Jump to content

Philosophy of science: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
remove References section - there are already Footnotes and Further reading (and External links) sections - the one reference listed was not sufficiently notable to be kept
→‎Further reading: first-pass cleanup removing non-English texts and least notable or relevant references, especially those which are either too broad or too narrow
Line 554: Line 554:
* Augros, Robert M., Stanciu, George N., ''The New Story of Science: mind and the universe'', Lake Bluff, Ill.: Regnery Gateway, c1984. ISBN 0-89526-833-7
* Augros, Robert M., Stanciu, George N., ''The New Story of Science: mind and the universe'', Lake Bluff, Ill.: Regnery Gateway, c1984. ISBN 0-89526-833-7
* Babich, Babette E. (1994) ''Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science'', Albany: State University of New York Press.
* Babich, Babette E. (1994) ''Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science'', Albany: State University of New York Press.
* Baudet, Jean C. (2005), ''Mathématique et vérité'', L'Harmattan, Paris.
* Baudet, Jean C. (2010), ''Curieuses histoires de la science. Quand les chercheurs se trompent'', Jourdan, Bruxelles.
* Ben-Ari, M. (2005) ''Just a theory: exploring the nature of science'', Prometheus Books, Amherst, N.Y.
* Ben-Ari, M. (2005) ''Just a theory: exploring the nature of science'', Prometheus Books, Amherst, N.Y.
* Bird, Alexander (1998) ''Philosophy of Science'', Routledge, London.
* Bird, Alexander (1998) ''Philosophy of Science'', Routledge, London.
Line 567: Line 565:
* [[Errol Harris|Harris, Errol E.]] (1965), ''The Foundations of Metaphysics in Science '', George Allen and Unwin, London, Reprinted by Routledge, London (2002).
* [[Errol Harris|Harris, Errol E.]] (1965), ''The Foundations of Metaphysics in Science '', George Allen and Unwin, London, Reprinted by Routledge, London (2002).
* Harris, Errol E. (1991), ''Cosmos and Anthropos'', Humanities Press, New Jersey.
* Harris, Errol E. (1991), ''Cosmos and Anthropos'', Humanities Press, New Jersey.
* [[Stephen Hawking|Hawking, Stephen]]. (2001), ''[[The Universe in a Nutshell]]'', Bantam Press. ISBN 0-553-80202-X
* [[Horace Romano Harré|Harré, R.]] (1972), ''The Philosophies of Science: An Introductory Survey'', Oxford University Press, London, UK.
* [[Horace Romano Harré|Harré, R.]] (1972), ''The Philosophies of Science: An Introductory Survey'', Oxford University Press, London, UK.
* Heelan, Patrick A. (1983), ''Space-Perception and the Philosophy of Science'', University of California Press, Berkeley, CA.
* Heelan, Patrick A. (1983), ''Space-Perception and the Philosophy of Science'', University of California Press, Berkeley, CA.
* Honderich, Ted (Ed.) (2005) The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. New York, NY.
* Kearney, R. (1994), ''Routledge History of Philosophy'', Routledge Press. See Vol. 8.
* Kearney, R. (1994), ''Routledge History of Philosophy'', Routledge Press. See Vol. 8.
* Klemke, E., et al. (eds., 1998), ''Introductory Readings in The Philosophy of Science'', Prometheus Books, Amherst, New York, NY.
* Klemke, E., et al. (eds., 1998), ''Introductory Readings in The Philosophy of Science'', Prometheus Books, Amherst, New York, NY.
* [[William Kneale|Kneale, William]], and [[Martha Kneale|Kneale, Martha]] (1962), ''The Development of Logic'', Oxford University Press, London, UK.
* Kuipers, T.A.F. (2001), ''Structures in Science, An Advanced Textbook in Neo-Classical Philosophy of Science'', Synthese Library, Springer-Verlag.
* Kuipers, T.A.F. (2001), ''Structures in Science, An Advanced Textbook in Neo-Classical Philosophy of Science'', Synthese Library, Springer-Verlag.
* [[James Ladyman|Ladyman, J.]] (2002), ''Understanding Philosophy of Science'', Routledge, London, UK.
* [[James Ladyman|Ladyman, J.]] (2002), ''Understanding Philosophy of Science'', Routledge, London, UK.
Line 583: Line 578:
* Papineau, D. (ed., 1997), ''The Philosophy of Science'', Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
* Papineau, D. (ed., 1997), ''The Philosophy of Science'', Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
* Papineau, David. 2005. ''Science, problems of the philosophy of.'' Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford.
* Papineau, David. 2005. ''Science, problems of the philosophy of.'' Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford.
* Piattelli-Palmarini, Massimo (ed., 1980), ''Language and Learning, The Debate between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky'', Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
* [[Michael Polanyi|Polanyi, Michael]] (1946). [http://books.google.com/books?id=6rqDqTn-bcoC&printsec=frontcover&source=gbs_summary_r&cad=0 ''Science, Faith, and Society'']. Oxford Univ. Press. ISBN 0-226-67290-5. Reprinted by the University of Chicago Press, 1964.
* [[Michael Polanyi|Polanyi, Michael]] (1946). [http://books.google.com/books?id=6rqDqTn-bcoC&printsec=frontcover&source=gbs_summary_r&cad=0 ''Science, Faith, and Society'']. Oxford Univ. Press. ISBN 0-226-67290-5. Reprinted by the University of Chicago Press, 1964.
* [[Alexander Rosenberg|Rosenberg, Alexander]], (2000), ''Philosophy of Science: A Contemporary Introduction'', Routledge, London, UK.
* [[Alexander Rosenberg|Rosenberg, Alexander]], (2000), ''Philosophy of Science: A Contemporary Introduction'', Routledge, London, UK.
* [[Dagobert D. Runes|Runes, D.D.]] (ed.), ''Dictionary of Philosophy'', Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ, 1962.
* Salmon, M.H., et al. (1999), ''Introduction to the Philosophy of Science: A Text By Members of the Department of the History and Philosophy of Science of the University of Pittsburgh'', Hacket Publishing Company, Indianapolis, IN.
* Salmon, M.H., et al. (1999), ''Introduction to the Philosophy of Science: A Text By Members of the Department of the History and Philosophy of Science of the University of Pittsburgh'', Hacket Publishing Company, Indianapolis, IN.
* Snyder, Paul (1977), ''Toward One Science: The Convergence of Traditions'', St Martin's Press.
* Snyder, Paul (1977), ''Toward One Science: The Convergence of Traditions'', St Martin's Press.
* Strevens, Michael (2011), [http://www.themontrealreview.com/2009/Depth-an-account-of-scientific-explanation-Michael-Strevens.php ''Depth: An Account of Scientific Explanation''], Harvard University Press. (reviewed in [http://www.themontrealreview.com/2009/Depth-an-account-of-scientific-explanation-Michael-Strevens.php The Montreal Review])
* Strevens, Michael (2011), [http://www.themontrealreview.com/2009/Depth-an-account-of-scientific-explanation-Michael-Strevens.php ''Depth: An Account of Scientific Explanation''], Harvard University Press. (reviewed in [http://www.themontrealreview.com/2009/Depth-an-account-of-scientific-explanation-Michael-Strevens.php The Montreal Review])
* van Fraassen, Bas C. (1980), ''The Scientific Image'', Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
* van Fraassen, Bas C. (1980), ''The Scientific Image'', Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
* van Fraassen, Bas C. (2008), ''Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective'', Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
* van Luik, James, ''The Energy of Ideas'', Crow Hill Press, Cambridge, MA. 2000
* van Luik, James, ''The Energy of Ideas'', Crow Hill Press, Cambridge, MA. 2000
* [[Benjamin Walker (author)|Walker, Benjamin]], ''Caesar's Church: The Irrational in Science & Philosophy,'' Book Guild, Lewes, Sussex, 2001, ISBN 1-85776-625-3
* [[Benjamin Walker (author)|Walker, Benjamin]], ''Caesar's Church: The Irrational in Science & Philosophy,'' Book Guild, Lewes, Sussex, 2001, ISBN 1-85776-625-3

