The Point of View (PDF), Routledge, archived from the original (PDF) on 2014-12-02 {{citation}}: Unknown parameter |deadurl= ignored (|url-status= suggested) (help)
  • Garfield, Jay L. (1994), "Dependent Arising and the Emptiness of Emptiness: Why did Nagarjuana start with causation?", Philosophy East & West, 44 (2)
  • Garfield, Jay L. (1995), The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way, Oxford: Oxford University Press
  • Garfield, Jay L. (2012), Madhyamaka is not emptiness (PDF), smith College, University of melbourne
  • Gomez, Luis O. (1976), "Proto-Mādhyamika in the Pāli canon", Philosophy East and West, 26 (2): 137–165, doi:10.2307/1398186
  • Harvey, Peter (1995), An introduction to Buddhism. Teachings, history and practices, Cambridge University Press
  • Hayes, Richard P. (1994), Nagarjuna's appeal. In: Journal of Indian Philosophy 22: 299-378
  • Hayes, Richard P. (2003), Nagarjuna: Master of Paradox,Mystic or Perpetrator of Fallacies? (PDF)
  • Hookham, S.K. (1991), The Buddha within : Tathagatagarbha doctrine according to the Shentong interpretation of the Ratnagotravibhaga, Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, ISBN 978-0791403587
  • Hopkins, Jeffrey; Napper, Elizabeth (1996), Meditation on Emptiness
  • Kalupahana, David J. (1992), The Principles of Buddhist Psychology, Delhi: ri Satguru Publications
  • Kalupahana, David J. (1994), A History of Buddhist philosophy, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers Private Limited
  • Loy, David (2006), Second Buddha : Nagarjuna - Buddhism's Greatest Philosopher. In: Winter 2006 edition of Tricycle : The Buddhist Review
  • Magee, William (1999), The Nature of Things. Emptiness and Essence in the Geluk World, Ithaca, New York: Snow Lion
  • Napper, Elizabeth (1989), Dependent-Arising and Emptiness, ISBN 0-86171-057-6
  • Ng, Yu-kwan (1990), Chih-i and Madhyamika, Hamilton, Ontario: dissertation, McMaster University, p. 1, archived from the original on February 3, 2014 {{citation}}: Unknown parameter |deadurl= ignored (|url-status= suggested) (help)
  • Renard, Philip (2010), Non-Dualisme. De directe bevrijdingsweg, Cothen: Uitgeverij Juwelenschip
  • Rizzi, Cesare (1988), Candrakirti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers Private Limited
  • Ruegg, D. Seyfort (1981), The literature of the Madhyamaka school of philosophy in India (A History of Indian literature), Harrassowitz, ISBN 978-3-447-02204-0
  • Sarma, Chandradhar (1996), The Advaita Tradition in Indian Philosophy, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass
  • Shantarakshita; Ju Mipham (2005), The Adornment of the Middle Way, Padmakara Translation, ISBN 1-59030-241-9
  • Suzuki, Daisetz Teitarō (1999), Studies in the Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass
  • Thich Nhat Hanh (1988), The Heart of Understanding: Commentaries on the Prajnaparamita Heart Sutra
  • Tsongkhapa, Lobsang Dragpa; Sparham, Gareth, trans.; in collaboration with Shotaro Iida (1993). Kapstein, Matthew (ed.). Ocean of Eloquence: Tsong kha pa's Commentary on the Yogacara Doctrine of Mind (in Tibetan and English) (1་ ed.). Albany, NY: State University of New York. ISBN 0791414795. Retrieved 18 December 2012.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  • Tsong Khapa (2002), The great treatise on the stages of the path to enlightenment: Volume 3, Snow Lion Publications, ISBN 1-55939-166-9
  • rJe Tsong Kha Pa; Garfield (tr.), Jay L.; Samten (tr.), Ngawang (2006), Ocean of Reasoning, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN 978-0-19-514733-9
  • Vetter, Tilmann (1988), The Ideas and Meditative Practices of Early Buddhism (PDF), BRILL, ISBN 90-04-08959-4
  • Warder, A. K. (2000), Indian Buddhism, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers
  • Williams, Paul (2000), Buddhist Thought, Routledge
  • Wynne, Alexander (2007), The Origin of Buddhist Meditation, Routledge

Further reading

  • Brunnholzl, Karl (2004), Center of the Sunlit Sky: Madhyamaka in the Kagyu Tradition, Snow Lion Publications
  • Della Santina, Peter (1986), Madhyamaka Schools in India, New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass
  • Harris, Ian Charles (1991), The Continuity of Madhyamaka and Yogacara in Indian Mahayana Buddhism, New York: E. J.Brill
  • His Holiness the Fourteenth Dalai Lama (Tenzin Gyatso) (2009), The Middle Way: Faith Grounded in Reason, Boston: Wisdom Publications
  • Huntington, C. W., Jr. (1989). The Emptiness of Emptiness: An Introduction to Early Madhyamika. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press
  • Jones, Richard H. (2014), Nagarjuna: Buddhism's Most Important Philosopher, New York: Jackson Square Books
  • Jones, Richard H. (2012), Indian Madhyamaka Buddhist Philosophy After Nagarjuna, 2 vols., New York: Jackson Square Books
  • Narain, Harsh. The Mādhyamika mind. Motilal Banarsidass Publishers, 1997.
  • Newland, Guy (2008), Introduction to Emptiness: As Taught in Tsong-kha-pa's Great Treatise on the Stages of the Path, Boston: Snow Lion
  • Ruegg, David S. (1981), The Literature of the Madhyamaka School in India, Wiesbaden: Otto Harrassowitz
  • Westeroff, Jan. (2009), Nāgārjuna's Madhyamaka. A Philosophical Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press