Revision as of 15:00, 12 February 2014

The philosophy of science is concerned with the assumptions, foundations, methods, and implications of science and with the use and merit of science. This discipline sometimes overlaps metaphysics, ontology and epistemology, for example, when it explores whether scientific results comprise a study of truth. In addition to these central problems of science as a whole, many philosophers of science consider problems that apply to particular sciences (e.g. philosophy of biology or philosophy of physics). Some philosophers of science also use contemporary results in science to reach conclusions about philosophy.

Philosophy of science has historically been met with mixed response from the scientific community. Though scientists often contribute to the field, many prominent scientists have felt that the practical effect on their work is limited.

Demarcation

The demarcation problem refers to the distinction between science and nonscience (including pseudoscience); Karl Popper called this the central question in the philosophy of science.[1] However, no unified account of the problem has won acceptance among philosophers, and some regard the problem as unsolvable or uninteresting.[2]

Early attempts by the logical positivists grounded science in observation while non-science was non-observational and hence meaningless.[3] Popper argued that the central property of science is falsifiability (i.e., all scientific claims can be proven false, at least in principle, and if no such proof can be found despite sufficient effort then the claim is likely true).[4]

Scientific realism and instrumentalism

Two central questions about science are (1) what are the aims of science and (2) how should one interpret the results of science? Scientific realists claim that science aims at truth and that one ought to regard scientific theories as true, approximately true, or likely true. Conversely, a scientific antirealist or instrumentalist argues that science does not aim (or at least does not succeed) at truth, and that it is a mistake to regard scientific theories as even potentially true.[5] Some antirealists claim that scientific theories aim at being instrumentally useful and should only be regarded as useful, but not true, descriptions of the world.[6]

Realists often point to the success of recent scientific theories as evidence for the truth (or near truth) of our current theories.[7][8][9][10][11] Antirealists point to either the history of science,[12][13] epistemic morals,[6] the success of false modeling assumptions,[14] or widely termed postmodern criticisms of objectivity as evidence against scientific realisms.[15] Some antirealists attempt to explain the success of scientific theories without reference to truth.[6][16]

Scientific explanation

In addition to providing predictions about future events, society often takes scientific theories to offer explanations for events that occur regularly or have already occurred. Philosophers have investigated the criteria by which a scientific theory can be said to have successfully explained a phenomenon, as well as what gives a scientific theory explanatory power. One early and influential theory of scientific explanation was put forward by Carl G. Hempel and Paul Oppenheim in 1948. Their Deductive-Nomological (D-N) model of explanation says that a scientific explanation succeeds by subsuming a phenomenon under a minor law. An explanation, then, is a valid deductive argument. For empiricists like Hempel and other logical positivists, this provided a way of understanding explanation without appeal to causation.[17] Although ignored for a decade, this view was subjected to substantial criticism, resulting in several widely believed counter examples to the theory.[18]

In addition to their D-N model, Hempel and Oppenheim offered other statistical models of explanation which would account for statistical sciences.[17] These theories have received criticism as well.[18] Salmon attempted to provide an alternative account for some of the problems with Hempel and Oppenheim's model by developing his statistical relevance model.[19][20] In addition to Salmon's model, others have suggested that explanation is primarily motivated by unifying disparate phenomena or primarily motivated by providing the causal or mechanical histories leading up to the phenomenon (or phenomena of that type).[20]

Analysis and reductionism

Analysis is the activity of breaking an observation or theory down into simpler concepts in order to understand it. Analysis is as essential to science as it is to all rational activities. For example, the task of describing mathematically the motion of a projectile is made easier by separating out the force of gravity, angle of projection and initial velocity. After such analysis it is possible to formulate a suitable theory of motion.

Reductionism can refer to one of several philosophical positions related to this approach. One type of reductionism is the belief that all fields of study are ultimately amenable to scientific explanation. Perhaps a historical event might be explained in sociological and psychological terms, which in turn might be described in terms of human physiology, which in turn might be described in terms of chemistry and physics.

Daniel Dennett invented the term greedy reductionism to describe the assumption that such reductionism was possible. He claims that it is just 'bad science', seeking to find explanations which are appealing or eloquent, rather than those that are of use in predicting natural phenomena. He also says that:

There is no such thing as philosophy-free science; there is only science whose philosophical baggage is taken on board without examination.—Daniel Dennett, Darwin's Dangerous Idea, 1995.

Grounds of validity of scientific reasoning

Empirical verification

Science relies on evidence to validate its theories and models, and the predictions implied by those theories and models should be in agreement with observation. Ultimately, observations reduce to those made by the unaided human senses: sight, hearing, etc. To be accepted by most scientists, several impartial, competent observers should agree on what is observed. Observations should be repeatable, e.g., experiments that generate relevant observations can be (and, if important, usually will be) done again. Furthermore, predictions should be specific; one should be able to describe a possible observation that would falsify the theory or a model that implies the prediction.

Nevertheless, while the basic concept of empirical verification is simple, in practice, there are difficulties as described in the following sections.

Induction

Philosophers of science have asked how the laws of science, such as Newton's Third Law, can be justified? After all, it is not possible to have tested every possible instance in which a scientific law applies. In the case of Newton's Third Law, there have been many tests, and in each one a corresponding reaction has been found, but can one ever be sure that future tests will continue to support Newton's Third Law? One approach to justifying scientific laws and more generally inferring generalizations from instances is to use induction. Using inductive reasoning, one reasons that if a situation holds in all observed cases, then the situation holds in all cases. Thus, by induction scientific laws and generalizations are inferred by observing a finite number of observations that conform to the law or generalization.

Explaining why people think induction produces knowledge has proven problematic. One cannot use deduction, the usual process of moving logically from premise to conclusion, because there is no syllogism that allows this. Indeed, induction is sometimes mistaken; 17th century biologists observed many white swans and none of other colours, but not all swans are white. Similarly, it is at least conceivable that an observation will be made tomorrow that shows an occasion in which an action is not accompanied by a reaction; the same is true of any scientific statement.

One answer has been to conceive of a different form of rational argument, one that does not rely on deduction. Deduction allows one to formulate a specific truth from a general truth: all crows are black; this is a crow; therefore this is black. Induction somehow allows one to formulate a general truth from some series of specific observations: this is a crow and it is black; that is a crow and it is black; no crow has been seen that is not black; therefore all crows are black.

The problem of induction is one of considerable debate and importance in the philosophy of science: is induction indeed justified, and if so, how?

Duhem-Quine thesis

According to the Duhem-Quine thesis, after Pierre Duhem and Willard Van Orman Quine, it is impossible to test a theory in isolation. One must always add auxiliary hypotheses in order to make testable predictions. For example, to test Newton's Law of Gravitation in our solar system, one needs information about the masses and positions of the Sun and all the planets. Famously, the failure to predict the orbit of Uranus in the 19th century led not to the rejection of Newton's Law but rather to the rejection of the hypothesis that there are only seven planets in our solar system. The investigations that followed led to the discovery of an eighth planet, Neptune. If a test fails, something is wrong. But there is a problem in figuring out what that something is: a missing planet, badly calibrated test equipment, an unsuspected curvature of space, etc.

One consequence of the Duhem-Quine thesis is that any theory can be made compatible with any empirical observation by the addition of a sufficient number of suitable ad hoc hypotheses. This is why science uses Occam's Razor; hypotheses without sufficient justification are eliminated.

This thesis was accepted by Karl Popper, leading him to reject naïve falsification, in favor of 'survival of the fittest', or most falsifiable, of scientific theories. According to Popper, any hypothesis that does not make testable predictions is simply not science. Such a hypothesis may be useful or valuable, but it cannot be called science. Confirmation holism, developed by Quine, states that empirical data are not sufficient to make a judgment between theories. In this view, a theory can always be made to fit with the available empirical data. However, the fact that empirical evidence does not serve to determine between alternative theories does not necessarily imply that all theories are of equal value, as scientists often use guiding principles such as Occam's Razor.

One result of this view is that specialists in the philosophy of science stress the requirement that observations made for the purposes of science be restricted to intersubjective objects. That is, science is restricted to those areas where there is general agreement on the nature of the observations involved. It is comparatively easy to agree on observations of physical phenomena, harder to agree on observations of social or mental phenomena, and difficult in the extreme to reach agreement on matters of theology or ethics (and thus the latter remain outside the normal purview of science).

Axiomatic assumptions

Whitehead wrote, "All science must start with some assumptions as to the ultimate analysis of the facts with which it deals. These assumptions are justified partly by their adherence to the types of occurrence of which we are directly conscious, and partly by their success in representing the observed facts with a certain generality, devoid of ad hoc suppositions."[21]

In Time's Arrow, Time's Cycle, Gould discussed two assumptions - the constancy of nature's laws and the operation of known processes - which he gave as examples for a scientist to assume before proceeding to do geology.[22] The axiom of uniformity of law, an unprovable postulate, is necessary in order for scientists to extrapolate inductive inference into the unobservable past. The constancy of natural laws must be assumed in order to study the past, else we cannot meaningfully study it.[23]

Theory-dependence of observations

When making observations, scientists look through telescopes, study images on electronic screens, record meter readings, and so on. Generally, on a basic level, they can agree on what they see, e.g., the thermometer shows 37.9 degrees C. But, if these scientists have different ideas about the theories that have been developed to explain these basic observations, they can interpret them in different ways. Ancient scientists interpreted the rising of the Sun in the morning as evidence that the Sun moved. Later scientists deduced that the Earth is rotating. For example, if some scientists may conclude that certain observations confirm a specific hypothesis, skeptical colleagues may suspect that something is wrong with the test equipment. Observations when interpreted by a scientist's theories are said to be theory-laden.

Observation involves both perception as well as cognition. That is, one does not make an observation passively, but is also actively engaged in distinguishing the phenomenon being observed from surrounding sensory data. Therefore, observations are affected by our underlying understanding of the way in which the world functions, and that understanding may influence what is perceived, noticed, or deemed worthy of consideration. More importantly, most scientific observation must be done within a theoretical context in order to be useful. For example, when one observes a measured increase in temperature with a thermometer, that observation is based on assumptions about the nature of temperature and its measurement, as well as assumptions about how the thermometer functions. Such assumptions are necessary in order to obtain scientifically useful observations (such as, "the temperature increased by two degrees").

Empirical observation is used to determine the acceptability of hypotheses within a theory. Justification of a hypothesis often includes reference to a theory – operational definitions and hypotheses – in which the observation is embedded. That is, the observation is framed in terms of the theory that also contains the hypothesis it is meant to verify or falsify (though of course the observation should not be based on an assumption of the truth or falsity of the hypothesis being tested). This means that the observation cannot serve as an entirely neutral arbiter between competing hypotheses, but can only arbitrate between hypotheses within the context of the underlying theory that explains the observation.

Thomas Kuhn denied that it is ever possible to isolate the hypothesis being tested from the influence of the theory in which the observations are grounded. He argued that observations always rely on a specific paradigm, and that it is not possible to evaluate competing paradigms independently. By "paradigm" he meant, essentially, a logically consistent "portrait" of the world, one that involves no logical contradictions and that is consistent with observations that are made from the point of view of this paradigm. More than one such logically consistent construct can paint a usable likeness of the world, but there is no common ground from which to pit two against each other, theory against theory. Neither is a standard by which the other can be judged. Instead, the question is which "portrait" is judged by some set of people to promise the most useful in terms of scientific "puzzle solving".

For Kuhn, the choice of paradigm was sustained by, but not ultimately determined by, logical processes. The individual's choice between paradigms involves setting two or more "portraits" against the world and deciding which likeness is most promising. In the case of a general acceptance of one paradigm or another, Kuhn believed that it represented the consensus of the community of scientists. Acceptance or rejection of some paradigm is, he argued, a social process as much as a logical process. Kuhn's position, however, is not one of relativism.[24] According to Kuhn, a paradigm shift will occur when a significant number of observational anomalies in the old paradigm have made the new paradigm more useful. That is, the choice of a new paradigm is based on observations, even though those observations are made against the background of the old paradigm. A new paradigm is chosen because it does a better job of solving scientific problems than the old one.

The fact that observation is embedded in theory does not mean observations are irrelevant to science. Scientific understanding derives from observation, but the acceptance of scientific statements is dependent on the related theoretical background or paradigm as well as on observation. Coherentism, skepticism, and foundationalism are alternatives for dealing with the difficulty of grounding scientific theories in something more than observations. And, of course, further, redesigned testing may resolve differences of opinion.

Coherentism

Induction must avoid the problem of the criterion, in which any justification must in turn be justified, resulting in an infinite regress. The regress argument has been used to justify one way out of the infinite regress, foundationalism. Foundationalism claims that there are some basic statements that do not require justification. Both induction and falsification are forms of foundationalism in that they rely on basic statements that derive directly from immediate sensory experience.

The way in which basic statements are derived from observation complicates the problem. Observation is a cognitive act; that is, it relies on our existing understanding, our set of beliefs. An observation of a transit of Venus requires a huge range of auxiliary beliefs, such as those that describe the optics of telescopes, the mechanics of the telescope mount, and an understanding of celestial mechanics, all of which must be justified separately. At first sight, the observation does not appear to be 'basic'.

Coherentism, on the other hand, asserts that statements can be justified by their being a part of a coherent system. In the case of science, the system is usually taken to be the complete set of beliefs of an individual scientist or, more broadly, of the community of scientists. Quine argued for a Coherentist approach to science, as do E O Wilson and Kenneth Craik, though neither use the term "Coherentism" to describe their views. An observation of a transit of Venus is justified by its being coherent with our beliefs about celestial mechanics and earlier observations. Where this observation is at odds with any auxiliary belief, an adjustment in the system will be required to remove the contradiction.

Ockham's razor

The practice of scientific inquiry typically involves a number of heuristic principles, such as the principles of conceptual economy or theoretical parsimony. These are customarily placed under the rubric of Ockham's razor, named after the 14th century Franciscan friar William of Ockham, who is credited with many different expressions of the maxim, not all of which have yet been found among his extant works.[25]

William of Ockham (c. 1295–1349) ... is remembered as an influential nominalist, but his popular fame as a great logician rests chiefly on the maxim known as Ockham's razor: Entia non sunt multiplicanda praeter necessitatem ["entities must not be multiplied beyond necessity]. No doubt this represents correctly the general tendency of his philosophy, but it has not so far been found in any of his writings. His nearest pronouncement seems to be Numquam ponenda est pluralitas sine necessitate [Plurality must never be posited without necessity], which occurs in his theological work on the Sentences of Peter Lombard (Super Quattuor Libros Sententiarum (ed. Lugd., 1495), i, dist. 27, qu. 2, K). In his Summa Totius Logicae, i. 12, Ockham cites the principle of economy, Frustra fit per plura quod potest fieri per pauciora [It is futile to do with more things that which can be done with fewer]. (Kneale and Kneale, 1962, p. 243)

As interpreted in contemporary scientific practice, "entities should not be multiplied beyond necessity" advises opting for the simplest theory among a set of competing theories that have a comparable explanatory power, discarding assumptions that do not improve the explanation. Among the many difficulties that arise in trying to apply Ockham's razor is the problem of formalizing and quantifying the "measure of simplicity" that is implied by the task of deciding which of several theories is the simplest. Although various measures of simplicity have been brought forward as potential candidates, it is generally accepted that there is no such thing as a theory-independent measure of simplicity. In other words, there appear to be as many different measures of simplicity as there are theories themselves, and the task of choosing between measures of simplicity appears to be every bit as problematic as the job of choosing between theories. Moreover, it is extremely difficult to identify the hypotheses or theories that have "comparable explanatory power", though it may be readily possible to rule out some of the extremes. Ockham's razor also does not say that the simplest account is to be preferred regardless of its capacity to explain outliers, exceptions, or other phenomena in question. The principle of falsifiability requires that any exception that can be reliably reproduced should invalidate the simplest theory, and that the next-simplest account which can actually incorporate the exception as part of the theory should then be preferred to the first. As Albert Einstein puts it, "The supreme goal of all theory is to make the irreducible basic elements as simple and as few as possible without having to surrender the adequate representation of a single datum of experience".[26]

Objectivity of observations in science

It is vitally important for science that the information about the surrounding world and the objects of study be as accurate and as reliable as possible. For the sake of this, measurements which are the source of this information must be as objective as possible. Before the invention of measuring tools (like weights, meter sticks, clocks, etc.) the only source of information available to humans were their senses (vision, hearing, taste, tactile, sense of heat, sense of gravity, etc.). Because human senses differ from person to person (due to wide variations in personal chemistry, deficiencies, inherited flaws, etc.) there were no objective measurements before the invention of these tools. The consequence of this was the lack of a rigorous science.

With the advent of exchange of goods, trades, and agricultures there arose a need for such measurements, and science (arithmetic, geometry, mechanics, etc.) based on standardized units of measurements (stadia, pounds, seconds, etc.) was born. To further abstract from unreliable human senses and make measurements more objective, science uses measuring devices (like spectrometers, voltmeters, interferometers, thermocouples, counters, etc.) and lately — computers. In most cases, the less human involvement in the measuring process, the more accurate and reliable scientific data are. Currently most measurements are done by a variety of mechanical and electronic sensors directly linked to computers—which further reduces the chance of human error/contamination of information. The current accuracy of measurement of mass is about 10−10, of angles—about 10−9, and of time and length intervals in many cases reaches the order of 10−13 - 10−15.[citation needed] This has made it possible to measure, say, the distance to the Moon with sub-centimeter accuracy (see Lunar laser ranging experiment), to measure slight movement of tectonic plates using GPS with sub-millimeter accuracy, or even to measure as slight variations in the distance between two mirrors separated by several kilometers as 10−18 m—three orders of magnitude less than the size of a single atomic nucleus—see LIGO.

Another question about the objectivity of observations relates to the so-called "experimenter's regress", as well as to other problems identified from the sociology of scientific knowledge: as with all forms of human reasoning, the people who interpret the observations or experiments always have cognitive and social biases that lead them, often in an unconscious way, to introduce their own interpretations into their description of what they are 'seeing'. Some of these arguments can be shown to be of a limited scope, when examined from a game-theoretic point of view. (See also "Rhetoric of Science").

Philosophy of particular sciences

In addition to addressing the general questions regarding science and induction, many philosophers of science are occupied by investigating philosophical or foundational problems in particular sciences. The late 20th and early 21st century has seen a rise in the number of practitioners of philosophy of a particular science.

Philosophy of biology

Philosophy of biology deals with epistemological, metaphysical, and ethical issues in the biological and biomedical sciences. Although philosophers of science and philosophers generally have long been interested in biology (e.g., Aristotle, Descartes, Leibniz and even Kant), philosophy of biology only emerged as an independent field of philosophy in the 1960s and 1970s.[27] Philosophers of science began to pay increasing attention to developments in biology, from the rise of the Modern synthesis in the 1930s and 1940s to the discovery of the structure of Deoxyribonucleic acid (DNA) in 1953 to more recent advances in genetic engineering. Other key ideas such as the reduction of all life processes to biochemical reactions as well as the incorporation of psychology into a broader neuroscience are also addressed. Research in current philosophy of biology is dominated[original research?][peacock prose] by investigations about the foundations of evolutionary theory.[28]

Philosophy of chemistry

Philosophy of chemistry considers the methodology and underlying assumptions of the science of chemistry. It is explored by philosophers, chemists, and philosopher-chemist teams.

Topics of interest include:

  1. The relationship between chemical concepts and reality. Resonance structures are often used in chemical explanations despite their decided non-reality. In a similar sense, the reality of concepts such as nucleophiles and electrophiles has been questioned.
  2. Questions regarding whether chemistry studies atoms (substances) or reactions (processes).
  3. Symmetry in chemistry, specifically the origin of homochirality in biological molecules
  4. Reductionism with respect to physics and questions regarding whether quantum mechanics can fully explain all chemical phenomena.

Philosophy of physics

Philosophy of physics is the study of the fundamental, philosophical questions underlying modern physics, the study of matter and energy and how they interact. The main questions concern the nature of space and time, atoms and atomism. Also included are the predictions of cosmology, the results of the interpretation of quantum mechanics, the foundations of statistical mechanics, causality, determinism, and the nature of physical laws. Classically, several of these questions were studied as part of metaphysics (for example, those about causality, determinism, and space and time).

Philosophy of psychology

Philosophy of psychology refers to issues at the theoretical foundations of modern psychology. Some of these issues are epistemological concerns about the methodology of psychological investigation. For example:

  • What is the most appropriate methodology for psychology: mentalism, behaviorism, or a compromise?
  • Are self-reports a reliable data gathering method?
  • What conclusions can be drawn from null hypothesis tests?
  • Can first-person experiences (emotions, desires, beliefs, etc.) be measured objectively?

Other issues in philosophy of psychology are philosophical questions about the nature of mind, brain, and cognition, and are perhaps more commonly thought of as part of cognitive science, or philosophy of mind, such as:

Philosophy of psychology also closely monitors contemporary work conducted in cognitive neuroscience, evolutionary psychology, and artificial intelligence, questioning what they can and cannot explain in psychology.

Philosophy of psychology is a relatively young field, because psychology only became a discipline of its own in the late 1800s. Philosophy of mind, by contrast, has been a well-established discipline since before psychology was a field of study at all. It is concerned with questions about the very nature of mind, the qualities of experience, and particular issues like the debate between dualism and monism.

Also, neurophilosophy has become its own field with the works of Paul Churchland and Patricia Churchland.

Philosophy of economics

Philosophy of economics is the branch of philosophy which studies philosophical issues relating to economics. It can also be defined as the branch of economics which studies its own foundations and morality.

Philosophy of mathematics

Philosophy of mathematics is the branch of philosophy that studies the philosophical assumptions, foundations, and implications of mathematics.

Recurrent themes include:

  • What are the sources of mathematical subject matter?
  • What is the ontological status of mathematical entities?
  • What does it mean to refer to a mathematical object?
  • What is the character of a mathematical proposition?
  • What is the relation between logic and mathematics?
  • What is the role of hermeneutics in mathematics?
  • What kinds of inquiry play a role in mathematics?
  • What are the objectives of mathematical inquiry?
  • What gives mathematics its hold on experience?
  • What are the human traits behind mathematics?
  • What is mathematical beauty?
  • What is the source and nature of mathematical truth?
  • What is the relationship between the abstract world of mathematics and the material universe?
  • What is a number?
  • Are mathematical proofs exercises in tautology?
  • Why does it make sense to ask whether "1+1=2" is true?
  • How do we know whether a mathematical proof is correct?

Philosophy of medicine

Beyond medical ethics and bioethics, The philosophy of medicine is a branch of philosophy that includes the epistemology, ontology/metaphysics, and ethics of medicine. Within the epistemology of medicine, Evidence-based medicine (EBM) (or Evidence Based Practice (EBP)) has attracted attention, mostly notably the special place that is given to randomisation,[29][30][31] blinding or masking and placebo controls have received great deal of recent attention. Related to these areas of investigation, ontologies of specific interest to the philosophy of medicine include Cartesian dualism, the monogenenic conception of disease[32] and the conceptualization of ‘placebos’ and ‘placebo effects’.[33][34][35][36] There is also a growing interest in the metaphysics of medicine,[37] particularly the idea of causation. Philosophers of medicine might not only be interested in how medical knowledge is generated, but also in the nature of such phenomena. Causation is of interest because the purpose of much medical research is to establish causal relationships, e.g. what causes disease, or what causes people to get better.[38]

Positivism and social science

The French philosopher, Auguste Comte (1798–1857), established the epistemological perspective of positivism in The Course in Positivist Philosophy, a series of texts published between 1830 and 1842. These texts were followed by the 1844 work, A General View of Positivism (published in English in 1865). The first three volumes of the Course dealt chiefly with the physical sciences already in existence (mathematics, astronomy, physics, chemistry, biology), whereas the latter two emphasised the inevitable coming of social science: "sociologie". Observing the circular dependence of theory and observation in science, and classifying the sciences in this way, Comte may be regarded as the first philosopher of science in the modern sense of the term.[39] For him, the physical sciences had necessarily to arrive first, before humanity could adequately channel its efforts into the most challenging and complex "Queen science" of human society itself. Comte offers an evolutionary system proposing that society undergoes three phases in its quest for the truth according to a general 'law of three stages'. These are (1) the theological, (2) the metaphysical, and (3) the positive.[40]

Comte's positivism established the initial philosophical foundations for formal sociology and social research. Durkheim, Marx, and Weber are more typically cited as the fathers of contemporary social science. In psychology, a positivistic approach has historically been favoured in behaviourism. In the early 20th century, logical positivism—a stricter version of Comte's basic thesis but a broadly independent movement— sprang up in Vienna and grew to become one of the dominant movements in Anglo-American philosophy and the analytic tradition. Logical positivists (or 'neopositivists') reject metaphysical assertions and attempt to reduce statements and propositions to pure logic.

The positivist perspective, however, has been associated with 'scientism'; the view that the methods of the natural sciences may be applied to all areas of investigation, be it philosophical, social scientific, or otherwise. Among most social scientists and historians, orthodox positivism has long since lost popular support. Today, practitioners of both social and physical sciences instead take into account the distorting effect of observer bias and structural limitations. This scepticism has been facilitated by a general weakening of deductivist accounts of science by philosophers such as Thomas Kuhn, and new philosophical movements such as critical realism and neopragmatism. Positivism has also been espoused by 'technocrats' who believe in the inevitability of social progress through science and technology.[41] The philosopher-sociologist Jürgen Habermas has critiqued pure instrumental rationality as meaning that scientific-thinking becomes something akin to ideology itself.[42]

Social accountability

Scientific openness

A very broad issue affecting the neutrality of science concerns the areas over which science chooses to explore, so what part of the world and man is studied by science.

Philip Kitcher in his "Science, Truth, and Democracy"[43] argues that scientific studies that attempt to show one segment of the population as being less intelligent, successful or emotionally backward compared to others have a political feedback effect which further excludes such groups from access to science. Thus such studies undermine the broad consensus required for good science by excluding certain people, and so proving themselves in the end to be unscientific.

Critiques of scientific method

Paul Feyerabend argued that no description of scientific method could possibly be broad enough to encompass all the approaches and methods used by scientists. Feyerabend objected to prescriptive scientific method on the grounds that any such method would stifle and cramp scientific progress. Feyerabend claimed, "the only principle that does not inhibit progress is: anything goes."[44]

Sociology, anthropology and economics of science

In his book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Kuhn argues that the process of observation and evaluation take place within a paradigm. 'A paradigm is what the members of a community of scientists share, and, conversely, a scientific community consists of men who share a paradigm'.[45] On this account, science can be done only as a part of a community, and is inherently a communal activity.

For Kuhn, the fundamental difference between science and other disciplines is in the way in which the communities function. Others, especially Feyerabend and some post-modernist thinkers, have argued that there is insufficient difference between social practices in science and other disciplines to maintain this distinction. It is apparent that social factors play an important and direct role in scientific method, but that they do not serve to differentiate science from other disciplines. Furthermore, although on this account science is socially constructed, it does not follow that reality is a social construct. (See Science studies and the links there.) Kuhn's ideas are equally applicable to both realist and anti-realist ontologies.

There are, however, those who maintain that scientific reality is indeed a social construct, to quote Quine:

Physical objects are conceptually imported into the situation as convenient intermediaries not by definition in terms of experience, but simply as irreducible posits comparable, epistemologically, to the gods of Homer ... For my part I do, qua lay physicist, believe in physical objects and not in Homer's gods; and I consider it a scientific error to believe otherwise. But in point of epistemological footing, the physical objects and the gods differ only in degree and not in kind. Both sorts of entities enter our conceptions only as cultural posits[46]

A major development in recent decades has been the study of the formation, structure, and evolution of scientific communities by sociologists and anthropologists including David Bloor, Barry Barnes, Harry Collins, Michel Callon, Bruno Latour, John Law, Anselm Strauss, Lucy Suchman, and others. The field has come to be known as Science and Technology Studies. Here the approach to the philosophy of science is to study how scientific communities actually operate.

Concepts and methods from economic science (as rational choice, social choice or game theory) have also been applied for understanding the efficiency of scientific communities in the production of epistemic outputs. (Main entry 'Economics of scientific knowledge').

Continental philosophy of science

In the Continental philosophical tradition, science is viewed from a world-historical perspective. One of the first philosophers who supported this view was Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel. Philosophers such as Pierre Duhem and Gaston Bachelard also wrote their works with this world-historical approach to science. Nietzsche advanced the thesis in his "The Genealogy of Morals" that the motive for search of truth in sciences is a kind of ascetic ideal.

All of these approaches involve a historical and sociological turn to science, with a special emphasis on lived experience (a kind of Husserlian "life-world"), rather than a progress-based or anti-historical approach as done in the analytic tradition. This emphasis can be traced through Edmund Husserl's phenomenology, the late works of Merleau-Ponty (Nature: Course Notes from the Collège de France, 1956–1960), and Martin Heidegger's hermeneutics.

The largest effect on the continental tradition with respect to science was Martin Heidegger's critique of the theoretical attitude in general which of course includes the scientific attitude. For this reason the Continental tradition has remained much more skeptical of the importance of science in human life and philosophical inquiry.

Notwithstanding, there have been a number of important works: especially a Kuhnian precursor, Alexandre Koyré. Another important development was that of Foucault's analysis of the historical and scientific thought in The Order of Things and his study of power and corruption within the "science" of madness.

Several post-Heideggerian authors contributing to the Continental philosophy of science in the second half of the 20th century include Jürgen Habermas (e.g., "Truth and Justification", 1998), Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker ("The Unity of Nature", 1980), and Wolfgang Stegmüller ("Probleme und Resultate der Wissenschafttheorie und Analytischen Philosophie", 1973–1986).

See also

Philosophers of science

Subfields

See also

Footnotes

  1. ^ Thornton, Stephen (006). "Karl Popper". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2007-12-01. {{cite web}}: Check date values in: |year= (help)
  2. ^ Laudan, Larry (1983). "The Demise of the Demarcation Problem". In Adolf Grünbaum, Robert Sonné Cohen, Larry Laudan (ed.). Physics, Philosophy, and Psychoanalysis: Essays in Honor of Adolf Grünbaum. Springer. ISBN 90-277-1533-5.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: editors list (link)
  3. ^ Uebel, Thomas (2006). "Vienna Circle". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2007-12-01.
  4. ^ Popper, Karl (2004 reprint). The logic of scientific discovery. London & New York: Routledge Classics. ISBN 0-415-27844-9  First published 1959 by Hutchinson & Co. {{cite book}}: Check date values in: |year= (help)CS1 maint: postscript (link) CS1 maint: year (link)
  5. ^ Levin, Michael (1984). "What Kind of Explanation is Truth?". In Jarrett Leplin (ed.). Scientific Realism. Berkeley: University of California Press. pp. 124–1139. ISBN 0-520-05155-6.
  6. ^ a b c van Fraassen, Bas (1980). The Scientific Image. Oxford: The Clarendon Press. ISBN 0-19-824424-X.
  7. ^ Popper, Karl (2002). Conjectures and Refutations. London & New York: Routledge Classics. ISBN 0-415-28594-1  First published 1963 by Routledge and Kegan Paul{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: postscript (link)
  8. ^ Smart, J. J. C. (1968). Between Science and Philosophy. New York: Random House.
  9. ^ Putnam, Hilary (1975). Mathematics, Matter and Method (Philosophical Papers, Vol. I). London: Cambridge University Press.
  10. ^ Putnam, Hilary (1978). Meaning and the Moral Sciences. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
  11. ^ Boyd, Richard (1984). "The Current Status of Scientific Realism". In Jarrett Leplin (ed.). Scientific Realism. Berkeley: University of California Press. pp. 41–82. ISBN 0-520-05155-6.
  12. ^ Stanford, P. Kyle (2006). Exceeding Our Grasp: Science, History, and the Problem of Unconceived Alternatives. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-517408-3.
  13. ^ Laudan, Larry (1981). "A Confutation of Convergent Realism". Philosophy of Science. 48: 218–249. doi:10.1086/288975.
  14. ^ Winsberg, Eric (September 2006). "Models of Success Versus the Success of Models: Reliability without Truth". Synthese. 152: 1–19. doi:10.1007/s11229-004-5404-6.
  15. ^ Boyd, Richard (2002). "Scientific Realism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2007-12-01.
  16. ^ Stanford, P. Kyle (June 2000). "An Antirealist Explanation of the Success of Science". Philosophy of Science. 67 (2): 266–284. doi:10.1086/392775.
  17. ^ a b Hempel, Carl G. (1948). "Studies in the Logic of Explanation". Philosophy of Science. 15 (2): 135–175. doi:10.1086/286983. {{cite journal}}: Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help)
  18. ^ a b Salmon, Merrilee (1992). Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Prentice-Hall. ISBN 0-13-663345-5. {{cite book}}: Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help)
  19. ^ Salmon, Wesley (1971). Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
  20. ^ a b Woodward, James (2003). "Scientific Explanation". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2007-12-07.
  21. ^ Whitehead, A.N. (1997) [1920]. Science and the Modern World. Lowell Lectures. Free Press. p. 135. ISBN 978-0-684-83639-3. LCCN 67002244.
  22. ^ Gould, Stephen J (1987). Time's Arrow, Time's Cycle: Myth and Metaphor in the Discovery of Geological Time. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. p. 120. ISBN 0674891996. You cannot go to a rocky outcrop and observe either the constancy of nature's laws or the working of known processes. It works the other way around." You first assume these propositions and "then you go to the outcrop of rock.
  23. ^ Simpson 1963, pp. 24–48, "Uniformity is an unprovable postulate justified, or indeed required, on two grounds. First, nothing in our incomplete but extensive knowledge of history disagrees with it. Second, only with this postulate is a rational interpretation of history possible, and we are justified in seeking—as scientists we must seek—such a rational interpretation."
  24. ^ T. S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd. ed., Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Pr., 1970, p. 206. ISBN 0-226-45804-0
  25. ^ Ockham's razor, however, was not originally a principle of science but of theology and the issue of parsimony comes, not from science, but from the vow of poverty that was modeled on the life of Christ. However, the origins of the idea do not necessarily take away from its overall usefulness.
  26. ^ The Complete citation is as follows: "The basic concepts and laws which are not logically further reducible constitute the indispensable and not rationally deducible part of the theory. It can scarcely be denied that the supreme goal of all theory is to make the irreducible basic elements as simple and as few as possible without having to surrender the adequate representation of a single datum of experience". Albert Einstein. On the Method of Theoretical Physics. Philosophy of Science, Vol. 1, No. 2, (Apr., 1934), pp. 163-169 (see page 165). The University of Chicago Press
  27. ^ Hull D. (1969), What philosophy of biology is not, Journal of the History of Biology, 2, p. 241–268.
  28. ^ Recent examples include Okasha S. (2006), Evolution and the Levels of Selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press, and Godfrey-Smith P. (2009), Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  29. ^ Papineau, D., 1994. The Virtues of Randomization. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 45(2), pp.437 -450.
  30. ^ Jstor, Worrall, J., 2002. What Evidence in Evidence-Based Medicine? Philosophy of Science, 69(3), p.S316-S330.
  31. ^ Worrall, J., 2007. Why there’s no cause to randomize. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58, pp.451-488.
  32. ^ Lee, K., 2012. The Philosophical Foundations of Modern Medicine, London/New York, Palgrave/Macmillan.
  33. ^ Grünbaum, A., 1981. The Placebo Concept. Behavioural Research & Therapy, 19(2), pp.157-167.
  34. ^ Gøtzsche, P.C., 1994. Is there logic in the placebo? Lancet, 344(8927), pp.925-926.
  35. ^ Nunn, R., 2009. It’s time to put the placebo out of our misery. British Medical Journal, 338, b1568.
  36. ^ Springer Turner, A., 2012. “Placebos” and the logic of placebo comparison. Biology & Philosophy, 27(3), pp.419-432.
  37. ^ PubMed, Worrall, J., 2011. Causality in medicine: Getting back to the Hill top. Preventive Medicine, 53(4-5), pp.235-238.
  38. ^ Springer, Cartwright, N., 2009. What are randomised controlled trials good for? Philosophical Studies, 147(1), pp.59-70.
  39. ^ Stanford Encyclopaedia: Auguste Comte
  40. ^ Giddens, Positivism and Sociology, 1
  41. ^ Schunk, Learning Theories: An Educational Perspective, 5th, 315
  42. ^ Outhwaite, William, 1988 Habermas: Key Contemporary Thinkers, Polity Press (Second Edition 2009), ISBN 978-0-7456-4328-1 p.68
  43. ^ Kitcher, P. Science, Truth, and Democracy, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001
  44. ^ Paul Feyerabend, Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge (1975), ISBN 0-391-00381-X, ISBN 0-86091-222-1, ISBN 0-86091-481-X, ISBN 0-86091-646-4, ISBN 0-86091-934-X, ISBN 0-902308-91-2
  45. ^ Kuhn, T. S. (1970). "[Postscript]". The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd. ed. [Univ. of Chicago Pr]. ISBN 0-226-45804-0.
  46. ^ Quine, Willard Van Orman (1980). "Two Dogmas of Empiricism". From a Logical Point of View. Harvard University Press. ISBN 0-674-32351-3.

Further reading

  • Agassi, J., (1975), Science in Flux, Reidel, Dordrecht.
  • Agassi, J. and Jarvie, I. C. (1987), Rationality: The Critical View, Kluwer, Dordrecht.
  • Augros, Robert M., Stanciu, George N., The New Story of Science: mind and the universe, Lake Bluff, Ill.: Regnery Gateway, c1984. ISBN 0-89526-833-7
  • Babich, Babette E. (1994) Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science, Albany: State University of New York Press.
  • Ben-Ari, M. (2005) Just a theory: exploring the nature of science, Prometheus Books, Amherst, N.Y.
  • Bird, Alexander (1998) Philosophy of Science, Routledge, London.
  • Bovens, L. and Hartmann, S. (2003), Bayesian Epistemology, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
  • Boyd, R., Gasper, P., and Trout, J.D. (eds., 1991), The Philosophy of Science, Blackwell Publishers, Cambridge, MA.
  • Chalmers, Alan (2007) What Is This Thing Called Science?, University of Queensland Press, Open University press, (reprint of 1999 3rd revised edition).
  • Feyerabend, Paul K. 2005. Science, history of the philosophy of. Oxford Companion to Philosophy, Oxford.
  • Glazebrook, Trish (2000), Heidegger's Philosophy of Science, Fordham University Press.
  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2003) Theory and reality: an introduction to the philosophy of science, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London
  • Gutting, Gary (2004), Continental Philosophy of Science, Blackwell Publishers, Cambridge, MA.
  • Harris, Errol E. (1965), The Foundations of Metaphysics in Science , George Allen and Unwin, London, Reprinted by Routledge, London (2002).
  • Harris, Errol E. (1991), Cosmos and Anthropos, Humanities Press, New Jersey.
  • Harré, R. (1972), The Philosophies of Science: An Introductory Survey, Oxford University Press, London, UK.
  • Heelan, Patrick A. (1983), Space-Perception and the Philosophy of Science, University of California Press, Berkeley, CA.
  • Kearney, R. (1994), Routledge History of Philosophy, Routledge Press. See Vol. 8.
  • Klemke, E., et al. (eds., 1998), Introductory Readings in The Philosophy of Science, Prometheus Books, Amherst, New York, NY.
  • Kuipers, T.A.F. (2001), Structures in Science, An Advanced Textbook in Neo-Classical Philosophy of Science, Synthese Library, Springer-Verlag.
  • Ladyman, J. (2002), Understanding Philosophy of Science, Routledge, London, UK.
  • Losee, J. (1998), A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
  • Newton-Smith, W.H. (ed., 2001), A Companion to the Philosophy of Science, Blackwell Publishers, Malden, MA.
  • Niiniluoto, I. (2002), Critical Scientific Realism, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
  • Okasha, Samir (), "Philosophy of science: A very short introduction", Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
  • Pap, A. (1962), An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, The Free Press, New York, NY.
  • Papineau, D. (ed., 1997), The Philosophy of Science, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
  • Papineau, David. 2005. Science, problems of the philosophy of. Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford.
  • Polanyi, Michael (1946). Science, Faith, and Society. Oxford Univ. Press. ISBN 0-226-67290-5. Reprinted by the University of Chicago Press, 1964.
  • Rosenberg, Alexander, (2000), Philosophy of Science: A Contemporary Introduction, Routledge, London, UK.
  • Salmon, M.H., et al. (1999), Introduction to the Philosophy of Science: A Text By Members of the Department of the History and Philosophy of Science of the University of Pittsburgh, Hacket Publishing Company, Indianapolis, IN.
  • Snyder, Paul (1977), Toward One Science: The Convergence of Traditions, St Martin's Press.
  • Strevens, Michael (2011), Depth: An Account of Scientific Explanation, Harvard University Press. (reviewed in The Montreal Review)
  • van Fraassen, Bas C. (1980), The Scientific Image, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
  • van Luik, James, The Energy of Ideas, Crow Hill Press, Cambridge, MA. 2000
  • Walker, Benjamin, Caesar's Church: The Irrational in Science & Philosophy, Book Guild, Lewes, Sussex, 2001, ISBN 1-85776-625-3
  • Ziman, John (2000). Real Science: what it is, and what it means. Cambridge, Uk: Cambridge University Press.